introduction to one-hundred years of the federal income tax
October 30, 2017 | Author: Anonymous | Category: N/A
Short Description
in conferences at the USC .. Aaron Director and Allen Wallis also testified to Simons' influence. Kahn, Jeffrey ......
Description
INTRODUCTION TO ONE-HUNDRED YEARS OF THE FEDERAL INCOME TAX JOSEPH M. DODGE *, STEVE R. JOHNSON ** & JEFFREY H. KAHN *** Income taxation in the United States got off to a less than auspicious start. 1 A few American colonies experimented with taxes that crudely attempted to reach certain income from business and professional activities during the 17th and 18th centuries. 2 Secretary of the Treasury Alexander Dallas urged adoption of an income tax during the War of 1812, but that conflict ended before action was taken on his proposal. 3 Both sides adopted income taxes during the American Civil War.4 The victorious North repealed its tax shortly after the war ended. 5 About a decade after the tax had been repealed, the Supreme Court upheld the constitutionality of the tax in the Springer case. 6 In 1894, a federal income tax system was again enacted. Especially compared to what we have now, that tax was a model of simplicity. As applied to individual taxpayers, it imposed a flat rate of two percent on any income over $4000. 7 A year later, in the famous (or infamous) Pollock decisions, the Supreme Court, effectively overruling Springer, struck down the federal income tax as unconstitutional. 8 In 1909, Congress proposed a constitutional amendment to overturn Pollock. This amendment was ratified on February 25, 1913 as * Stearns Weaver Miller Weissler Alhadeff & Sitterson Professor, Florida State University College of Law. ** University Professor, Florida State University College of Law. *** Charles W. Ehrhardt Professor & Associate Dean for Academic Affairs, Florida State University College of Law. 1. For discussion of the early history of taxation in the United States, see JOSEPH M. DODGE, J. CLIFTON FLEMING, JR. & ROBERT J. PERONI, FEDERAL INCOME TAX: DOCTRINE, STRUCTURE, AND POLICY 3-11 (4th ed. 2012). 2. See generally ROBIN L. EINHORN, AMERICAN TAXATION, AMERICAN SLAVERY (2006) (discussing tax systems of the American colonies); see also HAROLD DUBROFF, THE UNITED STATES TAX COURT: AN HISTORICAL ANALYSIS 1-2 (1979). 3. DUBROFF, supra note 2, at 2. 4. E.g., Act of August 5, 1861, ch. 45, § 49, 12 Stat. 292, 309; Act of July 1, 1862, ch. 119, § 89, 12 Stat. 432, 473; Tax History Museum: 1861–1865: The Civil War, TAX ANALYSTS, http://www.taxhistory.org/www/website.nsf/Web/THM1861?OpenDocument (last visited Feb. 1, 2014) (describing Confederacy income tax). 5. Act of July 14, 1870, ch. 255, § 6, 16 Stat. 256, 257. 6. Springer v. United States, 102 U.S. 586 (1880) (holding that the Civil War income tax was not subject to the requirement, imposed by Article I, Section 2, Clause 3 of the U.S. Constitution, that a federal “direct tax” had to be apportioned among the states in proportion to population). 7. Act of August 27, 1894, ch. 349, § 27, 28 Stat. 509, 553. 8. Pollock v. Farmers’ Loan & Trust Co., 157 U.S. 429 (1895), aff’d on reh’g, 158 U.S. 601 (1895) (holding that the income tax, in taxing income from property, was a nonapportioned direct tax).
xi
the Sixteenth Amendment, which provides: “The Congress shall have power to lay and collect taxes on incomes, from whatever source derived, without apportionment among the several States, and without regard to any census or enumeration.” Shortly after the ratification of the Sixteenth Amendment, Congress enacted the Revenue Act of 1913 and, thus, the modern federal income tax was born.9 Few events have been more important in shaping contemporary American life than the creation and development of the income tax. “No other branch of the law touches human activities at so many points” as does income tax law. 10 Income tax considerations bear on marriage, children, home, work, and the numerous other activities, transactions, and decisions fundamental to life. Income tax planning is crucial to businesses large and small. The modern welfare-defenseregulatory state would be impossible without the enormous and predictable flows of revenues provided mainly by the income tax. Whether the effects of the federal income tax are desirable can be debated. The pervasiveness of these effects cannot be. Thus, whether as celebration or lamentation, the centennial of the modern federal income tax is an occasion to mark. To do so, we at Florida State hosted an array of distinguished experts who offered perspectives on what we have learned in the last 100 years and where we should (or will) go in the future. Joining us for the occasion, as principal presenters and as commentators, were Steven Bank, Joseph Bankman, David Gamage, James Hines, Jr., Douglas Kahn, Leandra Lederman, Gregg Polsky, Clarissa Potter, Chris Sanchirico, Daniel Shaviro, and Lawrence Zelenak. Although they need no introduction, their institutional affiliations are listed at the end of this Introduction. We convened on March 1 and 2, 2013. Eight original articles and essays examined historical developments, current features, and future possibilities as to the federal income tax. First, authors presented their work, then designated commentators offered their perspectives, then all conference participants participated in rich and freewheeling debate. The pieces appearing in this symposium issue were enriched by this stimulating discussion. Beginning this symposium issue, Professor Daniel Shaviro explores The Forgotten Henry Simons. Simons is a household name with tax scholars on account of his well-known definition of personal income as the “algebraic sum of (1) the market value of rights exercised in consumption and (2) the change in value of the store of property rights between the beginning and end of the period in ques9. Act of October 3, 1913, ch. 16, 38 Stat. 114. Previously, the federal government had enacted a corporate income tax. Act of August 5, 1909, ch. 6, § 38, 36 Stat. 11, 112. The Supreme Court upheld the corporate income tax as a uniform “indirect” tax in Flint v. Stone Tracy Co., 220 U.S. 107 (1911). 10. Dobson v. Commissioner, 320 U.S. 489, 494-95 (1943).
xii
tion.” 11 This definition of personal income, now referred to as the Haig-Simons definition, is still used as a standard and remains important in modern tax scholarship. Professor Shaviro explores the man behind the definition. He provides a brief overview of Simons’ “meteoric” career. The article then moves to a discussion of the seemingly contradictory nature of some of his opinions. Simons described himself as “severely libertarian.” He generally denounced government economic regulation and was the intellectual leader of the pro-free market law and economics movement at the University of Chicago Law School. Yet he also was a proponent of “drastic progression” in a broad-based income tax. Professor Shaviro explores these apparently contradictory views and attempts to explain why Simons may have held them. Finally, while acknowledging that Professor Simons favored an income tax system over a consumption tax system during his lifetime, Professor Shaviro attempts to discern what Professor Simons might think today on that issue. In When We Taxed the Pyramids, Professor Steven Bank explores the dividends received deduction. 12 This deduction allows a corporation to deduct from its income an amount equal to a certain percentage (or all) of the dividends that it receives from other domestic corporations. The article examines the historical development of the deduction to explain how we ended up with the current tax treatment of such dividends. Professor Bank focuses on the original purpose for taxing intercorporate dividends, which was to discourage the formation of corporate “pyramids” or groups of corporations controlled by one parent holding corporation. These structures were viewed as abusive and facilitated the concentration of too much wealth and power in a small group of owners. The article explores the political shift in attitude over time regarding the concern of multi-level corporate groups and the gradual acceptance of the pyramid structure. Professor Bank uses the fall and rise of the corporate consolidated return to illustrate this shift of opinion. This leads us to where we are today, with a dividends received deduction for corporations that does not appear to fulfill any policy rationale. Professor Bank concludes the article by proposing reforms that would better align the treatment of intercorporate dividends with the policy justification for allowing a deduction for such income. The individual income tax has increasingly grown more complex over its 100-year history. In Some Income Tax Simplification Proposals, Professor Joseph Dodge presents explanations of how complexity has come about, while offering reasons why simplification, 11. HENRY C. SIMONS, PERSONAL INCOME TAXATION: THE DEFINITION OF INCOME AS A PROBLEM OF FISCAL POLICY 50 (1938). 12. I.R.C. § 243.
xiii
especially for individual and small-business taxpayers, has merit. Professor Dodge then offers an array of simplification proposals, broken down into one list of proposals that do not entail significant reform from the policy perspective and a separate list of commonly mentioned reform proposals that would also advance the cause of simplification. The lists are not exhaustive; for example, simplification of capitalization doctrine and capital recovery methods (including depreciation) is not considered. Many simplification proposals made by Professor Dodge are aimed at low to moderate individual taxpayers. For example, the taxable income computation could be simplified by eliminating the different treatment of various categories of deductions. Low-income allowances could be simplified by eliminating the separate rate schedules for unmarried individuals and heads of household, plus collapsing the existing standard deduction, personal exemption, and dependency exemptions into a single subsistence deduction based on family size. Similarly, the earned income credit, the child credit, and the household and dependent care credit could be combined into a single dependent-care allowance for the working poor. Another type of simplification entails elimination of (1) subjective tests, (2) assorted factintensive inquiries, (3) meaningless distinctions, and (4) pointless computations. Along these lines, the definition of “dependent” could be simplified by eliminating “support” tests, the Duberstein definition of “gift” 13 could be replaced by the gift tax definition of gift, 14 depreciation (and basis adjustments) could be disallowed on business or investment use of personal residences, the distinction between tax alimony and child support could be abolished, and various borderline personal-business costs could be disallowed. Ranging further afield, Professor Dodge floats notions of cash accounting for small business (including avoidance of inventory accounting), portfolio accounting for publicly traded securities held by an individual, and simplification of the income tax rules involving gratuitous transfers, grantor trusts, and estates. Also considered are various reform proposals pertaining to capital gains, the personal deductions, and the horrendously complex system of taxing retirement income deferrals. In A Proposed Replacement of the Tax Expenditures Concept and a Different Perspective on Accelerated Depreciation, Professor Douglas Kahn revisits the debate on tax expenditure budgets, a concept that he has previously criticized. 15 The tax expenditure concept rests uneasily on the premise that there is an “ideal” income tax system and 13. See Commissioner v. Duberstein, 363 U.S. 278, 285-86 (1960) (defining gifts excludible from income taxation as transfers animated by the donor’s “detached and disinterested generosity” (quoting Commissioner v. LoBue, 351 U.S. 243, 246 (1956))). 14. See I.R.C. § 2512(b) (defining gifts by reference to the extent by which the value of the transferred property exceeds consideration rendered for the transfer). 15. Douglas A. Kahn & Jeffrey S. Lehman, Tax Expenditure Budgets: A Critical View, 54 TAX NOTES 1661 (1992).
xiv
that any departures from that ideal system should be scrutinized to see if they are justified. In this essay, Professor Kahn contends that a major flaw in the tax expenditure concept is its view that the current tax provisions can be divided into two camps in black and white terms. That is, a provision either is a departure from the ideal system or it is within the system; there is no middle ground. To the contrary, Professor Kahn contends that the tax system is too sophisticated for such a crude classification to be appropriate. Instead, he maintains that the tax system should be analyzed under a more differentiated multivariate standard. Professor Kahn reviews the tax law's allowance of depreciation deductions as an example of the flaws in the tax expenditure concept. Taxpayers generally must capitalize business costs for items that will be used for more than one year (in contrast to deducting those costs immediately). The system for annually deducting a portion of the cost is referred to as depreciation. There has been much debate over the question of how the amount of depreciation deductions should be determined. Current tax law permits an accelerated method of depreciation (i.e., greater amounts deducted in the earlier years of use of the item) for some properties. One of the government's tax expenditure budgets treats depreciation in excess of what would be allowed under the straight-line method as a tax expenditure. Professor Kahn adopts an approach that shows that acceleration is not per se inconsistent with normal tax principles, but he does emphasize that his conclusion does not mean that accelerated depreciation is the proper system to employ. In The End of Cash, the Income Tax, and the Next 100 Years, Professors Jeffrey Kahn and Gregg Polsky take the occasion of the income tax centennial to question how future technology might improve tax compliance under the income tax system, although they note that such technology ironically may also signal the end of the income tax. Professors Kahn and Polsky propose that future technological advances in payment systems may shrink the cash economy down to an immaterial size. They suggest that such a world would lead to an increase in tax compliance since the government would easily be able to track income transfers between taxpayers, which should lead to increased tax compliance. The shrinkage of the tax gap would make the income tax system more efficient, thereby strengthening the system. Those same technological advances in payment systems also could lead to the demise of the income tax. For a variety of reasons, many economists and policy experts advocate the move from an income tax system to one that focuses more intently on consumption. One difficulty with such a move is the inability to introduce significant progressivity to such a system. Widespread and exclusive electronic payment systems, however, could change that and allow the government to tailor a consumption tax system with progressive xv
rates, thereby leading to the end of the income tax system that we celebrate today. Professor David Gamage’s contribution to the symposium—On the Future of Tax Salience Scholarship: Operative Mechanisms and Limiting Factors—builds on his earlier work, with Professor Darien Shanske, that reviewed the developing literature on tax salience. 16 “ ‘Tax salience’ ” refers to how the presentation of tax prices affects taxpayer behavior. In other words, tax salience measures how taxpayer behavior departs from key assumptions of neoclassical economic theory.” 17 Professor Gamage’s hope is that such analysis will further aid the development of scholarship and policymaking in the area. While he concedes that the body of literature is not quite there yet, Professor Gamage believes that the area will soon be developed enough to provide substantial policy recommendations for our federal income tax system. Appropriately, most of the attention of this symposium is directed at the substantive rules of federal income taxation, the policies behind them, and the alternatives to them. But procedural rules—the provisions governing resolution of controversies as to the meaning and application of the substantive rules—also are part of the story of the first 100 years and of the foreseeable future. Professor Steve Johnson takes a panoramic look at the procedural rules in Reforming Federal Tax Litigation: An Agenda. He identifies 12 key events and trends—statutory, regulatory, and judicial—that have shaped the current federal tax procedure and collection regimes. He finds that four sets of values have driven these events and trends: providing remedies for taxpayers and third parties that are both fair and perceived to be fair, protecting the revenue, achieving decisional consistency, and promoting process efficiency, reducing costs, and reducing delays. Applying these criteria, Professor Johnson proposes an array of reforms to federal tax litigation, as to available fora, available forms of action, and prerequisites to suit. His recommendations include expanding the Tax Court’s jurisdiction to give it nearly plenary civil tax jurisdiction, abolishing the Court of Claims’ tax jurisdiction, abolishing nearly all of the so-called TEFRA partnership audit and litigation regime, revising (though not abolishing) Collection Due Process hearings and litigation, and facilitating tax refund suits by allowing taxpayers to sue after paying only part of assessed liabilities (instead of having to pay the full assessment as a precondition of suit). The symposium issue concludes with Professor Larry Zelenak speculating on the question of whether Florida State University College of Law will hold another tax symposium in the year 2113 “cele16. David Gamage & Darien Shanske, Three Essays on Tax Salience: Market Salience and Political Salience, 65 TAX L. REV. 19 (2011). 17. Id. at 19.
xvi
brating” the 200th anniversary of the federal income tax. That is, will the income tax survive for another 100 years? In Will the Federal Income Tax Have a Bicentennial?, Professor Zelenak argues that the income tax system is defined by more than just its base. He notes that there are several defining features of the income tax that have nothing to do with its base. Believing that many of these features will remain intact, even if the income base changes, leads Professor Zelenak to conclude that it is arguable that the public would still consider our system to be an income tax—that is, that the label “income tax system” has become broader than just the income base. If true, it is likely that Florida State University College of Law will be issuing an all-digital, holographic symposium issue in 2113 celebrating (or lamenting) another 100 years of the income tax. We at Florida State are deeply grateful to all the conference participants for their enthusiasm and insights. We present the articles and essays in this symposium issue in the hope and belief that they will stimulate further thought and debate as the United States embarks on its second century of the federal income tax.
xvii
FEATURED PRESENTERS AND COMMENTATORS “One-Hundred Years of the Federal Income Tax” Florida State University College of Law March 1 & 2, 2013 Steven A. Bank, Paul Hastings Professor of Business Law, UCLA School of Law Joseph Bankman, Ralph M. Parsons Professor of Law and Business, Stanford Law School Joseph M. Dodge, Stearns Weaver Miller Weissler Alhadeff & Sitterson Professor, Florida State University College of Law David Gamage, Assistant Professor of Law, University of California, Berkeley School of Law James R. Hines, Jr., L. Hart Wright Collegiate Professor of Law and Richard A. Musgrave Collegiate Professor of Economics, University of Michigan Steve R. Johnson, University Professor, Florida State University College of Law Douglas A. Kahn, Paul G. Kauper Professor of Law, University of Michigan School of Law Jeffrey H. Kahn, Charles W. Ehrhardt Professor and Associate Dean, Florida State University College of Law Leandra Lederman, William W. Oliver Professor of Tax Law, Indiana University Maurer School of Law Gregg D. Polsky, Willie Person Mangum Professor of Law, University of North Carolina School of Law Clarissa Potter, Deputy Tax Director, AIG; former Deputy Chief Counsel, Internal Revenue Service Chris William Sanchirico, Samuel A. Blank Professor of Law, Business, and Public Policy, University of Pennsylvania Law School Daniel Shaviro, Wayne Perry Professor of Taxation, New York University School of Law Lawrence A. Zelenak, Pamela B. Gann Professor of Law, Duke Law School
xviii
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS DANIEL SHAVIRO * I. INTRODUCTION.................................................................................................. II. SIMONS’ METEORIC CAREER ............................................................................. III. HENRY SIMONS: A DIFFERENT TYPE OF LIBERTARIAN? .................................... A. Philosophical Libertarianism .................................................................... B. Assessing and Explaining Simons’ “Interventionism”............................... C. Simons’ Support for Progressive Income Taxation .................................... IV. SIMONS ON THE INCOME TAX ............................................................................ A. Income Taxation Versus Consumption Taxation....................................... 1. Why Did Simons Prefer the Income Tax? ............................................ 2. Simons’ View of Realization and Deferral ........................................... 3. What Might Simons Think Today About the Choice Between Income and Consumption Taxation? ............................................................... (a) More Pro-Income Tax?.................................................................. (b) Potentially Pro-Consumption Tax? .............................................. V. CONCLUSION .....................................................................................................
1 5 10 11 15 20 25 25 25 29 33 33 35 37
I. INTRODUCTION Surely just about everyone in the U.S. federal income tax field has heard of Henry Simons, although mainly for just one thing: his famous definition of “personal income” as the market value of one’s consumption plus change in net worth during the relevant period,1 as stated in his classic 1938 work, Personal Income Taxation. Simons’ formulation of what became known as the Haig-Simons income definition provided a central orientation point for U.S. tax policy thinking for many decades thereafter. Even today, it remains extremely important. The man behind the definition is, in some respects, considerably less well-known. For example, while most tax aficionados probably would identify him as a strong advocate of the federal income tax and of using a broadly defined base, fewer may know how comfortable he was with retaining the realization principle as a practical accommodation.2 Fewer still may be aware that he advocated eliminating the corporate income tax, conditioned only on a rule change providing for shareholder-level gain realization when appreciated stock (or other * Wayne Perry Professor of Taxation, NYU Law School. I am grateful to Miranda Perry, Chris Sanchirico, Robert Van Horn, and the participants in conferences at the USC and FSU Law Schools for helpful comments on an earlier draft. 1. More precisely, Simons states: “Personal income may be defined as the algebraic sum of (1) the market value of rights exercised in consumption and (2) the change in the value of the store of property rights between the beginning and end of the period in question.” HENRY C. SIMONS, PERSONAL INCOME TAXATION: THE DEFINITION OF INCOME AS A PROBLEM OF FISCAL POLICY 50 (1938) [hereinafter SIMONS, TAXATION]. 2. See, e.g., HENRY C. SIMONS, FEDERAL TAX REFORM 78 (1950) [hereinafter SIMONS, REFORM].
2
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
property) was transferred by gift or bequest, and accompanied by the suggestion that dividends not be taxed until the shareholder had fully recovered her basis in the underlying stock. 3 Perhaps fewest of all realize that today, in active intellectual memory, there are actually two Henry Simonses—albeit each the same person, not just biologically but also intellectually— remembered in two mostly distinct communities. First, of course, there is the income tax community’s Henry Simons, who, in the course of advocating a broad tax base and “drastic progression”4 memorably demolished intellectual opponents, 5 vehemently denounced support for his own bottom-line positions that was based on reasoning about utility or sacrifice,6 and lucidly addressed how a workable income definition could actually be implemented.7 Simons was not just an income tax writer, however. At the time of his death, most of his published work discussed other issues—for example, the case for a competitive free-market economy,8 the problems caused by labor unions,9 and his approach to monetary policy. 10 The nontax writings included not only Simons’ best-known work at the time of his death 11—which Personal Income Taxation cites as its underlying policy guide 12—but also the work that he considered his best. 13 Moreover, while these writings are little-known today in tax circles, there is a community interested in free enterprise, Chicagoschool economic analysis, and libertarianism, to which they remain at least historically important but highly controversial. 3. See id. at 112. 4. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 18. 5. See, e.g., id. at 16-17. 6. See id. at 8-16. 7. See id. at 41-60 (Chapter 2: “The Definition of Income”). 8. HENRY C. SIMONS, A Positive Program for Laissez Faire: Some Proposals for a Liberal Economic Policy, in ECONOMIC POLICY FOR A FREE SOCIETY 40 (1948) [hereinafter SIMONS, Positive Program]. 9. See Henry C. Simons, Some Reflections on Syndicalism, 52 J. POL. ECON. 1 (1944). 10. See Henry C. Simons, Rules versus Authorities in Monetary Policy, 44 J. POL. ECON 1 (1936). Simons’ previously published nontax writings were collected and posthumously published in Economic Policy for a Free Society (1948). The book includes twelve previously published essays that together are more than 300 pages long. This admittedly is slightly shorter than the combined page count for Personal Income Taxation (1938) plus his only other significant tax policy work, Federal Tax Reform (1950), but the latter was only posthumously published. 11. Aaron Director, Prefatory Note to ECONOMIC POLICY FOR A FREE SOCIETY, supra note 8, at v, v-vi (stating that Simons’ “best-known essay” was A Positive Program for Laissez Faire, initially published in 1934, which is discussed in more detail in Part III, infra). 12. See SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 2 n.1. 13. See George J. Stigler, Henry Calvert Simons, 17 J.L. & ECON. 1, 5 (1974) (stating that Simons once said that his article on monetary policy, Rules versus Authorities in Monetary Policy, was “the best piece of writing he had produced”).
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
3
George Stigler called Simons the “Crown Prince of . . . the Chicago school of economics,” 14 and others have agreed that he was its “prime architect.” 15 What is more, Simons labeled and regarded himself not merely as a free market supporter but more specifically as a libertarian. However, some aspects of Simons’ work—including, but not limited to, his advocacy of progressive income taxation—have caused this characterization to rankle in some quarters. Indeed, the wounds are sufficiently fresh that the title of one recent entry, published in the Journal of Libertarian Studies, used the present tense in proclaiming: “Henry Simons Is Not a Supporter of Free Enterprise.” 16 I first encountered the second Henry Simons at a lecture given by Ronald Coase at the University of Chicago Law School about twenty years ago. As I recall, Coase devoted a large portion of his remarks to denouncing Simons for what Coase considered an inappropriate willingness to rely on governmental regulatory solutions to market failure, rather than asking how markets could themselves handle these problems. 17 My then-Chicago colleague, the late Walter Blum, a Simons protégé who kindly acted as a mentor to me when I first entered law teaching, told me the next day that Coase had expressed surprise when Walter told him after the lecture of Simons’ continuing prominence as an intellectual architect of the income tax. It may seem most improbable that Simons, at least in his own self-assessment, was “at the same time an extreme libertarian and a believer in massive wealth redistribution.” 18 As Herbert Kiesling notes, however, while “[o]ne can wonder how such a strange mixture 14. Id. at 1. 15. See Bruce Caldwell, The Chicago School, Hayek, and Neoliberalism, in BUILDING CHICAGO ECONOMICS: NEW PERSPECTIVES ON THE HISTORY OF AMERICA’S MOST POWERFUL ECONOMICS PROGRAM 301, 304-06 (Robert Van Horn et al. eds., 2011) (accepting the “prime architect” claim although disagreeing in other respects with Van Horn’s and Mirowski’s analysis of the Chicago school’s early history); Rob Van Horn & Philip Mirowski, The Rise of the Chicago School of Economics and the Birth of Neoliberalism, in THE ROAD FROM MONT PÈLERIN: THE MAKING OF THE NEOLIBERAL THOUGHT COLLECTIVE 139, 140 (Philip Mirowski & Dieter Plehwe eds., 2009) (calling Simons the “prime architect” of the Chicago school); see also Edmund W. Kitch, The Fire of Truth: A Remembrance of Law and Economics at Chicago, 1932–1970, 26 J.L. & ECON. 163, 179 (1983) (discussing Simons’ strong intellectual influence on the development of the Chicago School). 16. See Walter Block, Henry Simons Is Not a Supporter of Free Enterprise, 16 J. LIBERTARIAN STUD. 3 (2002). 17. Coase relatedly, but as I recall less prominently at this particular lecture, criticized Arthur Pigou, who famously proposed what are now called “Pigovian” taxes to address negative externalities such as pollution, rather than asking how markets, through the assignment of property rights, could do the job. I would guess that Coase’s reason for emphasizing Simons more than Pigou was that he recalled Simons’ close connection with the University of Chicago Law School, the site and sponsor of the talk, as its first economist faculty member and an important early leader in the Chicago law and economics movement. 18. HERBERT KIESLING, TAXATION AND PUBLIC GOODS: A WELFARE-ECONOMIC CRITIQUE OF TAX POLICY ANALYSIS 67 (1992).
4
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
could be internally consistent, . . . in Simons’s hands the combination was logical.” 19 I will argue that he is best viewed as an egalitarian of a particular kind. He hated wealth inequality, concentrated economic power (as people on the left often do), and centralized political power (as anti-state people on the right often do), but for exactly the same reasons and in exactly the same way. He thus explained that he would have liked what he called “decentralized socialism,” just as much as he liked what he called libertarianism, if not for his conclusion that it was self-contradictory and/or would turn into the same thing anyway.20 By itself, this tale of the two (but actually one) Henry Simonses would provide ample motivation for looking back at his work in the context of a conference commemorating one hundred years of the U.S. federal income tax. In particular, it helps to show why he viewed comprehensive income taxation as such a good solution to a large piece of the dilemma that he faced by reason of hating both wealth inequality and government intervention in the economy. However, there is also an interesting story to review regarding Simons’ perspective on the design of the federal income tax. Although his reasons for favoring comprehensive income taxation were quite distinctive, other underlying motivations can lead to the same place. Thus, it is of interest today, for its own sake, to see how his views, as an undeniably smart commentator early in the intellectual history of the U.S. income tax, look more than seventy years later. I therefore will discuss Simons’ views on the choice between income and consumption taxation with an eye both to what has changed since the 1930s and to how these changes might matter to one who shared his normative framework. In effect, I will ask what Simons might think today— but with due understanding that it would be both silly and presumptuous to draw overly confident bottom-line conclusions. 21 The rest of this Article will proceed as follows: Part II offers a brief overview of Simons’ career; Part III discusses the issues raised by his self-proclaimed libertarianism, in light of its underlying philosophical motivations, his support for strong economic regulation in certain respects, and his support for a progressive income tax; Part IV dis19. Id. 20. HENRY C. SIMONS, Introduction: A Political Credo, in ECONOMIC POLICY FOR A FREE SOCIETY, supra note 8, at 1, 29-32 [hereinafter SIMONS, Political Credo]. George Stigler, while offering a strong statement of Simons’ libertarian credentials that I quote below, also said of Simons that “[m]uch of his program was almost as harmonious with socialism as with private-enterprise capitalism.” GEORGE J. STIGLER, MEMOIRS OF AN UNREGULATED ECONOMIST 149 (1988). 21. I am not the first to ask this sort of question. See Charlene Luke, What Would Henry Simons Do?: Using an Ideal to Shape and Explain the Economic Substance Doctrine, 11 HOUS. BUS. & TAX L.J. 108 (2011).
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
5
cusses his views on the income versus consumption tax debate; and Part V offers a brief conclusion. II. SIMONS’ METEORIC CAREER Henry Simons was born in 1899 in the small town of Virden, Illinois, the second child in an ambitious, upper middle class family.22 Second in his high school class, he was forced by family economic reverses to enroll at the University of Michigan, rather than following his older sister’s route to an elite eastern private college.23 Here, he initially planned to become a lawyer like his father, but he became interested in neoclassical economics. He started teaching economics at the University of Iowa in 1922. In 1927, he followed his mentor, the economist Frank Knight, to the University of Chicago Economics Department.24 Here, things initially did not go well. Many years later, Simons’ close friend Aaron Director reported that “Henry Simons was not liked in the economics department,” 25 although he had allies as well as foes. Economics students found him a rude and aggressively indifferent teacher, 26 quite in contrast to his subsequent very positive reception at the University of Chicago Law School. Simons’ scholarly record was also considered weak, as it consisted of “two book reviews in . . . twelve years” 27 until finally, in 1934, he published a selfdescribed “propagandist tract” in support of traditional liberalism 22. See Stigler, supra note 13, at 1; SHERRYL DAVIS KASPER, THE REVIVAL OF LAISSEZFAIRE IN AMERICAN MACROECONOMIC THEORY: A CASE STUDY OF THE PIONEERS 30 (2002) (noting that “[h]e grew up comfortably as a member of the middle class, the son of a moderately successful lawyer and an extremely ambitious homemaker”). 23. See Sherry Davis Kasper, Why Was Henry Simons Interventionist: The Curious Legacy of a Chicago Economist 6 (June 22, 2011) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://www.learningace.com/doc/5293928/7fbcc044dab921c837d7204dff3865e7/paper11kasper. 24. Id. at 6-8; Stigler, supra note 13, at 1 (describing Simons as Knight’s “premier student”). After starting at Iowa, Simons also completed a summer of graduate study at Columbia University and spent a half-year in Germany studying the work of leading German economists. Id.; Edmund W. Kitch, Simons, Henry Calvert, in 3 THE NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF ECONOMICS AND THE LAW 465 (Peter Newman ed., 1998). George Stigler later noted a view among the University of Chicago economics faculty that Simons “had been sent to Europe for six months so that he would learn German so he could get a Ph.D.” Kitch, supra note 15, at 177. 25. Kitch, supra note 15, at 176. 26. According to Paul Douglas, Simons’ colleague in the Chicago Economics Department, Simons was “almost openly insolent to those who ask questions and generally tells them that the questions they are asking are either too elementary for him to pay attention to or that they are not questions which any sensible person should propound or to which any sensible person reply.” See STIGLER, supra note 20, at 187 (quoting a letter by Douglas). 27. Kitch, supra note 15, at 177.
6
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
called A Positive Program for Laissez Faire: Some Proposals for a Liberal Economic Policy.28 Simons’ long pre-1934 period of academic torpor presumably reflects that, as George Stigler put it, not just “brilliance” but also a “capacity for boredom . . . marked his entire life.” 29 However, both the Great Depression and the Roosevelt Administration’s whirlwind “One Hundred Days” response to it upon taking office in 1933—which Simons detested but considered no worse than what the Hoover Administration had already been doing 30—galvanized him into activity. In June 1933, he gave a public speech in which he declared: “I must talk, I believe for the first time of my life, as an extreme conservative, as an exponent of that much ridiculed political philosophy, nineteenth century liberalism.” 31 Positive Program was then his followup, explaining not only why he favored what he called a laissez-faire economic policy but also why departures from that approach were, in his view, responsible for the Great Depression. He subsequently called Personal Income Taxation merely “part of a scheme of policy outlined” in Positive Program,32 and the latter includes a section on tax policy that extensively anticipates the now more famous follow-up work. I will further discuss Positive Program in Part III below. In terms of his career, however, while the tract attracted a large audience to its dissent from the popular New Deal-era consensus against laissezfaire economics,33 skeptics on the Chicago faculty viewed it as merely “skillful propaganda” that “isn’t basic scholarship[,] and we shouldn’t be giving our few jobs on that basis.” 34 What is more, while “[n]obody had any doubts about how smart Henry Simons was, . . . there were great doubts about . . . whether that book on personal income taxation would ever be finished.” 35 He had been working on it since the late 1920s,36 initially as his never-completed Ph.D. dissertation. 37 28. SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 1. 29. Stigler, supra note 13, at 1. 30. See SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 75 (“One cannot criticize the policies of the present administration without seeming to approve those of its predecessors. In fact, one must condemn the Democrats mainly for their wholesale extension of the worst policies of the past. The N.R.A. is merely Mr. Hoover’s trust policy and wage policy writ large. The agricultural measures and many other planning proposals are the logical counterpart and the natural extensions of Republican protectionism.”). 31. Kasper, supra note 23, at 15-16 (quoting a speech given by Simons to the Social Workers Discussion Group in June 1933). 32. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 2 n.1. 33. See ELLIS W. HAWLEY, THE NEW DEAL AND THE PROBLEM OF MONOPOLY 292 (1995). 34. Kitch, supra note 15, at 177 (quoting George Stigler, paraphrasing the views of Paul Douglas at the time). 35. Id. (footnote omitted). 36. Aaron Director, Simons on Taxation, 14 U. CHI. L. REV. 15, 15 (1946). 37. Kasper, supra note 23, at 10-11; Stigler, supra note 13, at 1. Reportedly, the rea-
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
7
There was a clear political and ideological element to the tenure fight over Simons. His mentor, Frank Knight, is “widely remembered as . . . one of the most prominent academic advocates of free markets during the Roosevelt years,” and as a man whose lectures “were credited . . . with transforming incoming socialists into nascent libertarians,” leaving behind ardent disciples such as George Stigler and Milton Friedman. 38 Knight’s and Simons’ arch-foe in the University of Chicago Economics Department, Paul Douglas—who spent several years trying to get Simons’ faculty appointment terminated 39—was a New Deal progressive, highly typical of an era in which institutionalist economists and legal realist law professors strongly favored extensive government in the economy and viewed laissez-faire as a doctrine that had utterly failed. As Milton Friedman later noted, Simons was “opposed to almost everything that the institutionalists and legal realists stood for.” 40 Ordinarily, Simons’ limited scholarly output, halfhearted teaching efforts, and stance outside the intellectual mainstream might have been expected to lead to his dismissal. However, in the face of Knight’s extremely emphatic support for Simons, and accompanying insistence that Simons’ opponents were engaged in a “personal attack on me,” 41 the easier course for the Economics Department was simply to put off any final decision. 42 Robert Maynard Hutchins, the energetic president of the University of Chicago, then resolved the impasse by (in Walter Blum’s later words) “thrusting” Simons onto the law school faculty 43 in 1939, one year after Personal Income Taxation had finally appeared in print. Simons had friends in the law school, but “the older members of the son Simons never finished obtaining his Ph.D. is that he “did not want to be examined by inferior minds” in oral examinations. Kasper, supra note 23, at 11 n.7. 38. Angus Burgin, The Radical Conservatism of Frank H. Knight, 6 MOD. INTELL. HIST. 513, 514 (2009). Knight did, however, to the long-lasting puzzlement of his followers, give a lecture at the University of Chicago in 1932 with the title “The Case for Communism, from the Standpoint of an Ex-liberal.” See id. He may have later regretted giving this talk, which was not widely published and which his libertarian supporters insisted was meant ironically or as a joke. See id. at 517-18. Others argue that it reflected his genuine ambivalence about free market capitalism, especially during the Great Depression, albeit reflecting feelings of “ex-liberalism” more than of actual communism or socialism. See id. 39. See STIGLER, supra note 20, at 187-89; Stigler, supra note 13, at 1-2. 40. Kitch, supra note 15, at 176. 41. Id. at 177 (quoting George Stigler, apparently paraphrasing what he learned from reading Knight’s correspondence). In his autobiography, Stigler quotes a letter from Knight saying: “I ‘feel’ as if eliminating [Simons] is eliminating me, and that when it is done I would be simply ‘through’ with the group, morally and sentimentally.” STIGLER, supra note 20, at 188-89. 42. George Stigler reports that the “controversy was resolved, Solomon-wise, by retaining Simons and releasing another Knight disciple.” Id. at 189. 43. See Kitch, supra note 15, at 176.
8
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
faculty were either opposed to having an economist or indifferent.” 44 Hutchins’ main motive, apart from resolving the impasse at the Economics Department, was to fill “the practical need to teach economics in the law school,” 45 an aim he valued given his view that “law schools as then in existence were mere trade schools anyway.”46 Things immediately started to go much better for Simons, who became a far more enthusiastic and effective teacher in his new setting. He not only intrigued and bemused law students who (in George Stigler’s words) had never before met an “intelligent conservative,” 47 but rapidly emerged as an intellectual leader. As Milton Friedman later noted, “Henry was a very gregarious fellow” and exerted a “great deal of influence through these social interactions.” 48 Walter Blum, for example, “got to know him as a result of drinking beer with him in Hanley’s tavern about once a week over a period of about six or eight months.” 49 By the early 1940s, according to Aaron Director, Simons “was slowly establishing himself as the head of a ‘school.’ ” 50 Friedrich Hayek, the pro-free market economist whose 1944 work, The Road to Serfdom, became a central libertarian tract, agreed, calling Simons the “intellectual centre” of a group of like-minded economists.51 Simons’ influence and teachings centered on using economic analysis to question the basic premises behind interventionist economic programs, such as minimum wage laws, securities regulations, price controls, and pro-union labor laws. 52 Simons was in touch with Hayek as early as 1934, when Hayek contacted him to express admiration for A Positive Program for Lais44. Id. (quoting Walter Blum). 45. Id. at 167. 46. Id. at 176 (quoting Aaron Director). 47. Id. at 177. 48. Id. at 179. Aaron Director and Allen Wallis also testified to Simons’ influence. See id. 49. Id. (quoting Blum). Simons’ intellectual influence is clear (although its limits can also be discerned) in the classic work WALTER J. BLUM & HARRY KALVEN, JR., THE UNEASY CASE FOR PROGRESSIVE TAXATION (1953). For example, this work shares Simons’ skepticism about theories “constructed on notions of benefit, sacrifice, [or] ability to pay.” Id. at 104. The authors agree with Simons that the main reason for tax progressivity is to reduce inequality (a much more obvious conclusion today than when the book was written). Blum and Kalven do, however, note of Simons’ critique of inequality as “unlovely” that “[t]his approach . . . forecloses any further discussion.” Id. at 72. They question the “contention [arguably made by Simons] that money represents economic power which permits its owners to make economic decisions affecting the lives of others.” Id. at 78. 50. Director, supra note 11, at v. 51. See Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15, at 169 n.10. 52. See Kitch, supra note 15, at 179 (quoting Walter Blum). Blum states that Simons’ intellectual contributions “had a great deal to do with the tone at the University of Chicago law school at that time and later.” Id.
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
9
sez Faire, and they soon became close friends. 53 In April 1945, after a Reader’s Digest condensation of The Road to Serfdom had become a national best-seller, things reached a new stage. A speech by Hayek at the Detroit Economics Club, while on a U.S. tour promoting the book, led a politically activist conservative businessman in the audience (Harold Luhnow, president of the Volker Fund) to propose funding a specifically American version of The Road to Serfdom. 54 While Luhnow wanted Hayek (or someone designated by him) to write an almost comic-book version of Road, suitable for a barely literate mass audience, 55 Hayek urged that the funding go instead to support the creation of a pro-free market intellectual center in the United States. To this end, he promptly contacted Simons, who responded enthusiastically. Simons proposed the establishment, at the University of Chicago, of an independent Institute to be headed by a serious pro-free market intellectual—he had in mind his close friend Aaron Director, whom he hoped to lure back from Washington to Chicago—and to have a largely academic bent. 56 While this was not quite what Luhnow wanted, further negotiations (also involving Robert Maynard Hutchins on behalf of the University of Chicago) led to a more modest plan to create a Free Market Study at Chicago, headed by Director, whose salary the Volker Fund would pay for five years. 57 There was one catch, however. The plan stipulated that Director would be granted tenure at the University of Chicago Law School, and this required approval not just from the law school (which agreed) but also from a university committee. On June 18, 1946, the committee rejected the proposal—to Simons’ great disappointment, in part due to his eagerness to persuade Director to move to Chicago. On the very next day, Simons died from an overdose of sleeping pills, possibly or even probably a suicide. 58 Shortly thereafter, Director agreed to come to Chicago even without an up-front promise of tenure. There, in addition to playing a key foundational role in establishing the law and economics program and movement at the University of Chicago Law School, Director oversaw 53. Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15, at 142. 54. See Caldwell, supra note 15, at 303; Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15, at 140-41. 55. Luhnow apparently “suggested the book How We Live by Fred G. Clark (1944) as stylistic model for the American Road to Serfdom. One doubts if Hayek had ever seen a copy, for if he had, he would have immediately soured on Luhnow. How We Live was a large-print book, with didactic pictures facing each page of ‘text,’ which itself consisted of single-sentence paragraphs written for people who still moved their lips as they read. The quality of argument resembled a fourth-grade civics textbook.” Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15, at 150. 56. See Caldwell, supra note 15, at 303-04. 57. See Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15, at 149-53. 58. For a full discussion of the question whether Simons committed suicide, see Robert Van Horn, A Note on Henry Simons’ Death, 46 HIST. POL. ECON. (forthcoming 2014).
10
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
the posthumous publication of two additional Simons books: Federal Tax Reform, collecting a linked set of essays that Simons had written in 1943 and 1944 to guide post-World War II U.S. tax policy; and Economic Policy for a Free Society, collecting a number of Simons’ non-tax works, including A Positive Program for Laissez Faire. III. HENRY SIMONS: A DIFFERENT TYPE OF LIBERTARIAN? Biographically speaking, Henry Simons’ credentials as a libertarian and free-market conservative could scarcely be stronger. He called himself “severely libertarian or, in the English-Continental sense, liberal” 59 and had what one can only call the audacity to write a spirited defense of laissez-faire economic principles in 1934, at the very moment when they were at their all-time U.S. low-water mark due to the Great Depression. He was closely associated both with Friedrich Hayek, whom contemporary libertarians still revere, and with such foundational conservative economists as Milton Friedman, George Stigler, and Aaron Director. 60 Indeed, if one had to name a single “architect” of the pro-free market law and economics movement at the University of Chicago, Simons’ credentials are as good as anyone’s. 61 Yet there are three at least apparent contradictions in thus classifying Simons. The first is that he was not a philosophical libertarian, at least as the term has often subsequently been defined in the literature. The second is that his version of laissez-faire economic policy, as set forth in his 1934 pamphlet, soon came to be seen by pro-free market conservatives as, in Ronald Coase’s later words, “highly interventionist.”62 The third is that Simons is rightly known for supporting progressive redistribution, and to this end championing a comprehensive income tax. Needless to say, progressivity and redistribution, not to mention the income tax, are anathema today among libertarians and many conservatives. Yet Simons himself evidently saw no contradiction, lauding progressivity in the 1934 pamphlet 63 and then describing Personal Income Taxation as merely an 59. Simons, Political Credo, supra note 20, at 1. 60. See, e.g., Robert Van Horn, Chicago’s Shifting Attitude Toward Concentrations of Business Power (1934–1962), 34 SEATTLE U. L. REV. 1527, 1528 (2011) (“From the mid1930s through the mid-1940s, among the economists (and economists in training) associated with the University of Chicago, there was a cohort of young economists—which included Henry Simons, Aaron Director, Milton Friedman, and George Stigler—who opposed concentrations of economic power on the basis of classical liberal doctrine. Simons was the public face of this group.”). 61. See, e.g., Caldwell, supra note 15, at 305; Kitch, supra note 15, at 179; Stigler, supra note 13, at 1; Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15, at 140. 62. Kitch, supra note 15, at 178. 63. See SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 65-69, 76-77.
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
11
elaboration of his 1934 ideas. 64 The rest of this part discusses these apparent contradictions. A. Philosophical Libertarianism In contemporary usage, libertarianism often is defined as a rightsbased or process-based approach to justice that rejects consequentialism. Thus, Robert Nozick, in Anarchy, State, and Utopia, disavows “end-result principles” that assess distributive justice in society based on how things have come out, in favor of the “historical” view that “whether a distribution is just depends upon how it came about.”65 Therefore, one can defend a state of affairs merely by showing that it had arisen via voluntary transactions from a just starting point. As Nozick recognized, this logic can support the enforceability of voluntary self-enslavement contracts. It thus can be deployed in defense of the essential justice of a society in which nearly everyone is observed to be a slave.66 While most libertarians reject this position, by positing that certain basic human rights are inalienable,67 libertarianism today is often construed as requiring acceptance, at least in most cases, of a rights-based, non-consequentialist approach to distributional and other issues. Thus, consider the claim that taking money from billionaires and giving it to poor people would be desirable if this would greatly increase aggregate human happiness— taking account both of the relative marginal utility of a dollar to people in the two groups and of the transfer’s incentive and political economy effects. To a modern deontological or rights-based libertarian, the underlying empirical claim need not be false in order for the conclusion to be rejected. Its classification as a rights violation rules it out from the start. This plainly is not Simons’ philosophical position. Consider the following statement from the second paragraph of his Positive Program: “There is in America no important disagreement as to the proper objectives of economic policy—larger real income, greater regularity of production and employment, reduction of inequality, 64. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 2 n.1. 65. ROBERT NOZICK, ANARCHY, STATE, AND UTOPIA 153 (1974). 66. See id. at 331 (“Will it be possible to shift to a nonvoluntary framework permitting the forced exclusion of various styles of life? . . . The comparable question about an individual is whether a free system will allow him to sell himself into slavery. I believe that it would.”). 67. See, e.g., Walter Block, Toward a Libertarian Theory of Inalienability: A Critique of Rothbard, Barnett, Smith, Kinsella, Gordon, and Epstein, 17 J. LIBERTARIAN STUD. 39, 40-41 (2003) (noting that few libertarians agree with his and Nozick’s view that voluntary self-enslavement contracts should be enforceable, and then proceeding to rebut prominent “middle ground” libertarians who have argued to the contrary).
12
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
preservation of democratic institutions. The real issues have to do merely with means, not with ends (or intentions) . . . .” 68 To show how this plays today in deontologically libertarian circles, consider the libertarian economist Walter Block’s aforementioned tract, Henry Simons Is Not a Supporter of Free Enterprise.69 Block, while himself an “anarcho-capitalist” libertarian who deems all government illegitimate, is willing to extend the label to “limitedgovernment libertarians . . . who take the position that a proper government exists only to protect peoples’ rights to personal safety and to the security of their legitimately held possessions.” 70 Hence, these libertarians, unlike Block himself, accept the potential legitimacy of armies, the police, and the courts. Alas, however, even thus given “at least a sporting chance of attaining the honorific ‘libertarian,’ ” 71 Simons falls so far short that Block convicts him of intellectual “fraud and false advertising,” 72 and closes by asking “how such a leftist could attain a reputation as a rightist . . . [and] why he felt the need to hide his views . . . under the banner of laissez faire. But these are questions for another day.” 73 Block is surely right that today’s libertarians—even though, in his view, they are for the most part lamentably heterodox—generally would be inclined to break Simons’ staff and expel him from the Libertarian Order. As we will see shortly, Simons most definitely did not view the government’s role as limited to providing an army, police, and the courts to protect people’s safety and “legitimately held possessions.” 74 However, Block’s reading of the term “libertarian” is both ahistorical and too narrow—at least, if we are trying to classify Simons as a matter of good intellectual history, rather than simply to apply one’s own preferred definition (which Block, of course, has every right to do). Consider Hayek’s The Road to Serfdom—surely, in intellectual history, a canonical and foundational libertarian work. Rather than stressing the importance of rights irrespective of consequences, Hayek emphasizes the empirical claim that movement towards greater centralized economic planning, even when it has as yet gone no further than it had in England and the United States as of the book’s 1944 publication date, will lead inexorably to Nazi- or Soviet-style 68. 69. 70. 71. 72. 73. 74.
SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 40. Block, supra note 16. Id. at 4-5. Id. at 5. Id. at 4 n.3. Id. at 31. Id. at 5.
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
13
totalitarianism.75 This is precisely the concern that Simons expressed a decade earlier in Positive Program. 76 Simons, just like Hayek, despised the “mongrel system of ‘national planning’ ” not only as a mere way station on the march towards totalitarianism, but as something that itself “implies and requires extreme concentration of political power, under essentially undemocratic institutions.” 77 The New Deal did not have to turn into Nazism in order for Simons to view it as containing odious qualities of the same type, even if in vastly lesser degree. Even in today’s intellectual climate, it makes little sense to out Simons as a “leftist” and as “not a supporter of free enterprise,” merely because he cared about consequences rather than about innate and inviolable rights, and thus was conditionally willing to contemplate rights violations. Such a classification scheme would rule out accepting the self-proclaimed credentials of any classical liberal/contemporary political conservative who relies on the consequentialist view that free markets, strong private property rights, and limited government are generally the best prescription for increasing human welfare. Its adoption would require classifying the likes of Adam Smith, Milton Friedman, and Richard Epstein, among others, as likewise “leftists” who oppose capitalism and freedom. In this regard, consider what Milton Friedman says about graduated income taxation in his classic 1962 book, Capitalism and Freedom. To be sure, Friedman does “find it hard, as a liberal” to see the justification for graduated rates when they are merely being used to redistribute income rather than to finance the costs of government.78 He considers this “a clear case of using coercion to take from some in order to give to others and thus to conflict head-on with individual freedom.” 79 Yet Friedman defines the costs of government, which everyone must help to pay for, as “including perhaps measures to eliminate poverty,” 80 even though this is redistribution (coercively funded) plain and simple. Moreover, Friedman accepts that, in principle, paying for the costs of government “might well call for some measure of graduation, both on grounds of assessing costs in accordance with benefits and on 75. See, e.g., FRIEDRICH A. HAYEK, THE ROAD TO SERFDOM 2-5 (1944). Hayek accepts that wartime calls for centralization of powers, but he views the current English and U.S. course as clearly towards totalitarianism even in the aftermath of Hitler’s then-impending defeat. 76. SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 40-41, 76-77. 77. Id. at 52. 78. MILTON FRIEDMAN, CAPITALISM AND FREEDOM 174 (1962). 79. Id. 80. Id.
14
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
grounds of social standards of equity.” 81 The only problem he sees is that the “present high nominal rates [then reaching 92%, under the federal income tax] . . . can hardly be justified on this ground—if only because their yield is so low.” 82 In short, under Block’s standard, not only is Milton Friedman no libertarian (a point that is uncontroversial), 83 but only as a matter of degree can he fall short of being a “leftist” who opposes capitalism and freedom despite having used those two words in the title of his most famous book. So perhaps the next question should be why Friedman, like Simons, declined to admit his ostensibly true nature as a secret “leftist.” Returning to Simons, he certainly did not claim to be a libertarian in today’s deontological sense—unsurprisingly, since any such claim would have been anachronistic. Rather, Simons placed himself squarely in an intellectual tradition whose “distinctive feature . . . is emphasis upon liberty as both a requisite and a measure of progress.”84 While consequentialist and thus “largely pragmatic” in his view of social ethics, he described his views as “giv[ing] special place to liberty . . . as a ‘relatively absolute absolute.’ ” 85 George Stigler helped make the case for the accuracy of Simons’ self-characterization in a 1974 retrospective: The central philosophy of the Positive Program was highly individual. Simons believed that it was essential to the preservation of personal freedom that a large sector of economic life be organized privately and competitively—this was a fundamental element of the liberal position that many, perhaps even an increasing share of us, still believe. . . . Simons’ central goal is as vital and as 81. Id. (emphasis added). 82. Id. A few pages earlier, in response to the view that progressive income taxation could be viewed as an insurance device that effectively pools people’s income and ability risk, thereby addressing the market failure that arises if the market fails to supply a suitable insurance vehicle, Friedman objects only that “the taxes are imposed after” market outcomes are known, with “taxes [being] voted mostly by those who think they have drawn the blanks.” Id. at 163. He states that he would have no objection if one generation voted the tax schedules that were to apply on this ground to as yet unborn generations, although he posits that the resulting rate structure would be much less graduated. Id. 83. Block has noted a long set of issues on which Friedman and libertarians disagree. See Walter Block, Milton Friedman RIP, MISES DAILY (Nov. 16, 2006), http://mises.org/daily/2393. He also has published correspondence in which Friedman goodhumoredly called him “a fanatic, not . . . a reasonable man.” Walter Block, Fanatical, Not Reasonable: A Short Correspondence Between Walter Block and Milton Friedman, 20 J. LIBERTARIAN STUD. 61, 61 (2006). 84. SIMONS, Political Credo, supra note 20, at 1. In naming his precursors within the liberal tradition, Simons did not restrict himself to people we would call libertarians. The people he cited included, for example, Adam Smith, John Stuart Mill, John Locke, David Hume, Jeremy Bentham, Alexis de Tocqueville, and his friend (as discussed above) Friedrich Hayek. Id. 85. Id. at 2. As I discuss below, the full quotation that I excerpted in the text above states that Simons “gives special place to liberty (and nearly coordinate place to equality) as a ‘relatively absolute absolute.’ ” Id. (emphasis added).
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
15
irresistible today as it was forty years ago: to devise a decentralized, unpoliticized world in which personal freedom and economic efficiency find wide scope and strong defense. 86
Stigler had strong grounds for reaching this conclusion. For example, Simons was, as Stigler notes, a “violent critic” of New Deal industrial policy legislation such as the National Recovery Act (NRA). 87 Nor was he kinder to specific NRA and industrial policy proponents, calling Henry Wallace, Secretary of Agriculture and then-Vice President in the Roosevelt Administration, “our leading advocate of the totalitarian or pre-totalitarian economy of negotiation among tightly organized, monopolizing functional groups.” 88 Simons also hated labor unions, saying that “our [most] serious and ominous monopoly problem lies in the labor market and in the power of unions to behave monopolistically.” 89 Simons argued that the greatest social and economic ill that the U.S. faced was monopolistic price-fixing, along with “excessive political interference with relative prices,” 90 such as through tariffs and industry subsidies. In his view, such interference with market prices was not merely allocatively inefficient (the standard neoclassical claim). Worse still, it was a prime cause of the Great Depression. However, worst of all, in Simons’ view, was the fact that such interference fundamentally violated principles of economic and political freedom and equality, and would lead inexorably to the need for dictatorship to mediate the conflicts between organized groups. 91 One might almost say here that the case is closed regarding Simons’ classical liberal and generally pro-free market credentials, except for one further consideration. Simons did indeed support a set of policies that involved significant government intervention in the economy. My next topic, therefore, is what to make of what he called his “positive program for laissez faire.” B. Assessing and Explaining Simons’ “Interventionism” As noted above, one reasonably might expect that a libertarian, or even a generally pro-free market classical liberal, would support 86. Stigler, supra note 13, at 3, 5. In Part III.B, infra, I discuss certain crucial qualifications to Stigler’s view that Simons favored free markets and laissez-faire. 87. See Kitch, supra note 15, at 178. Simons stated, for example, that “[n]o diabolical ingenuity could have devised a more effective agency for retarding or preventing recovery (or for leading us away from democracy) than the National Recovery Act and its codes.” SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 75. 88. Henry C. Simons, For a Free-Market Liberalism, 8 U. CHI. L. REV. 202, 203 (1941). 89. Id. at 205. Simons further discussed his negative view of unions in his article Some Reflections on Syndicalism. See Simons, supra note 9. 90. SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 42. 91. See id. at 43-46.
16
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
keeping the government’s economic and regulatory role quite limited. What about Henry Simons? In Positive Program and elsewhere, he called for the “outright dismantling of our gigantic corporations” with a “[l]imitation upon the total amount of property which any single corporation may own.” 92 In addition, he favored regulating companies’ financial structure by providing that they could issue only two or three types of securities, centered on a single class of common stock and what we might call plain-vanilla debt. 93 Likewise, almost startlingly (or, as Block says, “eerily” 94) anticipating the classic 1958 book, The Affluent Society, by the decidedly progressive and antilaissez-faire economist John Kenneth Galbraith, Simons condemned advertising for its capacity to manipulate—rather than actually satisfying—consumer demand. For this among other reasons, he urged that advertising face heavy taxation.95 Given such features of Simons’ thought, it is unsurprising that Ronald Coase, at a 1983 retrospective session among founders of the Chicago law and economics movement, should find it “difficult to understand” characterizations of the “highly interventionist” Positive Program as pro-free market, adding that he “would be interested if someone could explain this pro-market view of Henry Simons.” 96 As Brad DeLong, in telling this story, recounts, “Simons’ former Chicago pupils, his successors as upholders of classical liberalism in economics, did not [respond by] ris[ing] to his defense.” 97 Instead, they admitted that “ ‘You can paint him with different colors,’ ” and that “ ‘[i]t’s quite a mixed picture,’ ” to be defended on the ground that, when he wrote in the 1930s, almost everyone else, both at the University of Chicago and around the country, was even further to the left. 98 Aaron Director, his closest friend in the group attending the 92. Id. at 58-59. 93. See SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 59. 94. Block, supra note 16, at 28. 95. See SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 71-73. Simons complains that “[p]rofits may be obtained either by producing what consumers want or by making consumers want what one is actually producing. The possibility of profitably utilizing resources to manipulate demand is, perhaps, the greatest source of diseconomy under the existing system.” Id. at 71. 96. Kitch, supra note 15, at 178. Not long after this session, Stigler wrote in his autobiography that “Simons had preached a form of laissez-faire in . . . A Positive Program for Laissez Faire, but what a form! He proposed nationalization of basic industries such as telephones and railroads because regulation had worked poorly. (I am reminded of the king who was asked to award a prize to the better of two minstrels. After hearing the first, he said, ‘Give the prize to the second.’).” STIGLER, supra note 20, at 148-49. 97. J. Bradford DeLong, In Defense of Henry Simons’ Standing as a Classical Liberal, 9 CATO J. 601, 601 (1990). 98. Id. at 601 (quoting Kitch, supra note 15, at 178 (quoting Harold Demsetz and George Stigler, respectively)). Thus, Milton Friedman pointed out that, “in 1934 when [Positive Program] appeared, I would say that close to a majority of the social scientists and the
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
17
retrospective, even offered the suggestion that one of Simons’ reasons for expressing support for “interventionist programs was to make the private system of production palatable to his colleagues,” 99 as opposed to actually favoring such programs—as it happens, a suggestion that finds some support in Simons’ private correspondence. 100 Simons’ old friends may not entirely have remembered, however, the extent to which their own views had changed since the 1930s. Thus, consider Milton Friedman, who recalled viewing Positive Program as “strongly pro free market in its orientation” when he first read it in the 1930s—only, upon later rereading, to be “astounded at what [he] read.”101 Part of the reason for this change in perspective may have been that Friedman himself had changed in the interim. Friedman, not just in the 1930s but as late as 1947, had been sufficiently worried about the corporate monopoly problem to resemble Simons in favoring regulatory restrictions (albeit milder ones) that he hoped would discourage corporate mergers and the existence of large companies.102 Private monopoly, as a potential consequence of corporate size and thus perhaps even its cause, was a major concern to Chicago school economists until empirical work in the 1950s persuaded them of two things. The first was that competition in private markets pervasively undermines monopoly even if it is briefly established. 103 Thus, regulatory intervention is not needed to combat it. Second, they now concluded that the main danger of monopoly “come[s] not from large corporations that exploit purely private economies of scale . . . but from interest groups that enter a symbiotic relationship with a government that purports to ‘regulate’ them.” 104 Hence, concern about the private exercise of monopoly power should make one all the more eager to restrict the scope of regulation, since “[w]henever the governstudents in the social sciences at the University of Chicago were either members of the Communist party or very close to it,” and “the general intellectual atmosphere was strongly prosocialist.” Kitch, supra note 15, at 178-79. 99. Kitch, supra note 15, at 179. 100. As Sherry Davis Kasper recounts, in response to a letter from Hayek questioning Simons’ proposal for direct government ownership (in lieu of regulation) of natural monopolies, Simons wrote: “I may confess privately to having used a low, debating trick. . . . I am willing to prostitute my judgment somewhat, in advocating government ownership, in order to vent my spleen fully as to the merits of a grand system of private monopoly with government regulation of prices and wages.” Kasper, supra note 23, at 28. 101. Kitch, supra note 15, at 178. 102. See Van Horn, supra note 60, at 1540. 103. See id. at 1540-43; see also Arnold C. Harberger, Monopoly and Resource Allocation, AM. ECON. REV., May 1954, at 77, 86-87 (suggesting that the deadweight loss resulting from the exercise of monopoly power was relatively small). 104. DeLong, supra note 97, at 615.
18
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
ment does something, it probably acts in the interest of some powerful and monopolistic interest group.”105 Given this change in empirical knowledge (or at least belief), DeLong argues that Coase and others were mistaken, in later years, to classify Simons as an interventionist rather than as truly one of them. He merely differed from them empirically, based on the Chicago school’s state of knowledge about monopoly problems when he was writing, as compared to later. Thus, “Simons was a consistent classical liberal of his times, even if, in retrospect, he may now appear to have been [empirically] wrong in his judgment on specific issues.”106 DeLong concludes that, under Simons’ empirical beliefs concerning the monopoly problem (which, again, were standard in Chicago at the time), restricting corporate size so that markets will remain competitive is merely “a completion of the idea of the night watchman state. The night watchman state enforces contracts and guards against explicit theft. A monopolist is also an implicit thief because his possession of market power leads to the exchange of commodities at prices that do not reflect underlying social scarcities.” 107 Simons makes very much the same point in Positive Program. Responding to laissez-faire’s reputation as “a merely do-nothing policy,” he calls this characterization “unfortunate and misleading. It is an obvious responsibility of the state under [laissez-faire] policy to maintain the kind of legal and institutional framework within which competition can function effectively as an agency of control.” 108 In short, breaking up large companies is no more a violation of laissezfaire than enforcing contracts and protecting private property against thieves. The same line of argument could also, perhaps, apply to Simons’ support for heavily taxing advertising. A key complaint he makes about advertising is that, because it is so costly, it “[e]ntrenches monopoly by setting up a financial barrier to the competition of new and small firms.” 109 Relatedly, it creates wasteful arms races among firms, which “must spend enormous sums . . . if only to counteract the expenditures of competitors.” 110 Thus, even if he adds the Galbraithstyle complaint that advertisers manipulate consumers into 105. Id. 106. Id. at 614. 107. Id. at 606. Consistently with this view, Simons defines “commutative justice,” which he distinguishes from “distributive justice” while regarding both as important, as “connot[ing] exchange of equal values, as measured objectively by organized [but competitive] markets.” SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 4. Monopoly is indeed theft under Simons’ view. 108. SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 42. 109. Id. at 72. 110. Id. at 71.
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
19
“want[ing] what one is actually producing,” 111 which seems to raise broader issues about the welfare effects of market outcomes, one could argue that he is mainly just seeking to advance his antimonopoly program, while also addressing a collective action problem as between business rivals that leads to waste. As George Stigler later noted, Simons’ hostile view of advertising was widely held among economists before the 1960s, when Stigler’s own work on the economics of information made the case for viewing advertising much more benignly, as “an extremely efficient way of conveying much of this information . . . [that] is as essential for competitive firms as for monopolies.” 112 Thus, in defense of Simons’ standing as a pro-free market classical liberal notwithstanding his view of advertising, one could again argue that the dispute is merely empirical, concerning means rather than ends, and that it is anachronistic to judge Simons based on whether he had accepted, in advance, arguments that the Chicago school only made decades later. Nonetheless, his view of advertising does indeed suggest a more capacious sense of market failure, and of the need for government intervention, than one might expect from a “laissez-faire” economist. The metaphor of the mere night watchman grows increasingly strained as the list of market failures that the state must address keeps growing. Suppose one nonetheless accepts Simons’ classical liberal and generally pro-free market credentials. How does one square them with his favoring significant redistribution through an income tax that features “drastic progression”113 in its rates? One possibility is to separate the two Henry Simonses as if they were different people. Thus, DeLong “place[s] to one side” Simons’ tax policy views when assessing his classical liberal credentials, 114 and George Stigler— sounding less certain than one might have expected—describes these views as “surely independent” of Simons’ other beliefs.115 Simons himself evidently did not thus classify his tax views, however. Indeed, Positive Program treats a set of tax policy recommendations that are largely identical to those in Personal Income Taxation—mainly written by this time, although not yet published—as part and parcel of his libertarian and laissez-faire program. As we will see next, this reflects a commonality of motivation that has powerful internal logic, even if it is not at all how people typically parse the issues today. 111. 112. 113. 114. 115.
Id. STIGLER, supra note 20, at 164. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 18. DeLong, supra note 97, at 603 n.3. See Stigler, supra note 13, at 4.
20
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
C. Simons’ Support for Progressive Income Taxation In determining why Simons favored “drastic progression,” a natural first stop is Personal Income Taxation, and in particular the first half of its forty-page first chapter. Here Simons evaluates at length various grounds for favoring progressivity, while the second half of the chapter considers tradeoffs to pursuing redistribution (such as effects on efficiency) and the question of what tax and other fiscal instruments might be deployed in its behalf. Unfortunately, the result of this inquiry—unless supplemented by looking at other writings by Simons—is disappointing and even perplexing, potentially creating the false impression that his endorsement of progressivity is so whimsical and seemingly unmotivated that the question of how it might relate to his other economic views is destined to remain mysterious. Only when one supplements it, in particular by looking at Positive Program and at A Political Credo, which offers a broader account of his political views, 116 does the mystery lift to a degree. Simons opens the first chapter of Personal Income Taxation with a harsh attack on tax policy writers who “dissemble” their true underlying beliefs by “maintain[ing] a pretense of rigorous, objective analysis untinctured by mere ethical considerations.” 117 These aspiring, but fake, scientists “religiously eschew a few proscribed phrases, clutter up title-pages and introductory chapters with pious references to the science of public finance, and then write monumental discourses upon their own prejudices and preconceptions.”118 Whom exactly might Simons mean by this? The answer appears to be: virtually everyone in the then-existing academic literature on tax policy. He starts by mentioning the “doctrine of taxation according to benefit,” under which “[e]ach person may be called upon, as in his dealings with private enterprise, to pay according as he receives.” 119 But given the impossibility of measuring different people’s benefit from the provision of public goods, such as national defense and internal security, this “slogan, of course, has little more than emotive content,” and “leads nowhere at all.” 120 Next he addresses “[t]he greater part of what has been written about justice in taxation . . . couched in terms of sacrifice. This concept, along with ‘ability’ and ‘faculty,’ ” rests ultimately on the con116. Simons wrote A Political Credo in 1945, although it was only published posthumously “in an endeavor to formulate specifically the political predispositions implicit in his work.” SIMONS, Political Credo, supra note 20, at 1 (editor’s note). 117. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 1. 118. Id. at 2. 119. Id. at 3. 120. Id. at 4.
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
21
cept of utility. 121 Unfortunately, however, each version of these doctrines (in Simons’ view) is utter nonsense—unsurprisingly, given how “absurd” and “naïve” he finds all “hedonistic ethics” and welfare economics (i.e., anything relying on the concept of utility).122 So what if “[m]any professors of economic dialectic still find comfort and intellectual satisfaction (and ‘filler’ for courses and textbooks) in the ‘explanations’ of hedonism,” and if they “continue to practice a kind of utility therapy and to write their prescriptions for the economist’s millennium in the hedonistic code”? 123 Thus, John Stuart Mill’s doctrine of “equal sacrifice—that tax burdens should so be distributed that the same total sacrifice is imposed upon every individual”—has received “devastating criticism,” in particular from Francis Edgeworth, who “demonstrates conclusively—so far as is possible with such dialectical tools—that equal individual sacrifice by no means minimizes the total burden” in utility terms, which definitionally is the proper utilitarian aim.124 Yet Edgeworth’s “minimum sacrifice” theory fares no better in Simons’ hands. This theory ostensibly supports complete leveling of income, on the ground that everyone has the same utility function, characterized by declining marginal utility of income. Thus, so long as A has even one dollar more than B, equalizing their after-tax incomes will increase B’s welfare more than it reduces A’s welfare. Simons raises numerous objections, however. What about people’s attachment to their current levels of income? 125 And what about the unproved “assumption that all individuals are, or must be treated as, equally efficient as pleasure machines”? 126 Given these absurdities (in Simons’ view), “[w]hat really commends the Edgeworth doctrine to liberal students, of course, is its conclusion—its pseudoscientific statement of the case against inequality.” 127 Having thus disposed, at least to his own satisfaction, of what remains today the most widely followed ground in the public economics literature for favoring progressive redistribution, 128 Simons concludes 121. Id. at 5. 122. Id. at 12. 123. Id. at 14-15. 124. Id. at 6. 125. Id. at 8-10. 126. Id. at 11. 127. Id. at 10. 128. I refer here to the claim that people have, or should generally be treated as having, identical utility functions characterized by declining marginal utility. Edgeworth’s claim that this leads to favoring a 100% tax rate and full equalization of everyone’s aftertax income is generally rejected today due to concern about incentive effects. The literature on optimal income taxation, building on James Mirrlees’ work, generally treats the question of tax rate design as turning on the tradeoff between Edgeworth’s logic and concern about the incentive effects of positive marginal tax rates. See generally J.A. Mirrlees, An
22
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
his scathing survey of the existing literature by dismissing the work of writers who assert that tax burdens should vary based on “ability” or “faculty.” 129 This standard is “totally ambiguous,” and thus not even to be described as a “principle” except in scare quotes. Given that “ability or faculty . . . cannot be conceived quantitatively or defined in terms of any procedure of measurement,” their use “indicates that the writer prefers the kind of taxation which he prefers; that he is unwilling to reveal his tastes or examine them critically; and that he finds useful in his profession a basic ‘principle’ from which, as from a conjuror’s hat, anything may be drawn at will.”130 This brings us near the end of Simons’ almost wholly destructive survey in Personal Income Taxation of why one might favor a progressive tax system. What does he propose to do instead? In a word, he proposes simply to be forthright about his own priors and prejudices. Then comes what is probably the most famous sentence in Personal Income Taxation, other than the income definition: “The case for drastic progression in taxation must be rested on the case against inequality—on the ethical or aesthetic judgment that the prevailing distribution of wealth and income reveals a degree (and/or kind) of inequality which is distinctly evil or unlovely.”131 And with that said, Simons moves on to discussing tradeoffs and methods of implementation. Reading Personal Income Taxation all by itself can make it seem natural to conclude that Simons’ aversion to inequality—and his consequent support for “drastic progression”—is a mere isolated prejudice or sentiment that he sees no need to explain. We have the biases we have, he suggests, so all we can do is acknowledge them and move on, as distinct from reasoning or arguing about them. 132 And if that is so, then there might perhaps also be no point in seeking to relate this particular sentiment to anything else that Simons believes, given the lack of any broader discussion of his views in Personal Income Taxation. And while careful readers may have observed that Chapter One has a footnote at the start, stating that one’s tax policy views are “properly a derivative, or subordinate part, of a broader position on general questions of economic policy,” as to which (for Simons’ views) readers are encouraged to consult Positive Program, 133 this precedes Exploration in the Theory of Optimum Income Taxation, 38 REV. ECON. STUD. 175 (1971). 129. Simons finds a kind word for the “so-called sociopolitical theory of [the German writer] Adolph Wagner.” SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 15. Wagner is praised, however, for saying that one needs a prior view as to the proper distribution of income in order to support any particular theory. Thus, “[h]is views (if we pursue them no farther) seem eminently sensible and represent sound criticism of other writers.” Id. 130. Id. at 17. 131. Id. at 18-19. 132. See id. at 2. 133. Id. at 2 n.1.
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
23
the famous “unlovely” statement by a full sixteen pages and thus is easy to miss. As it happens, the words “evil” and “unlovely” are in fact derived from Positive Program, where Simons states the following: Turning now to questions of justice, of equitable distribution, we may suggest that equitable distribution is at least as important with respect to power as with reference to economic goods or income . . . . Surely there is something unlovely, to modern as against medieval minds, about marked inequality of either kind. A substantial measure of inequality may be unavoidable or essential for motivation; but it should be recognized as evil and tolerated only so far as the dictates of expediency are clear. 134
This still does not offer an underlying rationale for Simons’ dislike of inequality. It does, however, reveal the core of what his support for laissez-faire has in common with his tax policy views. Both political power and economic wealth, in his view, should be distributed more equally, rather than less equally, albeit subject to “dictates of expediency” to the contrary. 135 With respect to political power, this means having a limited government that leaves alone relative prices and the allocation of capital between industries. With respect to economic power, it calls for redistribution through the income tax. Positive Program’s reference to “unloveliness” comes right after a sustained denunciation, first of centralized economic planning as leading inexorably to dictatorship, and then of private monopoly power as equally odious and dangerous. 136 Simons has the same revulsion for state actors wielding centralized authority to tell us what to do—the case of unequal political power—as he does for princes living it up in their castles while paupers starve—the case, in his view, of unequal economic power. Elsewhere in Positive Program and Political Credo, Simons expresses more of the same vision. Thus, to offer a full quote that I selectively edited above, he says that classical liberalism “gives special place to liberty (and nearly coordinate place to equality) as a ‘relatively absolute absolute.’ ” 137 These two values are linked, however, by the difficulty of having either one without the other. “Freedom without power, like power without freedom, has no substance or meaning.” 138 And this presumably applies to economic freedom no less than to political freedom, given Simons’ habit of linking the two. In Simons’ view, therefore, an economically unequal society, even if re134. 135. 136. 137. 138.
SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 51-52 (emphases added). See id. See generally id. at 40-51. SIMONS, Political Credo, supra note 20, at 2 (emphasis added). Id. at 6.
24
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
flecting free market outcomes rather than the exercise of government or private monopoly power, is one in which the worst-off people are not entirely free. This is a horizontal, or even a leveling, vision of both economic and political power. Simons does not like plutocrats rising far above the peasants (even if the latter, as a formal legal matter, are entirely free), any more than he likes Washington bureaucrats telling private economic actors what to do. Is this “liberal” in the classical sense? That depends on how one defines the tradition. In any event, however, emotionally no less than intellectually, it is certainly no Ayn Rand or Paul Ryan version of the laissez-faire creed. Simons does not yearn for a world in which the great are permitted to thrive, but for one in which the small do not have anyone too far above them, either politically or economically. 139 In this regard, Sherry Davis Kasper makes an important point about the difference between Simons’ intellectual background and that of his successors in the Chicago school. She notes that he, like other economists who received their training between the two World Wars, was influenced by the immediately preceding era’s Gilded Age economists, for whom “the primary problem . . . [was] the concentration of economic wealth and power and the accompanying inequality it engendered.” 140 She later adds that Simons “worked in the climate of interwar pluralism. As a result, he looked through the world with a different set of lenses, colored primarily by elements of progressive social science that the pluralism of interwar economics allowed to linger.” 141 Only, Simons amalgamated these classic Gilded Age and interwar concerns of economic power with a commonly motivated dislike of centralized political power that his successors would hold without retaining the Gilded Age element. One last point worth noting here concerns how Simons’ views about economic and political power cohered to make a comprehensive income tax so attractive to him. One of its greatest virtues, in his view, was that, insofar as it treated all different types of income neutrally, it avoided engaging in selective economic regulation—the great vice, along with regressivity, that he ascribed to the tariffs and excise duties that were still a key U.S. federal revenue source when he wrote and published Personal Income Taxation. Taxing all income as alike as possible keeps the government out of the price-fixing and resource allocation business, thus preserving free market conditions 139. See id. at 23 (“A cardinal tenet of libertarians is that no one may be trusted with much power—no leader, no faction, no party, no ‘class,’ no majority, no government, no church, no corporation, no trade association, no labor union, no grange, no professional association, no university, no large organization of any kind.”). 140. Kasper, supra note 23, at 5. 141. Id. at 28.
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
25
and limiting centralized political power, even if people face very high tax rates. IV. SIMONS ON THE INCOME TAX With Simons’ general philosophical commitments and motivations better in focus, I turn now to his work on income taxation and will focus on why, and to what extent, he preferred income taxation to consumption taxation. After discussing his main arguments and conclusions, along with the separate issue of the degree to which he actually favored an income tax in practice, I will ask what has changed since he wrote and how that might affect the views that one who shared his intellectual commitments would hold today. A. Income Taxation Versus Consumption Taxation 1. Why Did Simons Prefer the Income Tax? For a number of decades, the leading big-picture issue in U.S. academic debate about tax policy has been whether the federal income tax should be replaced by an individual-level consumption tax that, like the income tax, has graduated rates. Experts’ awareness that one can levy a consumption tax at the individual level—as distinct from, say, a retail sales tax or value-added tax model, in which businesses’ role in collecting the tax impedes applying varying individual rates—often is thought to date from no earlier than 1955, when the British economist Nicholas Kaldor published a book advocating cashflow taxation of individuals, 142 or perhaps even 1974, when Harvard law professor William Andrews published a classic article on the subject. 143 It thus may come as a surprise to see Simons addressing this very topic at length, in both Personal Income Taxation and Federal Tax Reform. This, however, turns out to reflect two antecedents. The first is economist Irving Fisher’s advocacy of a progressive consumption tax, to which Simons responded at some length—and, by his acerbic standards, quite respectfully—in Personal Income Taxation. The second, less well-known today, although cited by both Simons and Fisher, is an actual legislative proposal for a cash-flow tax, which Congressman Ogden Mills introduced in 1921 and wrote about in the National Tax Journal. 144 This was essentially a Kaldor- or Andrewsstyle cash-flow consumption tax avant la lettre. It involved replacing the existing income tax with a tax on people’s consumer expenditures 142. See generally NICHOLAS KALDOR, AN EXPENDITURE TAX (1955). 143. See generally William D. Andrews, A Consumption-Type or Cash Flow Personal Income Tax, 87 HARV. L. REV. 1113 (1974). 144. Ogden L. Mills, The Spendings Tax, 7 NAT’L TAX ASS’N BULL. 18 (1921).
26
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
during the year, which it would have computed by requiring taxpayers to report on the following information: (1) Cash or equivalent assets on hand at the beginning of the taxable year ; (2) Total receipts including amounts borrowed ; (3) The amounts of the items exempt from taxation [i.e., deductible], including investments ; (4) Cash or equivalent assets at the close of the taxable year. 145
With Ogden Mills’ proposal retaining its status as a known though untested alternative as of the late 1930s, debate concerning its merits took on an odd form. Based on an argument that went back at least to John Stuart Mill, 146 Fisher asserted that such a tax not only was both feasible and desirable, but was actually the true form of an “income tax.” In Fisher’s view, an income tax, as conventionally defined to include both consumption and returns to saving, involves the “fallacy of double counting,” because it applies twice to assets’ capitalized value—first when they are received, and then again when they generate annual consumption or cash returns. “[S]avings may be invested in land or in confectionery. The only true income is the use of the land or the use of the confectionery. To include also the value of the land or the value of the confectionary is to count as income the capitalization of income.” 147 Thus, taxing returns to saving was not merely a bad policy idea (although it might be that as well, if it reduced saving). In addition, Fisher viewed it as actively fallacious, reflecting the “confusions” 148 promulgated by sloppy writers. Simons’ response to Fisher is partly semantic, reflecting the character of Fisher’s own argument. He calls his disagreement with Fisher “essentially one of terminology rather than of logic.” 149 While the question of how to define a given term is “only that of choice among verbal symbols . . . , it seems a hardly debatable proposition that usage is already too firmly established to permit our accepting Fisher’s proposal”150 regarding what “income” actually means. “His proposal comes all too tardily in the history of our language; and his pleas 145. Id. at 19-20. Items that were effectively deductible included not only most investment outlays, but also ordinary and necessary business expenses, other taxes paid, charitable gifts, amounts paid for medical and dental services, and funeral expenses. Id. at 19. For examples that mention the Mills bill, see Irving Fisher, The Double Taxation of Savings, 29 AM. ECON. REV. 16, 16-17 (1939), and SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 226. 146. See John Stuart Mill, PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY bk. V, ch. 2, § 4 (Donald Winch ed., Pelican Books 1970) (1848), quoted in Fisher, supra note 145, at 16 (arguing that “[u]nless . . . savings are exempted from income-tax, the contributors are twice taxed on what they save”). 147. IRVING FISHER, THE NATURE OF CAPITAL AND INCOME 108-09 (1906). 148. Id. at 107. 149. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 89. 150. Id. at 98.
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
27
have been, and must be, without effect upon our courts, legislatures, accountants, and men of affairs—not to mention the economists.” 151 The disagreement was not just semantic, however. Simons was fundamentally unsympathetic to the line of thought that had led Fisher down his semantic blind alley. As Simons notes, the real intellectual value of Fisher’s work on income and capital lay in his development of time-preference theory, which treats saving as merely deferred consumption. 152 Once one accepts this view of saving, it becomes clear that taxing returns to saving means that future consumption is being taxed at a higher rate than current consumption (all else equal), which may appear unmotivated. And if it is unmotivated, one may conclude that consumption is a better tax base than income, resulting not just in less economic distortion but also in better measurement of people’s relative “ability” or “ability to pay.” 153 Simons, however, believed that “there is something sadly inadequate about the idea of saving as [merely] postponed consumption.” 154 “Many people save mainly because it is the thing to do, because it is expected of them.” 155 And—echoing his denunciation of utility-based theories in other contexts—“[t]o assert that considerations of utility determine the allocation of consumption funds [over time] explains nothing at all but merely says, with egregious extravagance of language, that people consume what they consume.” 156 Accordingly, in his view, two people with the same income make a better horizontal comparison than two people with the same consumption, and the former pair is thus the one whose members should presumptively be equated through the choice of tax base.157 151. Id. (footnote omitted). 152. See id. at 95. 153. See, e.g., DAVID F. BRADFORD & U.S. TREASURY TAX POLICY STAFF, BLUEPRINTS FOR BASIC TAX REFORM 2, 37 (2d rev. ed. 1984); Joseph Bankman & David A. Weisbach, The Superiority of an Ideal Consumption Tax Over an Ideal Income Tax, 58 STAN. L. REV. 1413 (2006). 154. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 97. 155. Id. at 96-97. 156. Id. at 95. Although perhaps not germane here, I have explained elsewhere why I regard Simons’ position on this issue, which is commonly expressed to this day, as itself fallacious. The value of wealth lies in the fact that it can be used to buy things. Accordingly, under a perpetual flat rate consumption tax, one has already borne the full burden of the tax with respect to one’s unconsumed wealth. The fact that it can be spent is what gives it value. “Wealth is worth only what it can buy; otherwise, it might as well be play money from the board games Monopoly or Life.” Daniel N. Shaviro, Replacing the Income Tax With a Progressive Consumption Tax, 103 TAX NOTES 91, 105 (2004). Treating saving as deferred consumption therefore correctly reflects the fact that we have no particular reason to think savers are better off on a lifetime basis than consumers, unless we mean to rely on specific empirical theories regarding people’s behavior and welfare. 157. Under a view of saving as deferred consumption, if A and B earn the same wage this year and the tax base is consumption (with a perpetual flat rate), they pay the same taxes, in present value over the long run, even if this year one of them consumes less and
28
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
As a matter of logic, then, Simons preferred income taxation to consumption taxation. Perhaps the most important motivation, however, lay in his underlying distributional concerns. Because economic income includes, not just current year consumption, but also the amount of any increase in the market value of one’s assets during the year, it offers a “more inclusive measure of economic power” 158 than does consumption. And economic power was the very thing that he wanted the tax system to equalize. So what, he argued, if—as he expressly agreed—to save the preponderance of a large income was “moral[ly] superior[]” to engaging in “vulgar and tasteless ostentation in private consumption”? 159 While “[o]ur private sentiments may properly distinguish between better and worse uses of great economic power,”160 tax policy should take no heed of the difference. [T]here is an urgent social and political problem of preventing excessive and persisting inequality of power. . . . [T]hese distinctions should not blind us to the need for mitigating inequality or to the danger that our efforts in this direction will miscarry if we attempt to differentiate greatly among persons according to the way in which they use their power.” 161
A last reason for Simons’ preferring the income tax to Fisher’s and Ogden Mills’ spendings (i.e., progressive consumption) tax was administrative. The income tax was in current use and working reasonably well, albeit susceptible to significant improvement. “Fisher is urging us to abandon the best part of an established revenue system and to start anew with an untried form of personal tax.” 162 Departing radically from existing (and income-based) business accounting and creating a need, among other challenges, to measure taxpayers’ dissaving (such as from borrowing) was asking for trouble and might prove unworkable. 163 What is more, while Simons understood that the spendings tax could achieve “the same degree of progression that we now have, or the same amount of taxes on persons of great wealth,” this might require imposing high-end marginal tax rates as high as 1000%. 164 This seemed likely to be politically unfeasible and would, in any event, increase compliance problems. 165 saves more. Thus, support for consumption taxation does not rely on the claim that two people who consume the same amount this year should bear the same tax burden, even if one of them has greater savings. 158. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 229. 159. Id. 160. Id. 161. Id. 162. Id. at 226. 163. See id. at 227-28. 164. Id. at 230. 165. Id.
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
29
In sum, the picture so far appears clear. Simons was on the income tax side of the long-standing debate and seemingly considered it important to tax wealth-holders on their returns to saving. The case is apparently closed, and with a conclusion as unsurprising as that in the banal headline “Dog Bites Man.” Surely everyone in the tax community who has heard of Simons already knew that he was a strong income tax proponent. A surprise emerges, however, when one turns to the details of his tax reform views. Simons was actually quite comfortable with letting savers defer their income tax liabilities without penalty, so long as the deferral was not potentially permanent, and thereby embraced an end result that looks very similar to that under consumption taxation, so long as one specifies (as he did) that making gifts and bequests is itself a form of consumption. I show this next by examining how he dealt with the realization requirement, under which gain and loss are not taxed prior to the occurrence of a realization event, such as an asset sale. 2. Simons’ View of Realization and Deferral As Simons well understood, an income tax in name may not function much like one in practice if taxpayers can take sufficient advantage of a realization-based system. Current law, for example, might permit a “very wealthy diversifying ‘operator’ . . . [to] show little or no taxable income at all, while living like a king and steadily increasing his net worth.” 166 All that this required was selectively realizing losses and not gains, while borrowing as needed to fund current consumption. The deferred tax liability would then disappear at death, given the allowance at that point of a tax-free step-up in basis.167 While realization can turn the income tax into something that functions more like a consumption tax, in the above scenario we do not even have that. Blocking exploitation of the scenario may therefore be crucial to the effectiveness of the income tax (in name) as either a true income tax or an effective consumption tax, so far as highend progressivity is concerned. And if one prefers the income tax approach, as Simons emphasized that he did, one might be expected to emphasize as well the importance of limiting the deferral, not just the permanent elimination, of the tax on unrealized gain. Our priors here might therefore lead us to predict that Simons would want to address and limit taxpayers’ use of realization for deferral, and not just for permanent elimination of gain. This, however, is not at all what we find when we look closely at Personal Income Taxation and Federal Tax Reform. 166. SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 62. 167. Id.
30
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
Simons is remembered as a foe of realization doctrine for several reasons. One is that the Haig-Simons income definition gives realization absolutely no place. Changes in the market value of one’s assets are economic income, as the definition makes clear, whether one sells the assets or not. Simons also notably called financial accounting’s reliance on realization a “professional conspiracy against truth,” albeit one that might be expedient “in a world of corruptible accountants and optimistic directors.” 168 And he famously executed a brutally effective intellectual takedown 169 of Edwin R. A. Seligman of Columbia University for incoherently arguing that realization is a conceptually necessary component of income. 170 Seligman was Simons’ elder by thirty-eight years and arguably had been the preeminent U.S. tax economist since before Simons was born. 171 168. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 81. 169. See id. at 85-88. Simons’ critique of Seligman is remarkably sarcastic and dismissive. Seligman assumes what he needs to in order to supply the end result he wants, “then moves merrily to his conclusion.” Id. at 85. “[H]e has evidently no misgivings as to the finality of his [in Simons’ view, ad hoc and incoherent] contribution.” Id. He starts by defining income as consumption, but “[b]efore long . . . income becomes something more familiar—savings being slipped in quite unceremoniously.” Id. At one point in Seligman’s argument, “income” depends on value, but soon enough this “ceases to be true.” Id. at 86. A periodicity requirement for income is “essential” at two points in Seligman’s argument, but at another point “is excluded utterly.” Id. “Seligman’s differentiation between the growth of a herd and the growth of a forest is one of the less obscure features of his argument.” Id. Later on, “[i]ncome depends on the number of trees cut—but only provided they do not cut too many!” Id. at 87. “After an extended parade of dogmatic assertions—put forward as necessities of logic—the author [adds yet another extraneous argument] . . . rather casually.” Id. “Professor Seligman’s insistence both upon ‘realization’ and upon depreciation deductions seems to involve serious logical difficulties.” Id. at 88. “Of course, it goes without saying that, after dragging in an amazing variety of income concepts and choosing useful attributes from different ones at will, Seligman finds little difficulty in throwing out an item like stock dividends, which was almost defenseless from the start.” Id. 170. The Seligman article to which Simons gave this harsh treatment was Edwin R.A. Seligman, Are Stock Dividends Income?, 9 AM. ECON. REV. 517 (1919), from which the opinion of the Supreme Court in Eisner v. Macomber, 252 U.S. 189 (1920), holding that stock dividends cannot constitutionally be taxed because they fail a realization prerequisite for finding taxable income, had largely been cribbed. Simons was not the only tax academic to be unimpressed by Seligman’s analysis. See, e.g., Robert Murray Haig, The Concept of Income—Economic and Legal Aspects, in THE FEDERAL INCOME TAX 1 (Robert Murray Haig ed., 1921) (describing cases such as Eisner as “leading toward a definition of income so narrow and artificial as to bring about results which from the economic point of view are certainly eccentric and in certain cases little less than absurd”); Paul H. Wueller, Concepts of Taxable Income II, 53 POL. SCI. Q. 557, 564 (1938) (Seligman’s “concepts of income are, in the last analysis, but philological derivatives—without acknowledged social purpose.”). 171. Seligman was born in 1861, started at Columbia in 1885, published two major books on taxation in the 1890s, was the president of the American Economic Association from 1902 through 1904, and became a chaired Professor of Political Economy at Columbia in 1904. He then continued publish regularly through 1932. See Ajay K. Mehrotra, Edwin R.A. Seligman and the Beginnings of the U.S. Income Tax, 109 TAX NOTES 933, 936-38 (2005). Simons clearly saw no need to pull punches with an eminent senior member of his field, whose influence he obviously thought had lasted long enough.
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
31
In practice, however, Simons was comfortable with taxpayers’ use of realization accounting to defer gain. It is not just that he considered realization “indispensable to a feasible income-tax system” 172 and opposed departing from it selectively even where this was most feasible, such as under an early proposal to require annual mark-tomarket accounting for publicly traded securities.173 What is more, he considered realization “relatively unobjectionable in principle where it results only in postponement of assessment” rather than its permanent elimination. 174 Annual accrual of gain, while “implied by the underlying definition of income . . . is quite unnecessary to effective application of that definition.” 175 He even called the argument that income must be allocated to the right period, in order to eliminate the “interest saving” from deferral, “this mosquito argument,” at which he had “several times swatted . . . [and] must now swat once more, [albeit] not to kill the pest.” 176 Part of the reason for Simons’ impatience with arguments that income must be allocated to the right period, rather than being deferred under the realization rule, was simply his general conviction that the best should not be the enemy of the good. A reasonably wellfunctioning system should be considered entirely acceptable, even if along the way it posed insoluble (or, in his words, “hopeless”) dilemmas that could only be given “arbitrary” solutions. 177 However, he did not consider the time value of deferral—in an era when interest rates were low, by the standards of more recent decades—as merely something that one would like to eliminate, but that in practice was too small to worry about. Instead, in many circumstances he was actually affirmatively reluctant to deny it to taxpayers. Simons recognized, for example, that “long postponement of tax payment” can have a significant “interest cost to the Treasury.” 178 Nonetheless, allowing such postponement to businesses would yield “some gains, even to the Treasury, in allowing capital so to ‘fructify.’ The interest loss seems a moderate price to pay, not only for simple tax procedure but also for stimulation of new enterprise and venturesome investment . . . .” 179 Indeed, there was “very much to be said for not forcing unproved enterprises to deplete their reinvestable earnings or reserves by forcing them to pay taxes,” even indirectly via a 172. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 162. 173. SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 74. 174. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 162. 175. Id. at 208. 176. SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 127. 177. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 53-54 (discussing problems of imputed income and of drawing a firm boundary between business expenses and personal consumption). 178. SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 127. 179. Id.
32
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
shareholder-level tax that would lead to increased dividend payouts.180 Simons argued that this “scheme really does derive sound support from much the same argument which Professor Fisher has used, persuasively but (I think) improperly, to condemn the income tax.” 181 This perspective, under which the mere deferral of gain was unobjectionable so long as it did not turn into permanent exclusion, pervasively influences Simons’ actual reform proposals. As Aaron Director noted in his introduction to the posthumously published Federal Tax Reform, Simons’ “great contribution” to income tax thinking was to propose what he called “constructive realization.” 182 Under this approach, “[e]very transfer of property by gift, inheritance or bequest [w]ould be treated as a realization, at the estimated fair market value, by the donor or by the deceased owner’s estate.” 183 This tax would be levied in addition to treating gifts as taxable income to the donee while retaining their non-deductibility by the donor—a result that Simons defended on the ground that gifts constituted consumption by both parties.184 So long as constructive realization guaranteed a final accounting when the taxpayer ceased to own appreciated property, Simons not only could tolerate, but affirmatively supported, eliminating the corporate tax.185 The fact that corporate shareholders could thereby earn income that was free of any current tax was not a problem, so long as there was corporate-level dividend withholding plus a guarantee that any transfer of the underlying stock, including by gift or bequest, would be treated as a realization by the shareholder, with the gain being taxed at the ordinary income rate (and preferably subject to averaging, so taxpayers would not be adversely affected by the “bunching” problem if annual rates were steeply graduated). 186 How could Simons be so casual, ambivalent, and even selfcontradictory regarding whether income’s broader tax base than consumption (as he saw it) was actually reached in practice? The answer probably goes back to his underlying motivation for viewing tax reform as a vital part of his “laissez-faire program.” At the time when 180. Id. at 128. 181. Id. 182. Id. at vii. 183. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 167. 184. See id. at 57-58. Simons dismissed the critique that this would result in doublecounting on the ground that this critique “implies . . . the familiar, and disastrous, misconception that personal income is merely a share in some undistributed, separately measurable whole.” Id. at 58. He further argued that a gift exclusion unwisely “distinguish[es] among an individual’s receipts according to the intentions of second parties.” Id. at 57. 185. See, e.g., SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 16, 23, 40. 186. Id. at 40, 44.
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
33
he wrote, the U.S. income tax contributed less than 10% of all federal revenues,187 with the rest coming from tariffs and excise taxes that he abhorred as both anti-free market and regressive. Replacing them with a broad-based and relatively neutral levy that reflected individuals’ overall personal circumstances was the big thing, with the exact details being considerably less important. What is more, Simons’ broader macroeconomic interests (and his experience of the Great Depression) appear to have encouraged him to focus more on savings and growth, as opposed to just internal tax policy analysis, than if he had been purely a tax scholar, and one who lived in less interesting times. 3. What Might Simons Think Today About the Choice Between Income and Consumption Taxation? Given Simons’ surprising degree of comfort with employing an income tax by name that, in practice, often followed timing rules that were at least as favorable to taxpayers as those under a consumption tax, it is natural to ask, if only out of curiosity or as a kind of parlor game, what he might think about the choice of tax base today. Or more precisely, without speculating about such imponderable questions as whether he would have been swayed by intellectual developments and fashions in the field that he never lived to see, one can ask what, given his views, he might have made of our many subsequent decades of practical experience. Overall, I see two reasons why he might have been more fervently pro-income tax in practice today than he was back then, and two reasons why he might have shifted to favoring a progressive consumption tax. (a) More Pro-Income Tax? (1) Importance of timing. The first reason why Simons might have become more eager to impose a true income tax, in the sense of limiting interest-free deferral, is that the decades since he published Personal Income Taxation and Federal Tax Reform have taught us how much timing matters. Perhaps this is simply because we have frequently lived with higher interest rates than those of his era, and thus have gotten to observe how pervasively timing issues can dominate income tax practice and lead to economic distortions. 188 As William Andrews put it, we have learned that realization is often the 187. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 39. 188. On the other hand, with today’s generally lower tax rates than those in the 1930s, the distinction between pre-tax and after-tax rates of return may be narrower. One way of describing the key advantage of deferral is that it enables one to enjoy returns to saving at the pre-tax rather than the after-tax rate of return.
34
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
“Achilles’ heel” of the income tax, 189 and not just because Simons’ constructive realization approach has never been adopted. Today, income tax proponents generally recognize that it is quite important to their goals that deferral issues be addressed more aggressively than he thought was necessary. Thus, for example, few would argue today that we can simply eliminate the corporate income tax while still imposing such a tax at the individual level, serene in the knowledge that a given shareholder’s slice of corporate income might often fail to be taxed before that shareholder died. (2) Greatly increased high-end inequality. Over the last thirty years, high-end income inequality in the U.S. has vastly increased. Between 1986 and 2008, for example, under one relevant measure the share of national income earned by the top 1% of the income distribution almost doubled, while the income share of the top 0.01% more than tripled.190 Unsurprisingly, and as Simons would have predicted, increased economic inequality has affected the distribution of political power. In the last few years, we have seen the greatest and most sustained collapse of employment levels since the Great Depression prompt startlingly little concern from Washington policymakers. Instead, the concern of people in business and finance about forestalling even the remotest threat of modest inflation appears to matter a lot more politically. Likewise, consider the spectacle in the 2012 presidential campaign of billionaire donors, set free from campaign finance restrictions by the Supreme Court’s Citizens United decision,191 giving millions of dollars to support their favored candidates and causes in apparent exchange for access and at least hoped-for influence. It is not just anachronistic projection to posit that all this would have disgusted, and even enraged, the Henry Simons who wrote in the 1930s and 1940s. He viewed concentrated economic and political power as ugly and offensive, and he thought no group, profession, or class should be allowed too much superiority or sway in either realm. Thus, he presumably would have wanted to take strong measures to address high-end inequality. At least when he wrote, the income tax, along with the estate and gift tax, was the main policy tool that he considered suitable for this purpose. His concern that a spendings tax would not be progressive enough in practice, even if in principle it 189. See William D. Andrews, The Achilles’ Heel of the Comprehensive Income Tax, in NEW DIRECTIONS IN FEDERAL TAX POLICY FOR THE 1980S, at 278 (Charles E. Walker & Mark A. Bloomfield eds., 1983). 190. See Daniel N. Shaviro, 1986-Style Tax Reform: A Good Idea Whose Time Has Passed, 131 TAX NOTES 817, 834 (2011) (summarizing research by Facundo Alvaredo, Tony Atkinson, Thomas Piketty, and Emmanuel Saez). 191. Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 558 U.S. 310, 365-66 (2010).
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
35
could be, would surely have remained relevant to his analysis of the choice of policy tool. (b) Potentially Pro-Consumption Tax? (1) Political difficulty of addressing inter-asset distortions. I posited above that the clearly demonstrated importance of timing issues over the last few decades might have motivated Simons to support fuller implementation of a true Haig-Simons income tax. It also is possible, however, that it would move him in the opposite direction, by demonstrating that the income tax could not be as politically pure and economically neutral as he had fondly hoped. Even by the early 1940s, he was worrying that the federal income tax “reads less and less like a prescription of taxes on persons according to their incomes, and more and more like an inventory of miscellaneous dispensations” to well-connected interest groups. 192 This introduction of “in rem elements,” like those in excise taxes, was an instance of “concealed democratic corruption,” exemplified at the time by the oil depletion allowance. 193 Simons favored tax policy transparency 194 and might reasonably have concluded (as others have) that an income tax inherently lacks this virtue with respect to cost-recovery methods that are neutral between assets or industries. By contrast, in a cash-flow tax that applies to businesses (whether incorporated or not) as well as directly to individuals, expensing achieves inter-asset neutrality by relatively simple and transparent means. He thus might reasonably have asked himself the question of whether shifting to a cash-flow consumption tax might lead to greater neutrality and transparency, thereby reducing industry groups’ capacity to hijack economic and regulatory policy. As I have argued elsewhere,195 it is far from certain that shifting to a cash-flow consumption tax would actually improve political outcomes, but the possibility that it would (by reason of uniform expensing’s simplicity) would certainly have merited Simons’ consideration. (2) Administrative complexity of the income tax. A second reason why Simons might consider giving up on the income tax, if he saw where we are today, concerns its tax planning, compliance, and administrative costs. The baroque complexities of modern practice, founded in large part on realization problems that matter much more 192. SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 96. 193. Id. 194. See id. at 4-5. 195. See, e.g., Daniel Shaviro, Simplifying Assumptions: How Might the Politics of Consumption Tax Reform Affect (Impair) the End Product?, in FUNDAMENTAL TAX REFORM: ISSUES, CHOICES, AND IMPLICATIONS 75, 75-76 (John W. Diamond & George R. Zodrow eds., 2008).
36
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
than he had anticipated given the frequent existence of higher interest rates (along with the continuing non-adoption of his constructive realization idea), might conceivably move him to consider progressive consumption tax prototypes, even though they remain largely untested. One set of issues that Simons did not and could not have fully anticipated in the 1930s concerns the extraordinary growth, since that era, of aggressive tax sheltering transactions and legal responses thereto, the latter involving both expansive judicial doctrines 196 and detailed statutory enactments.197 A second set of issues that he did anticipate, but that arguably has grown worse, concerns entity-level corporate income taxation, which most analysts now agree (contrary to his view) is necessary if one taxes income rather than consumption at the individual level. Simons detested the impact of income tax considerations on companies’ business planning and also on their financial structure. His Federal Tax Reform emphasizes the undesirability of the corporate income tax system’s bias in favor of debt over equity. 198 And while debt bias is not inevitable under a corporate income tax, as decades of diverse “corporate integration” proposals have shown, 199 the very fact that none have been enacted may add to the appeal of a “Gordian knot” solution, in the form of eliminating the need to tax income at the entity level. International tax considerations arguably weigh in this direction as well. The rise of international business transactions, along with capital flows that facilitate income-shifting for tax purposes in the decades since Simons wrote, may cause longstanding problems with the international tax rules to be ever more damaging to the cause of taxing individuals on the income they earn through corporate entities. With a corporate income tax, in which residence determinations must be made at the entity rather than the individual level, these problems inevitably lack good solutions. 200 196. The economic substance doctrine that lies at the core of judicial responses to aggressive tax planning predates the publication of Simons’ Personal Income Taxation. See Gregory v. Helvering, 293 U.S. 465 (1935). However, Gregory concerned not the creation of artificial tax losses, but the use of a tax-free reorganization rule to reduce greatly the tax imposed on a corporate distribution. Id. at 468-70. Simons noted the “awful complexity” of the corporate reorganization rules and attributed it to what he considered the mistake of taxing corporations as if they were natural persons. SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 89-90. 197. Detailed statutory responses to tax sheltering in the current tax code include, for example, the investment interest limitation, the at-risk rules, and the passive loss rules. See I.R.C. §§ 163(d), 465, 469. The economic substance doctrine was also recently codified. See id. § 7701(o). 198. See SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 4, 19, 26. 199. On the variety of leading corporate integration proposals, see, for example, DANIEL N. SHAVIRO, DECODING THE U.S. CORPORATE TAX 151-65 (2009). 200. See generally DANIEL N. SHAVIRO, FIXING U.S. INTERNATIONAL TAXATION (2014).
2013]
THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS
37
While income taxation surely looks worse administratively than it did when Simons was writing, progressive consumption taxation looks somewhat better. Ogden Mills’ spendings tax was fairly rudimentary in design and in its degree of specification. Its lineal descendant, the “Blueprints” cash flow that David Bradford and the U.S. Treasury Tax Policy Staff developed in the 1980s,201 goes considerably further in showing how such an approach might work. It also contains a tax rate-smoothing or income averaging feature 202 that Simons might conceivably have liked, given his belief that this is important. 203 The decades since Simons wrote have also seen the promulgation of an alternative approach to progressive consumption taxation: Bradford’s X-tax, which builds administratively on the rise (since the 1950s) of value-added taxes that tax consumption relatively simply and efficiently through broad-based taxes that are collected at the company level.204 While these progressive consumption tax models remain largely untested, clearly the consumption tax side of the administrability debate has gained ground today relative to when Simons was writing. Obviously, one cannot, in the end, really say what Simons would think today about the choice of tax base if he were miraculously revived and apprised of the last few decades’ main developments. He surely would, however, be disappointed by the trajectory of the income tax in recent decades. It thus is plausible that he would be open to considering whether a progressive consumption tax could both do much better administratively and sufficiently match the actual progressivity of the existing income tax. If one had a definite answer to these questions, not only Simons’ choice, but also ours, would likely be a lot easier and clearer. V. CONCLUSION The Henry Simons who called himself an “extreme conservative” and foe of economic regulation, and the Henry Simons who favored “drastic progression” in the income tax, were one and the same intellectually, not just biologically. They shared a dislike for concentrated economic and political power, and a view of liberty and equality as not just comparably important, but also highly interdependent in practice. In his view, unlike that of many of today’s libertarians and 201. See BRADFORD & U.S. TREASURY TAX POLICY STAFF, supra note 153. 202. See id. at 44. 203. See SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 40, 127. 204. The X-tax combines a value-added tax with allowing businesses to deduct wages, which are taxed to workers under a progressive rate structure. See ROBERT CARROLL & ALAN D. VIARD, PROGRESSIVE CONSUMPTION TAXATION: THE X TAX REVISITED (2012); David F. Bradford, The X Tax in the World Economy (Nat’l Bureau Econ. Research, Working Paper No. w10676, 2004).
38
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:1
free market advocates, a plutocratic society would be unappealing even if everyone’s legal rights were formally inviolate. It is an interesting question—grist for a number of recent studies 205—why his concern about economic as well as political power, and his view that “[f]reedom without power . . . has no substance or meaning,” 206 have faded as much as they have among his successors in the classical liberal tradition. Intellectual history moves inexorably forward, reflecting not just fashion but new information and improved understanding. Thus, to my mind (although others may disagree), neither Simons’ scorn for theories based on utility and/or ability, nor his analysis of the choice between income and consumption taxation, is persuasive today. His hatred of all hierarchies, while appealing to me emotionally, needs a fuller intellectual foundation than he offers. And his broader economic analysis, such as that concerning the dangers of monopoly power, may in some respects be more dated still. Even seventy years down the road, however, much of Simons’ work remains compelling, lucid, and persuasive. This is no small accomplishment. His brilliance, vehemence, and urgent commitment to improving the world in which he lived helped motivate him to produce, not just a few instances of inspired advocacy, but substantial contributions both to income tax scholarship and to the intellectual and institutional foundations of modern law and economics. I only wish that, in some imaginary place, I could adequately praise and thank him to his face—perhaps over a beer at Hanley’s tavern in the twilight zone as Walter Blum looks on with a benign half-smile, and even Ronald Coase, persuaded at last to accept the value of Simons’ contributions, nods approvingly.
205. See, e.g., DANIEL STEDMAN JONES, MASTERS OF THE UNIVERSE: HAYEK, FRIEDMAN, BIRTH OF NEOLIBERAL POLITICS (2012); Caldwell, supra note 15; DeLong, supra note 97; Kasper, supra note 23; Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15. 206. SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 6. AND THE
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS STEVEN A. BANK ∗ I. INTRODUCTION.................................................................................................. II. ORIGINS ............................................................................................................ A. 1909............................................................................................................ B. 1913–1921 .................................................................................................. C. 1921–1934 .................................................................................................. D. 1935–1936 .................................................................................................. III. EVOLUTION ....................................................................................................... IV. FUTURE .............................................................................................................
39 42 42 45 48 53 59 65
I. INTRODUCTION One of the more anomalous structural features of the corporate income tax is the dividends received deduction, 1 which permits a corporation to deduct from income an amount equal to some or all of the dividends it receives in its capacity as a shareholder of another domestic corporation. At first glance, the provision seems to be justified by the general sentiment against taxing corporate income more than twice. If this is the explanation, however, the dividends received deduction is underinclusive because some intercorporate dividends are only partially deductible. As currently drafted, the amount of the deduction is based on the degree of a shareholder’s control. Dividends are completely (100%) exempt if a corporate shareholder owns at least 80% of the distributing corporation,2 80% exempt if the ownership interest is less than 80% but at least 20%, and 70% exempt if the ownership interest is less than 20%. 3 If avoiding triple (or more) taxation was the rationale, it is not clear why all intercorporate dividends would not be completely exempt from further taxation. Given partial deductibility and the importance of degree of control, it is therefore natural to conclude that the dividends received deduction is less about a concern over multiple layers of taxation and more about substance-over-form concerns. In other words, it is about differentiating true dividends from distributions that are really just shifts in money from a corporation’s right pocket to its left pocket. If that is the explanation, however, the dividends received deduction is overinclusive because it applies to very small investments in another corporation where the distribution really does move money from one tax∗ Paul Hastings Professor of Business Law, UCLA School of Law. Thanks to Joe Bankman, Mirit Eyal-Cohen, Jim Hines, Sheldon Pollack, Clarissa Potter, Chris Sanchirico, Dan Shaviro, Larry Zelenak, and participants at the FSU Law Review Symposium commemorating the centennial of the federal income tax and the National Tax Association’s annual meeting for their helpful comments. 1. I.R.C. § 243. 2. See id. §§ 243(a)(3), (b), 1504(a)(2). 3. Id. § 243(a)(1), (c).
40
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
payer to an entirely different taxpayer. Thus, a corporation that owns a single share of stock in a large public corporation still can exclude 70% of the dividend from income. The incoherence of the current tax treatment of intercorporate dividends is a product of its historical development. As described by the few commentators who have examined the history of intercorporate dividends taxation to any extent, its origins can be traced back to the New Deal. 4 In the Revenue Act of 1935, 5 corporate income was for the first time subject to graduated marginal rates. In announcing the progressive rate scheme, President Franklin Delano Roosevelt noted that to prevent the evasion of the new graduated rates through the use of subsidiaries, each of which had income below the thresholds for the application of the higher rates, it would be necessary to impose a tax on intercorporate dividends. Intercorporate dividends went from being fully exempt to being only 90% exempt. In theory, this change was designed to discourage any attempts to evade the new graduated system. In reality, however, the additional effective tax burden was too small to be a significant deterrent in most cases given the alternative of having a corporation’s income subject to the top corporate rates. The underlying rationale for taxing intercorporate dividends was more about discouraging the formation and continued existence of certain large corporate groups, or “pyramids,” than it was about closing a loophole in the graduated rate scheme. The name for these controversial corporate structures derived from their multilevel corporate chains of ownership in which the investors at the top of the pyramid were able to leverage a relatively small investment in one corporation in order to exercise power and influence over a large group of subsidiaries at the bottom of the pyramid. As economist Randall Morck observed, this pyramidal structure was “believed to facilitate governance problems, tax avoidance, market power, and dangerously concentrated political influence.”6 Although the resulting tax burden from the introduction of intercorporate dividend taxation was too small to force an immediate change in organizational structures,7 it 4. See, e.g., David R. Francis, The Taxation of Intercorporate Dividends: Current Problems and Proposed Reforms, 64 TAXES 427, 430 (1986); George Mundstock, Taxation of Intercorporate Dividends Under an Unintegrated Regime, 44 TAX L. REV. 1, 9-10 (1988); Daniel C. Schaffer, The Income Tax on Intercorporate Dividends, 33 TAX LAW. 161, 163 (1979); Michael J. Maimone & G. Frank Riley III, Note, Taxation of Intercorporate Dividends: A Missed Opportunity for Tax Reform, 7 VA. TAX REV. 777, 779 (1988). 5. Revenue Act of 1935, Pub. L. No. 74-407, 49 Stat. 1014. 6. Randall Morck, How to Eliminate Pyramidal Business Groups: The Double Taxation of Intercorporate Dividends and Other Incisive Uses of Tax Policy, 19 TAX POL’Y & ECON. 135, 136 (2005). 7. See Steven A. Bank & Brian R. Cheffins, The Corporate Pyramid Fable, 84 BUS. HIST. REV. 435, 443-45 (2010) (finding in a study of SEC filings between 1936 and 1938 of
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
41
was part of a multifaceted campaign against corporate pyramids that included changes in tax laws, securities laws, and the enactment of the Public Utility Holding Company Act.8 Not only was the intercorporate dividends tax primarily about this campaign against pyramids, it was tied as much—or more—to a prior move to repeal the consolidated return. Formerly a requirement for corporate groups to prevent evasion of the war profits and excess profits taxes, 9 the consolidated return had become merely an option for affiliated corporations as of 1921. By 1932, however, growing concern about the use of holding companies had led Congress to consider reforms to make such structures less desirable. Initially, corporate groups had to pay a penalty tax to file a consolidated return, and then in 1934, the privilege was revoked entirely for most corporations. A companion proposal to tax intercorporate dividends, however, was narrowly defeated. The continued existence of the full exemption for intercorporate dividends after 1934 appeared to be an endrun around at least one aspect of the consolidated return repeal. In 1935 and 1936, Congress reduced the exemption for intercorporate dividends in order to bolster the concerted action against holding companies. This original rationale for the taxation of intercorporate dividends soon became unnecessary. Starting in the 1940s, concern about pyramidal structures lessened as reorganization began to occur under the Public Utility Holding Company Act, which had also been enacted in 1935. In 1942, the consolidated return privilege was revived, and all penalties were eliminated as of 1964. Consequently, Congress moved away from an intercorporate dividends tax and back toward the exemption concept that had existed prior to 1935.10 In the time since, however, the provision has neither returned to its roots nor fully embraced a scheme based on degree of control. In Part II, this Article examines the history of the tax treatment of intercorporate dividends, focusing on both the failed attempt to repeal the dividends received deduction in 1934 and then its reduction in 1935. Part III corporate shareholders owning more than 10% of the stock of another corporation that more than 80% of corporate shareholders remained unchanged, and of the corporate shareholders that changed their holdings, the number of purchases of increased shares virtually matched the number of sales). 8. Id. at 439, 448; Public Utility Holding Company Act of 1935, Pub. L. No. 74-333, 49 Stat. 803. 9. See infra text accompanying notes 36-40. 10. The use of the word “exemption” is a reference to the effect rather than the means of accomplishing that end. The partial or full exclusion of intercorporate dividends has sometimes been accomplished through an exemption, sometimes through a credit, and more commonly through a dividends received deduction. There is no clear explanation for the difference, but one commentator has suggested that it was a difference in “nomenclature only.” Mundstock, supra note 4, at 7 n.28.
42
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
describes the evolution of the dividends received deduction after the New Deal, taking special note of the changes in circumstances regarding the treatment of consolidated corporate groups. Finally, the Article concludes by discussing the possible future of the tax treatment of intercorporate dividends and the proposals that have been raised for its reform. II. ORIGINS A. 1909 The idea that a corporation could hold stock in another corporation was a relatively new phenomenon in America at the turn of the century. New Jersey was the first state to enact a statute broadly permitting corporate ownership of other corporations in 1889, and other states were slow to follow. 11 Even as late as 1916, Professor Maurice Wormser reported in his corporate law treatise that “it is generally held in this country that a corporation has no power to subscribe for or to purchase stock in another corporation, unless such power is expressly given in its charter or is reasonably implied in it.” 12 Otherwise, a corporation could bypass any charter restrictions on its purpose by purchasing stock in a corporation undertaking an unauthorized line of business. 13 Perhaps to get around such ultra vires objections, investors created the holding company. Wormser noted: In recent years there has come into existence a class of corporations known as holding companies. These corporations are organized exclusively for the purpose of acquiring and holding stock in other corporations. Their validity has been upheld in some states, including New York, but in others, notably Illinois, they have been condemned because of their tendency to create monopolies. 14
Critics of excessive business consolidation during the first decade of the twentieth century were especially concerned about the development of holding companies, which they viewed as an abusive stock 11. CHRISTOPHER GRANDY, NEW JERSEY AND THE FISCAL ORIGINS OF MODERN AMERICORPORATION LAW 42 (1993); CHARLES S. TIPPETTS & SHAW LIVERMORE, BUSINESS ORGANIZATION AND CONTROL: CORPORATIONS AND TRUSTS IN THE UNITED STATES 213 (1932). Prior to affording general statutory authority, some states permitted corporate stockholding under special charters or in statutes targeted at specific industries. WM. L. CLARK, JR., HANDBOOK OF THE LAW OF PRIVATE CORPORATIONS 183 (I. Maurice Wormser ed., 3d ed. 1916). For example, in 1853 New York granted telegraph companies the authority to own stock in other telegraph companies as part of a program to facilitate interstate telegraph holding companies. RONALD E. SEAVOY, THE ORIGINS OF THE AMERICAN BUSINESS CORPORATION, 1784-1855, at 198-99 (1982). 12. CLARK, supra note 11, at 183. 13. JAMES WILLARD HURST, THE LEGITIMACY OF THE BUSINESS CORPORATION IN THE LAW OF THE UNITED STATES 1780-1970, at 45 (1970). 14. CLARK, supra note 11, at 185. CAN
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
43
consolidation technique designed to evade the Sherman Antitrust Act. 15 By 1912, the Democratic Party platform specifically proposed to limit the ability of states to permit holding companies and interlocking directorates. 16 After the election, William C. Redfield, the Secretary of Commerce in President Woodrow Wilson’s new administration, publicly stated that corporations should “not hold stock in the competing companies, and that neither a person nor a corporation shall at the same time own a controlling interest in two or more competing corporations.” 17 Eventually, these statements led to a bill proposing to bar corporate acquisitions of stock in other corporations whenever “the effect of such acquisition may be to substantially lessen competition between the corporation whose stock is so acquired and the corporation making the acquisition, or to restrain such commerce . . . or to tend to create a monopoly.” 18 The Clayton Act, as the bill was called after passage in 1914, 19 was too ambiguously drafted to be viewed as a substantial impediment to holding companies, but it did reflect the prevailing sentiment against such structures in the pre-World War I era. 20 This controversy over corporate holding companies was looming during the debates over the 1909 corporate excise tax—often considered the forerunner of the modern corporate income tax because the amount due was a function of the corporation’s income. 21 The original bill introducing the excise tax included an exemption for dividends received from another corporation, 22 but this was attacked as a de facto tax exemption for corporate holding companies. During deliberations over the 1909 corporate excise tax, Insurgent Republican Senator Moses Clapp of Minnesota introduced a motion to repeal the exemption of dividends paid by corporate subsidiaries to their parent 15. HARLAND PRECHEL, BIG BUSINESS AND THE STATE: HISTORICAL TRANSITIONS AND CORPORATE TRANSFORMATION, 1880S-1990S, at 66 (2000). As Lawrence Mitchell has written, “[t]he trust structure was no longer a subterfuge. The holding company transformed it into a perfectly legal device.” LAWRENCE E. MITCHELL, THE SPECULATION ECONOMY 31 (2007). 16. PRECHEL, supra note 15, at 66. 17. Id. at 66-67 (citation omitted). 18. Id. at 68. 19. Id.; Clayton Act, Pub. L. No. 63-212, 38 Stat. 730 (1914). 20. PRECHEL, supra note 15, at 68. 21. Payne-Aldrich Tariff Act of Aug. 5, 1909, Pub. L. No. 61-5, § 38, 36 Stat. 11, 112. 22. In a carefully scripted exercise, the corporate excise tax was introduced in the Senate by Senate Finance Committee Chair Nelson Aldrich as an amendment to Senator Henry Cabot Lodge’s motion to substitute an inheritance tax for Democrat Joseph Bailey’s income tax bill. It was drafted by Senator Elihu Root and Attorney General George Wickersham under the close supervision of the President, and it was “carefully scrutinized” by the Senate Finance Committee as part of a campaign by the President to make the bill more likely to pass through Congress. ROY G. BLAKEY & GLADYS C. BLAKEY, THE FEDERAL INCOME TAX 45-47 (1940).
44
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
holding companies. 23 Clapp complained that the bill “permits the organization of holding companies and exempts such holding companies from any tax where their capital is invested in the stock of subordinate companies.” 24 Senator Nelson Aldrich, a Republican from Rhode Island, objected: No holding company or any other company is exempted . . . . This proposition simply, in the case of corporations which have paid the tax once and whose stock is held by another corporation, permits the second holding corporation or the corporation holding the stock to return an exemption on account of that first payment. In other words, it does not enforce double taxation upon these various corporations. Every corporation must pay the tax, and if it is paid once, this act says in effect it shall not from necessity be paid a second time. 25
Anti-holding company legislators used the words of the bill’s sponsors, which had been carefully drawn to avoid constitutional scrutiny after the Supreme Court struck down an income tax in Pollock 26 in response to such argument. New York Senator Elihu Root, one of the principal drafters of the corporate excise tax bill, had said earlier in the session that “it is not the profits that would be subject to the tax, but the privilege or facility of transacting the business through corporate form.” 27 Jonathan Dolliver, an Insurgent Republican from Iowa, recited that quote and went on to say: If, then, this is not an income tax, if it is not a tax on earnings, if it makes no difference where the money comes from that flows into the corporate treasury, on what theory are we, who sit here representing the American people, exempting from the burden of this tax not little corporations, because they can not afford to pay it, but great corporations, many of them grown so great that they trample under foot the laws of the United States, and have in some instances turned our Government itself into a farce through its impotency in dealing with their pretensions? 28
Clapp echoed Dolliver’s argument, noting that because this was an excise tax on the privilege of operating in corporate form, rather than a true income tax where double taxation might be a valid objection, “there can be no reason . . . why a great holding corporation, organized to buy a controlling interest in other corporations, should es23. 44 CONG. REC. 3877 (1909). 24. Id. at 4228. 25. Id. at 4231. 26. Pollock v. Farmers’ Loan & Trust Co., 158 U.S. 601, 635-37 (1895) (noting that the decision striking down the 1894 income tax as unconstitutional would not preclude imposing an excise tax on the privilege of doing business). 27. 44 CONG. REC. 4230 (1909). 28. Id.
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
45
cape any taxation for the privilege or right of being a corporation and engaging in the business of operating and dominating other corporations.” 29 After futile debate between Aldrich and several Insurgent Republicans over the issue, Aldrich announced he was going to accept the amendment in order to move on to the rest of the bill. 30 Proponents of Clapp’s proposal to tax intercorporate dividends suspected that Aldrich expected it “to be sacrificed in conference,” but Aldrich insisted he would carry forth the views of the majority. 31 As it turns out, the Insurgent Republicans were right to be suspicious of Aldrich’s motives because Clapp’s amendment was stricken during conference proceedings.32 When Representative Sereno Payne, a Standpatter Republican from the holding company-friendly state of New York, reported back to the House regarding the conference proceedings, he was asked why the exemption for intercorporate dividends was reinserted. 33 Payne responded that “[t]here is no reason in the world why a corporation that owns stock in another company should pay a double tax upon those holdings. It is not equitable, it is not right, and it ought not to be exacted. [Applause].” 34 Payne noted: When it comes to the breaking up or absorption of a company in order to get rid of competition by another company, I will go to the full length in preventing it; but I am not in favor of using the taxing power for that purpose, and, of course, a tax of 1 per cent would not accomplish any purpose in that respect. 35
Critics of the growing influence of holding companies assailed the result, declaring that “[t]his exemption of the giant concerns that draw enormous tribute from combinations of lesser companies is regarded by many as the most pernicious feature of the bill.” 36 B. 1913–1921 Notwithstanding the strong repudiation of intercorporate dividend taxation in 1909, the anti-holding company movement described earlier may have ultimately gotten the upper hand because the exemption for intercorporate dividends was not imported from the corporate excise tax when the first post-Sixteenth Amendment income tax was adopted in 1913. 37 Although unpopular among businesses, this was 29. 30. 31. 32. 33. 34. 35. 36. 37.
Id. at 4228. Id. at 4233. Id. BLAKEY & BLAKEY, supra note 22, at 49. 44 CONG. REC. 4696 (1909). Id. Id. Dividend Tax Now in Bill, LAFOLLETTE’S WKLY. MAG., July 31, 1909, at 14. Revenue Act of 1913, Pub. L. No. 63-16, § II, 38 Stat. 114, 116.
46
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
accepted in part because of the low stakes. As Columbia economist Edwin Seligman reported to the American Economic Association’s Committee on War Finances, “[t]his was possible, although unjustifiable, when the rate of the income tax was only 1 or 2 per cent.” 38 Once the U.S. entered World War I, the stakes increased and the tax treatment of intercorporate dividends became more intolerable for many businesses. With the corporate income tax rate tripling from 2% in 1913 to 6% in 1917, coupled with a 1916 levy that imposed a tax of fifty cents per $1000 of capital stock outstanding, which disproportionately affected corporate groups, some holding companies even considered reorganizing to lessen their burden. 39 In response, Congress in the War Revenue Act of 1917 adopted a tax credit for the receipt of intercorporate dividends. 40 This credit was merely partial relief, however, because it only covered the 4% surtax imposed under the Revenue Act of 1917 passed earlier in the year, and it did not cover the 2% tax that had been adopted in the 1916 Act. The Wall Street Journal noted that the intercorporate dividend tax credit, “commendable as it was, did not go far enough and resulted in much confusion.” 41 In 1918, Congress went the final step and permitted corporate shareholders to deduct the full amount of intercorporate dividends from income. 42 Seligman called it “simple justice,” with the deduction amounting to a complete exemption of the dividends. 43 This Congressional focus on the tax treatment of intercorporate dividends was part of a broader review of the taxation of corporate groups. Originally, affiliated corporations were not permitted to file a single, consolidated tax return that combined the profits and losses of each member of the group.44 All corporations were taxed separately on their own profits and losses, regardless of their common ownership and control. This may have disadvantaged some companies seeking to offset the gains of one member of the corporate group with the losses of another member, but as one businessman later noted, “[T]he rate of income tax on corporations was very slight, and it probably did not make very much difference one way or the other 38. Seligman Reports on War Finances, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 28, 1918, at 14. 39. See, e.g., New Taxation to Spur Corporate Reorganization, WALL ST. J., Oct. 21, 1916, at 5 (describing an announcement by Distillers Securities Corporation that it planned to merge all of its subsidiaries into its parent company to reduce its capital stock burden). 40. War Revenue Act of 1917, Pub. L. No. 65-50, § 4, 40 Stat. 300, 302. 41. Justice to Corporations Begins to Appear, WALL ST. J., May 14, 1918, at 10. 42. Revenue Act of 1918, Pub. L. No. 65-254, § 234(a)(6), 40 Stat. 1057, 1078 (1919). 43. Seligman Reports on War Finances, supra note 38, at 14. 44. Walter A. Staub, Consolidated Returns, in THE FEDERAL INCOME TAX 188 (Robert Murray Haig ed., 1921).
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
47
whether there was a consolidated return or a series of returns for the members of one business family.” 45 In 1917, the introduction of excess profits taxation made the separate entity approach more advantageous for some corporate taxpayers, at least with respect to the excess profits tax. Through intercompany charges between affiliated corporations, such as management fees or the price paid for items supplied by one company to the other, a corporate group could manipulate its profits so as to avoid or greatly minimize its exposure to the excess profits tax. Initially, the Treasury issued regulations authorizing the Commissioner of Internal Revenue to require consolidated excess profits tax returns “[w]henever necessary to more equitably determine the invested capital or taxable income.” 46 Congress followed up in the Revenue Act of 1918 by requiring consolidated income tax and excess profits tax returns for corporate groups in which at least 95% of the stock of each of the corporations within the group was owned by one or more of the other corporations in the group and a common parent corporation owned at least 95% of the stock of at least one member of the group.47 This was apparently welcomed by the business community, since even under the Treasury Regulations “most corporations identified themselves as eligible for consolidated filing and filed the consolidated return, probably because the resulting consolidated return reduced their tax.” 48 According to one report, 75% of all corporate tax collected in 1917 came from companies voluntarily filing consolidated returns. 49 Thus, although the move to require consolidated returns 45. Revenue Revision, 1934: Hearings Before the H. Comm. on Ways & Means, 73rd Cong. 523 (1934) [hereinafter 1934 House Hearings] (statement of John G. Buchanan, Armstrong Cork Co.). 46. Regs. 41, Art. 78, T.D. 2694, 20 Treas. Dec. Int. Rev. 294, 321 (1918). The authority for issuing this regulation was somewhat tenuous. One contemporary observer identified the authority as Section 201 of the Act of October 3, 1917, which provided: For the purpose of this title every corporation or partnership not exempt under the provisions of this section shall be deemed to be engaged in business, and all the trades and businesses in which it is engaged shall be treated as a single trade or business, and all its income from whatever source derived shall be deemed to be received from such trade or business. Staub, supra note 44, at 189. 47. Revenue Act of 1918, Pub. L. No. 65-254, § 240, 40 Stat. 1057, 1081-82 (1919). Although enacted in 1918, it was made retroactive to 1917. Edward H. Green, Aspects of the Problem of Income Taxation From the Standpoint of Corporations, 10 TAXES 441, 44344 (1932). 48. Jasper L. Cummings, Jr., Consolidating Foreign Affiliates, 11 FLA. TAX REV. 143, 172-73 (2011). Although the regulations were only meant to apply to certain groups of companies, the instructions to the excess profits tax return asked whether the return was a consolidated return, which Cummings speculates “may have indicated to taxpayers that filing a consolidated return was at their option.” Id. at 172. 49. Internal Revenue: Hearing on H.R. 8245 Before the S. Comm. on Fin., 67th Cong. 133 (1921) (statement of Professor T.S. Adams).
48
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
was initially prompted by concerns of excess profits tax evasion, the push for consolidated returns more generally was ultimately linked with Congress’ move to exempt intercorporate dividends from tax to avoid the punishing effects of the high wartime surtax rates. When the excess profits tax was ended under the Revenue Act of 1921, Congress made consolidated returns optional rather than mandatory, 50 but the exemption for intercorporate dividends remained. C. 1921–1934 In 1927, dissatisfaction with the consolidated return led the Joint Committee on Internal Revenue Taxation to recommend discontinuing consolidated returns. 51 Prompted by this recommendation, the House voted for the repeal of the privilege in 1928. 52 These moves, however, were primarily based on administrative rather than substantive concerns. Moreover, the Treasury worried that abolishing consolidated returns “would be a practical impossibility in view of the complexity of modern corporate business, and endless confusion in corporation tax administration would result.” 53 Ultimately, Congress rejected the repeal option and authorized the Treasury to issue new regulations to clarify the application and operation of the consolidated return. 54 Consolidated returns had survived, but not for very long. In 1932, Congress once again considered the issue of the propriety of permitting consolidated returns. In the House, Representative Clarence Cannon, a Democrat from Missouri, introduced an amendment to repeal the consolidated return privilege. 55 Rather than simply being a reprise of the administrative concerns that had prompted a similar proposal in the late 1920s, however, this repeal proposal was animated by concern about the evils of affiliated corporate groups such as corporate pyramids. 56 This focus on the evils of corporate pyramids and other affiliated organizational structures reflected a growing concern that these practices had played a central role during the 1920s in crowding out small competitors and concentrating wealth and power in the hands of a few. 57 The principal feature of the pyramidal structure was that 50. Revenue Act of 1921, Pub. L. No 67-98, §§ 240(a), 301, 42 Stat. 227, 260, 272. 51. Cummings, supra note 48, at 177-78. 52. Id. 53. Senate to Decide Fate of Tax Bill, WALL ST. J., Dec. 21, 1927, at 18. 54. Roy G. Blakey, The Revenue Act of 1928, 18 AM. ECON. REV. 429, 435-36 (1928); Robert N. Miller, The Taxation of Intercompany Income, 7 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 301, 306 (1940). 55. See, e.g., 75 CONG. REC. 7124 (1932) (statement of Rep. Cannon). 56. See infra text accompanying notes 61-62. 57. See, e.g., FREDERICK LEWIS ALLEN, THE LORDS OF CREATION 248 (1935) (“[I]f it
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
49
the owners could use a small investment to exert control over a vast empire. 58 In 1932, at the same time Congress was considering whether the use of consolidated returns was appropriate, Adolf Berle and Gardiner Means published their landmark work, The Modern Corporation and Private Property. 59 In this work, they explained that “[t]he owner of a majority of the stock of the company at the apex of a pyramid can have almost as complete control of the entire property as a sole owner even though his ownership interest is less than one per cent of the whole.” 60 One prominent example of this was the Van Swearingen brothers, who accumulated control of railroad corporations throughout the 1920s via investments by their Allegheny Corporation holding company. 61 According to Berle and Means, “[b]y this pyramid an investment of less than twenty million dollars has been able to control eight Class I railroads having combined assets of over two billion dollars.” 62 The presence of corporate pyramids was particularly pronounced in the public utility sector. One contemporary study of the period concluded that “[s]o great was the importance of pyramiding holding companies in the utilities industries in the decade from 1920 to 1930 that the terms ‘holding company’ and ‘public utility company’ became synonymous in the public mind.” 63 In the presidential campaign of 1932, Roosevelt promised to seek “[r]egulation and control of holding companies by Federal [P]ower [C]ommission and the same publicity with regard to such holding companies as provided for the operating companies.”64 Roosevelt declared that the failure of [t]he great Insull monstrosity, made up of a group of holding and investing companies and exercising control over hundreds of operating companies . . . has opened our eyes. It shows us that the development of these financial monstrosities was such as to compel had not been for the lavish use of this logical extension of the holding-company device, many of the giants of the economic world would never have got their growth.”). 58. Investors at the top of the pyramid used a variety of means to maintain control, including cascading holdings of bare majority ownerships, thin capitalization (with funds provided by preferred stock and debt), and multiple classes of stock (some of which are nonvoting). See JAMES C. BONBRIGHT & GARDINER C. MEANS, THE HOLDING COMPANY: ITS PUBLIC SIGNIFICANCE AND ITS REGULATION 147-48 (1932); WILLIAM Z. RIPLEY, MAIN STREET AND WALL STREET 317 (1927). 59. ADOLF A. BERLE, JR. & GARDINER C. MEANS, THE MODERN CORPORATION AND PRIVATE PROPERTY (1932). 60. Id. at 73. 61. See id. at 23; BONBRIGHT & MEANS, supra note 58, at 256, 259; RICHARD SAUNDERS, JR., MERGING LINES: AMERICAN RAILROADS 1900–1970, at 64 (2001). 62. BERLE & MEANS, supra note 59, at 73. 63. CHARLES S. TIPPETTS & SHAW LIVERMORE, BUSINESS ORGANIZATION AND PUBLIC CONTROL 184 (2d ed. 1941). 64. Text of Governor Roosevelt’s Speech at Portland, Oregon, on Public Utilities, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 22, 1932, at 16.
50
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
ultimate ruin, that practices had been indulged in that suggest the old days of railroad wild-catting, that private manipulation had outsmarted the slow-moving power of government. 65
The concern was that the consolidated return helped facilitate anticompetitive behavior by holding companies. According to Representative Cannon, the consolidated return “penalizes David and assists Goliath.”66 Cannon went on to note that the consolidated return is a favorite device of the utilities. An electric company or telephone branch or transportation company pays little attention to the cost of installing new services. A railroad company can run a bus line at a loss, a streetcar company can operate a line of taxicabs, or a power company can preempt a new community at a loss. Through the benevolent provisions of this law they charge these losses against their profits elsewhere and reduce their taxes while destroying competition and monopolizing the market. 67
Contemporary observers called the question of whether to repeal or severely tax consolidated returns “[o]ne of the hardest fought contests” during deliberations over the Revenue Act of 1932. 68 Acknowledging that “[t]he House is divided on this proposition,” Representative Charles Robert Crisp, a Democrat from Georgia, successfully persuaded his colleagues to adopt a compromise proposal to subject corporate groups to an additional 1.5% tax for the privilege of filing a consolidated return. 69 At the urging of Andrew Mellon’s replacement, Treasury Secretary Ogden Mills, 70 the Senate Finance Committee removed the penalty tax in the bill it reported on the Senate floor,71 but a compromise was reached in conference. Congress elected to subject corporate groups filing consolidated returns to an additional three-fourths of 1% tax for the privilege of filing such a return in 1932 and 1933, and 1% in 1934 and 1935.72 Supporters of repeal consoled themselves by noting that a penalty provision would test whether supporters of consolidated returns were correct as to their benefits. As House Speaker John Nance Garner—an advocate for repeal in 1928 and reportedly the behind-the-scenes leader of the 1932 65. James A. Hagerty, Portland Cheers Speech: The Governor Cites ‘Insull Monstrosity’ as He Hits ‘Interests,’ N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 22, 1932, at 1. 66. 75 CONG. REC. 7125 (1932). 67. Id. 68. Roy. G. Blakey & Gladys C. Blakey, The Revenue Act of 1932, 22 AM. ECON. REV. 620, 625 (1932). 69. 75 CONG. REC. 7126 (1932) (statement of Rep. Crisp). 70. Text of Secretary Mills’s Statement to Senate Finance Committee on Tax Bill, N.Y. TIMES, Apr. 7, 1932, at 20. 71. Blakey & Blakey, supra note 68, at 631; House’s Rates Increased, N.Y. TIMES, Apr. 28, 1932, at 1; Tax Bill Completed; Revised Throughout on Mills’s Pattern, N.Y. TIMES, May 7, 1932, at 1. 72. BLAKEY & BLAKEY, supra note 22, at 345.
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
51
repeal effort 73—noted, “[i]f it is advantageous to them to file such returns they will pay the penalty. If there is no advantage in consolidated and affiliated returns, they will submit separate returns.” 74 Thus, as part of a general increase in the corporate income tax rate from 12% to 13.75%, the rate for affiliated corporations filing a consolidated return was increased to 14.5% for 1932 and 1933. 75 In 1933, the consolidated return issue was revisited. A subcommittee of the Ways and Means Committee issued a report on the prevention of tax avoidance in which it revived the earlier proposals of the Joint Committee on Taxation and the Ways and Means Committee to repeal the consolidated return. 76 According to the report, the primary impetus for addressing the consolidated return was the repeal under the National Industrial Recovery Act of the ability to carry forward net operating losses from one year to the next. The Subcommittee noted: In the past, when any corporation could carry forward a net loss from one year to another, the consolidated group did not have such a great advantage over the separate corporation. Now that this net-loss carry-over has been denied, the advantage of the consolidated return is much greater on a comparative basis. 77
Commentators immediately assailed this recommendation as imprudent and unfairly penalizing most businesses for the abuses of a few. Godfrey Nelson of the New York Times noted that “[e]xisting law in respect of the filing of consolidated returns by affiliated corporations is amply justified on the ground of sound business practice and should be retained.” 78 In hearings held before the House Ways and Means Committee in the aftermath of the subcommittee report, a representative from the Standard Oil Company of New Jersey testified that [t]here may be arbitrary allocations in consolidated groups to produce that result [of consistent loss offsets], but there are many other types of consolidations, natural vertical set-ups, as in our case, where there is every reason to have separate corporations for 73. Garner Will Take Floor Today to Lead Fight for Tax Bill, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 29, 1932, at 1. In the debates over the 1928 Act, Garner also proposed a graduated corporate income tax rate scheme. Senate to Decide Fate of Tax Bill, supra note 53 (describing the graduated tax on corporations as “the brain-child” of Representative Garner). See Barbara Deckard Sinclair, Party Realignment and the Transformation of the Political Agenda: The House of Representatives, 1925-1938, 71 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 940, 943 (1977). 74. 75 CONG. REC. 7127 (1932). 75. Blakey & Blakey, supra note 68, at 622. 76. SUBCOMM. ON TAX REVISION, COMM. ON WAYS & MEANS, 73D CONG., PREVENTION OF TAX AVOIDANCE 10 (Comm. Print 1933). 77. Id. 78. Godfrey N. Nelson, Consolidated Tax Held as Sound Plan, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 24, 1933, at N5.
52
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
certain operations . . . , and it is not a case of taxation, because they would continue to exist regardless of the tax penalty, and do exist regardless of any tax penalty. 79
Railroad representatives were particularly insistent that their business model was necessary, in no small part because of state and federal limits on consolidation. 80 Ben Dey, the general counsel of the Southern Pacific Co., a railroad company that both operated and owned the stock of sixty subsidiaries, urged that if the full committee approves the recommendation of the subcommittee I say to you in all fairness and on behalf of these railroad systems in the United States, only five or six of whom are making their way or are not on the verge of bankruptcy, that you should make an exception with respect to the parent company if it is engaged in interstate commerce as a common carrier, that it may come in and make a consolidated return for itself and its subsidiaries. 81
Dey concluded that “it is impossible to put the railroads under this proposal without committing a terrific public crime. They simply cannot stand it.” 82 Although the Ways and Means Committee ended up only proposing an increased penalty tax for consolidated returns, repeal was again proposed in the Senate. Seeking to “strike at the holding company system,” Progressive Senator William Borah introduced amendments to deny corporate groups the right to file consolidated returns and to deny any deduction for intercorporate dividends. 83 The proposal to repeal consolidated returns passed the Senate by a vote of forty to thirty-seven, albeit with an exception for railroad corporations, but the denial of the dividends received deduction was defeated by a vote of thirty-nine to thirty-three. 84 The result was that the law was left in a bit of a muddle. Barring consolidated returns arguably did reduce one advantage of utilizing a holding company structure by denying a corporation the right to offset its gains from one subsidiary with the losses of another subsidiary. 85 By preserving the dividends received deduction, however, 79. 1934 House Hearings, supra note 45, at 518 (statement of M.E. McDowell, Standard Oil Co. of New Jersey). 80. See, e.g., id. at 503-04 (statement of Jacob Aronson of the New York Central Lines) (arguing that the 1920 Transportation Act limited the ability of railroads to consolidate all of their lines and operations in a single corporation). 81. Id. at 484 (statement of Ben C. Dey, General Counsel, Southern Pacific Co.). 82. Id. at 486. 83. Tax Bill Changes Offered by Borah, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 2, 1934, at 38. 84. See Estate Tax Levy Raised $92,000,000 by Senate, 65 to 14, N.Y. TIMES, Apr. 13, 1934, at 1. 85. But see Godfrey N. Nelson, Corporations Hit by New Tax Policy, N.Y. TIMES, May 6, 1934, at N9 (“Either because of misunderstanding or by reason of a superficial
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
53
holding companies could still pass income through multiple tiers without recognizing additional layers of taxation. Moreover, for those seeking to attack the Van Swearingen-style corporate pyramid, an intercorporate dividends tax was far more likely to be important because of the absence of a 95% control requirement as that which existed for consolidated returns. The seeming inconsistency would soon be resolved. D. 1935–1936 On June 19, 1935, Roosevelt delivered a special Tax Message to Congress. 86 Right from the start of his message, it became clear that his focus was less about revenue and more about using tax to remedy certain perceived economic ills. According to Roosevelt, if a government is to be prudent its taxes must produce ample revenues without discouraging enterprise; and if it is to be just it must distribute the burden of taxes equitably. I do not believe that our present system of taxation completely meets this test. Our revenue laws have operated in many ways to the unfair advantage of the few, and they have done little to prevent an unjust concentration of wealth and economic power. 87
After justifying a graduated corporate income tax rate scheme as one means of addressing the inequities of the concentration of wealth, Roosevelt went on to revive the tax on intercorporate dividends that had been defeated in 1934. He contended that it would serve as an anti-abuse measure for the graduated rates: Provision should, of course, be made to prevent evasion of such graduated tax on corporate incomes through the device of numerous subsidiaries or affiliates, each of which might technically qualify as a small concern even though all were in fact operated as a single organization. The most effective method of preventing such evasions would be a tax on dividends received by corporations. 88
Business groups swiftly responded to the President’s tax message and the proposals for reforming corporate taxation. In a report issued one month later, the Committee on Federal Finance of the U.S. Chamber of Commerce concluded, “The purpose of the proposed taxes is obviously to break up large organizations and to compel business
knowledge of the practical use and operation of the consolidated return, this form of accounting has been erroneously associated with the freely denounced holding company or condemned as a device for the promotion of top-heavy capitalizations.”). 86. Franklin D. Roosevelt, Message to Congress on Tax Revision, AM. PRESIDENCY PROJECT (June 19, 1935), http:www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/?pid=15088. 87. Id. 88. Id.
54
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
to conduct its activities by means of relatively small units.” 89 Similarly, the National Industrial Conference Board observed that “[t]he Administration desires a program of taxation, the effect of which is primarily to tax or penalize size or bigness, wherever and in whatever form it may be found.” 90 During the hearings over the ensuing bill, businesses assailed any notion that the intercorporate dividends tax could be defended as a revenue or anti-abuse provision. Fred Clausen, Chairman of the Committee on Federal Finance for the United States Chamber of Commerce, pointed out that the maximum the proposed tax could possibly hope to raise at the 85% exemption rate would be $39.7 million, but even that assumed all dividends were taxed regardless of whether the corporation receiving it had any net income aside from the dividend. 91 At a 90% exemption, it effectively amounted to a 1.5% tax on dividends received. 92 Ellsworth Alvord, also of the U.S. Chamber of Commerce, added that “I do not know of anyone who admits that an intercompany dividend tax is sound. . . . [E]ven as a safeguard [against abuse of the graduated corporate tax rates] it is not necessary.” 93 Alvord explained that “the hazards—the plain business financial hazards—of busting up a large corporation into a large number of subsidiaries far outweigh the gains which might be made by a saving in the graduated tax.” 94 O.G. Saxon, a Professor of Business Administration at Yale, was also dubious of the anti-abuse rationale, testifying that “[t]he President’s objective of preventing evasion of the graduated tax could be obtained by requiring consolidated returns or some similar method.” 95 Moreover, Saxon added that “[t]he proposal that dividends to corporations on shares of other corporations owned by them be taxed in order to avoid evasion through subsidiary or holding companies is so clearly discriminatory against investors in corporations and particularly in large corporations as to require little discussion.” 96 Saxon predicted that “[i]t would have a deflationary effect on the stocks owned, for large-scale liquidation would likely ensue. Furthermore, 89. COMM. ON FED. FIN., CHAMBER OF COMMERCE OF THE U.S., FEDERAL TAXATION: THE SUGGESTIONS IN THE PRESIDENT’S TAX MESSAGE 17 (1935). 90. NAT’L INDUS. CONFERENCE BD., THE NEW FEDERAL TAX PROPOSALS 29 (1935). 91. Proposed Taxation of Individual and Corporate Incomes, Inheritances and Gifts: Hearing Before the H. Comm. on Ways & Means, 74th Cong. 258-59 (1935) [hereinafter 1935 House Hearings]. 92. MARK H. LEFF, THE LIMITS OF SYMBOLIC REFORM: THE NEW DEAL AND TAXATION, 1933-1939, at 143 (1984). 93. Revenue Act of 1935: Hearing on H.R. 8974 Before the S. Comm. on Fin., 74th Cong. 339-40 (1935). 94. Id. at 340. 95. 1935 House Hearings, supra note 91, at 243. 96. Id.
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
55
there is no occasion for such a provision. The revenue yield would be comparatively small and there is adequate control today of stock ownership in competing corporations through the Clayton Act.” 97 Given the weakness of the tax evasion rationale for the intercorporate dividends tax proposal, it is not surprising that Treasury officials paid mere lip service to it and instead focused on the role the non-taxation of intercorporate dividends played in contributing to the growth of corporate pyramids. Robert Jackson, Counsel for the Bureau of Internal Revenue and a future Supreme Court Justice, noted that even outside of the economic and fairness concerns about pyramidal structures, “their effect on the revenue system is demoralizing and destructive of good administration.” 98 According to Jackson: Tax law has for some years encouraged and almost subsidized the growth of these systems. Stocks of our domestic corporations, when held by parent corporations, have had almost the same status as to the tax exempt privilege that the Government has given to its own securities. There was a distinct incentive to corporations to acquire investments in other corporations, and once acquiring investments, there were, of course, the usual incentives to acquire control. 99
Jackson argued that taxing intercorporate dividends would aid in the assault against corporate pyramids that had already begun with the withdrawal of the consolidated return privilege. He indicated that it “would be desirable as a means of encouraging the simplification of corporate structures. Intercorporate dividends are largely unnecessary transfers brought about and multiplied by complex corporate structures.”100 Jackson explicitly situated the intercorporate dividends tax in the broader campaign against corporate pyramids that started with the repeal of consolidated returns for most companies: Up until last year the Federal Government had done little or nothing to discourage such needless complexities. Last year a definite step was taken in this direction by the abolition of consolidated returns. The partial elimination of the exemption allowed intercorporate dividends would be a further step in this direction and would have the effect of discouraging the multiplication of intermediate holding companies and of encouraging the creation and maintenance of straight-forward capital structures that can be understood by the average investor and public official. 101 97. Id. 98. ROBERT H. JACKSON, TREASURY DEP’T, MEMORANDUM AS TO GRADUATED CORPORATION INCOME TAX AND INTERCORPORATE DIVIDEND TAX 30 (1935), available at http://archive.org/stream/memorandumastogr00jack#page/n5/mode/2up. 99. Id. at 33. 100. Id. at 34. 101. Id. at 35.
56
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
Even the revenue estimates looked better when the intercorporate dividends tax was viewed as an attack on multitiered corporate structures. In the context of a corporate pyramid, for instance, the effective rate might rise if a multitiered corporation actually distributed a dividend up several steps in the chain. According to one estimate, “the tax on intercorporate dividends would vary from 1½ per cent to 2⅝ per cent, if the tax applied to 15 per cent of such dividends. . . . In the case of pyramided complex holding companies, such taxes might amount to 8 or 10 per cent.” 102 In specific cases, the tax burden of the intercorporate dividends tax on corporate pyramids might be even higher: In the case of one large public utility holding company with many subsidiaries, which the Treasury took for illustrative purposes, it was estimated that this tax would have amounted to 12 cents per share in 1930; in the case of a certain large industrial company with many subsidiaries, 5 cents a share in the same year. 103
Not only was the intercorporate dividends tax consistent with the campaign against corporate pyramids, but it derived from a tax proposal that had been explicitly considered during the debates earlier in 1935 over the Public Holding Company Act. 104 In the House Committee on Interstate and Foreign Commerce, Representative Samuel Pettengill, a Democrat from Indiana, had proposed an explicit 2% tax on intercorporate dividends, 105 which he explained during the House hearings over the Revenue Act of 1935 as the equivalent of an exemption of 85% on dividends at a time when the corporate rate was 13.75%. 106 Pettengill later explained that he understood the Interstate and Foreign Commerce Committee lacked jurisdiction to consider a tax, but “it was our way of getting it to the attention of the committee, with the thought of later bringing it to the attention of the Committee on Ways and Means.” 107 Economist Walter M.W. Splawn, special counsel to the Committee on Interstate and Foreign Commerce, had testified to that Committee that “[t]he most effective means of preventing pyramiding is to eliminate the so-called intermediary companies interposed between the operating company and the company at the top. Heretofore these intermediary companies have, in effect, been subsidized by the Federal Government 102. Roy G. Blakey & Gladys C. Blakey, The Revenue Act of 1935, 25 AM. ECON. REV. 673, 684 (1935). 103. Id. 104. At least one witness in the House Hearings for the tax bill makes reference to this. See 1935 House Hearings, supra note 91, at 327 (statement of Rep. Samuel B. Pettengill). 105. See Public Utility Holding Companies: Hearing on H.R. 5423 Before the H. Comm. on Interstate & Foreign Commerce, 74th Cong. 2214 (1935). 106. 1935 House Hearings, supra note 91, at 329. 107. Id. at 328.
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
57
through exemption from taxes of dividends on their stock.” 108 Splawn recommended that “[i]nstead of giving Government encouragement to intermediate holding companies through exemption from taxation, those companies should be required to pay taxes as though they were not tied in through stock ownership with a number of other corporations.” 109 Months before Roosevelt delivered his 1935 tax message proposing the intercorporate dividends tax as a means of stemming evasion of the graduated rate scheme, he had endorsed an anti-holding company proposal similar to Pettengill’s for taxing intercorporate dividends. In January of 1935, Representative Sam Rayburn of Texas reportedly received White House support and approval for a proposed bill that would regulate and subject public utility holding companies to a penalty tax not unlike the one imposed on consolidated returns prior to 1934. 110 The prediction was that “the tax finally decided on will be such as to permit holding companies which have not weakened their structures through pyramiding to exist, while the public will be protected largely through the regulation, which will be of a character to prevent the rise of new holding companies.” 111 Although the Public Utility Holding Company Act adopted later in 1935 substituted a total ban for the proposed tax penalty, the Administration remained committed to using taxes more generally as a check against corporate structures deemed to be abusive. Roosevelt merely made a strategic decision to subordinate the intercorporate dividends tax to the graduated corporate income tax rate proposal as part of an effort to simplify matters for the public by focusing primarily on the “unhealthy and mischievous concentrations of wealth.” 112 Nevertheless, the connection between intercorporate dividend taxation and the assault on pyramids was already publicly established. Moreover, there is evidence that Roosevelt was well aware of the connection between the intercorporate dividends tax and corporate pyramids when he made his proposal in 1935. In the President’s Secretary’s notes, which contain documents that the White House considered important and confidential, there is a memorandum titled “Intercorporate Dividend Tax.” 113 The memorandum, which may have come from Treasury Secretary Henry Morgenthau, explained that 108. Id. at 328 (quoting Dr. Splawn in House Report 827, pt. 2, at 7). 109. Id. 110. White House Backs Holding Unit Taxes, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 23, 1935, at 25. 111. Id. 112. LEFF, supra note 92, at 136 (quoting a letter from Felix Frankfurter to Roosevelt). 113. Intercorporate Dividend Tax, in Franklin D. Roosevelt, Papers as President: The President’s Secretary’s File (PSF), 1933-1945, Box 186 – Taxes, at 5 (undated 1935) (on file with the Franklin D. Roosevelt Presidential Library and Museum), available at http://www.fdrlibrary.marist.edu/_resources/images/psf/psfc0129.pdf.
58
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
“[t]here has not yet been incorporated in the new tax bill the principle, originated in the tax legislation of last year, of taxing intercorporate dividends so as to discourage holding companies. . . . An amendment to effect this tax has been carefully drafted in the Department of Justice and is ready for presentation to the Ways and Means Committee by [Robert] Jackson.” 114 Business leaders assailed this use of the intercorporate dividends tax as part of the campaign against corporate pyramids that began with the repeal of consolidated returns. Fred Clausen of the U.S. Chamber of Commerce noted that if the intercorporate dividends tax was aimed at breaking up holding companies, it was overinclusive in its application. As Clausen explained, “the proposal is not limited to taxing the dividends received by a corporation owning most of . . . the stock of another but applies to any holding of stock, no matter how small in percentage.” 115 Business arguments apparently prevailed in the House, which excluded the President’s suggestion for an intercorporate dividends tax from its bill. 116 The House did indicate a willingness to consider the measure in a separate bill aimed at “discouraging chains of holding companies,” 117 however, suggesting that the majority wanted the proposal to be stripped of its thin façade as a tax evasion measure and discussed in its true context. Nevertheless, the intercorporate dividends tax was reinserted in the Senate bill in the form of an 85% dividends received deduction. 118 In Conference proceedings, the House agreed to accept the principle of intercorporate dividends taxation as part of the tax bill, but it successfully reduced the amount of the dividend subject to tax from the 15% proposed in the Senate to 10%. 119 The following year, the question of intercorporate dividends taxation was again on the agenda as part of the consideration of the Revenue Act of 1936. Although much of Congressional attention was focused on a radical proposal to subject undistributed corporate profits to a penalty tax, 120 the bill reported out by the Ways and Means Committee to the House contained a provision that would eliminate the dividends received deduction altogether.121 Ultimately, Congress
114. Id. 115. 1935 House Hearings, supra note 91, at 258. 116. Blakey & Blakey, supra note 102, at 685. 117. Id. 118. Id. 119. BLAKEY & BLAKEY, supra note 22, at 381. 120. See Steven A. Bank, Corporate Managers, Agency Costs, and the Rise of Double Taxation, 44 WM. & MARY L. REV. 167, 170, 204 (2002). 121. Miller, supra note 54, at 303.
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
59
reduced the deduction from 90% to 85%, but it was changed from a deduction to a credit. 122 III. EVOLUTION Although the intercorporate dividends tax was not significant enough to actually disrupt corporate structures, it continued to loom large for both proponents and detractors in the years that followed. As Ellis Hawley observed, “the advocates of decentralization regarded the act as an opening wedge. The small tax on intercorporate dividends might someday evolve into a weapon that would eliminate useless and monopolistic holding companies.” 123 This is precisely what worried opponents. A tax agent for Sears, Roebuck & Co. noted during a discussion of the issue at the 1938 Annual Meeting of the National Tax Association that [i]ntercorporate holdings will not be disposed of because of a tax of 2½% on the intercorporate dividends, if the investment is profitable. Therefore, in order to accomplish its stated purpose of forcing the discontinuance of intercorporate holdings, the government will be forced to increase the rates. It clearly follows that the trend of this kind of legislation leads directly to punitive measures, and regulation. 124
As it turned out, this concern that the tax would continue to loom large was accurate, even if the prediction of increasing rates was not. In 1937, Robert Jackson declared that the tax had already succeeded in breaking up some holding companies, and he predicted that an increase in the tax would finish the job. [T]he privilege of paying dividends profits free of tax from one corporation to another, operated as a subsidy for the holding companies, one of the most favored forms of creating and operating monopoly. The recent repeal of this privilege and the substitution of an intercorporate dividend tax has already proved highly effective in dissolving holding companies, and undoubtedly an increase in that tax would prove an automatic discouragement of that particular type of antitrust violations. 125
Roosevelt joined Jackson in advocating an increase in the intercorporate dividend taxation as a means of addressing anticompetitive behavior. In his 1938 Message to Congress regarding the Temporary 122. Id. 123. ELLIS W. HAWLEY, THE NEW DEAL AND THE PROBLEM OF MONOPOLY 350 (1966). 124. A.R. Kaiser, NATIONAL TAX ASS’N, Discussion of the Taxation of Intercorporate Dividends, in PROCEEDINGS OF THE THIRTY-FIRST ANNUAL CONFERENCE ON TAXATION 439, 443 (W.G. Query ed., 1939). 125. Robert H. Jackson, Address, The Struggle Against Monopoly, 1937 GA. B.A. REP. 203, 206, available at http://www.roberthjackson.org/files/theman/speeches-articles/files/ the-struggle-against-monopoly.pdf (last visited Jan. 30, 2014).
60
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
National Economic Committee, Roosevelt noted that “[t]ax policies should be devised to give affirmative encouragement to competitive enterprise,” including “increasing the intercorporate dividend tax to discourage holding companies.” 126 Opponents tried to limit the application of the tax, but to no avail. In 1937, for example, the Twentieth Century Fund’s Committee on Taxation proposed a version of the intercorporate dividends tax that was more narrowly tailored to discouraging corporate pyramids: The pyramiding of two or more holding companies is rarely necessary for operating purposes, and it facilitates manipulation. Accordingly, the corporation income tax might distinguish between the first intercorporate payment of dividends, and the second and subsequent intercorporate payment of dividends. That is, dividends paid to a holding company by the operating company would be exempt or taxed at a lower rate than dividends paid by one holding company to another. Such a tax would strongly discourage the pyramiding of holding companies and would discourage single holding companies only slightly—if at all. 127
This proposal, however, fell on deaf ears. In 1939, business lobbyists successfully targeted many aspects of the New Deal tax program for repeal or revision, but it fell short in securing a reduction in the tax on intercorporate dividends. 128 The beginning of the end for intercorporate dividend taxation as a means of attacking corporate pyramids came when the ban on consolidated returns was eased in 1942 and a 2% penalty tax similar to the one in place between 1932 and 1934 was revived. 129 Much like in 1917, this came on the heels of the adoption of an excess profits tax with the accompanying concerns about the need for consolidated returns to prevent profit shifting. Contemporary scholars had always viewed the ban on consolidated returns and the taxation of intercorporate dividends to be inextricably linked as policies against corporate pyramids. In 1940, Gerhard Colm, an economics professor and fiscal expert for the U.S. Department of Commerce, wrote that “[i]ntercorporate stockholdings have been used as a means for controlling corporations without necessarily involving full financial responsibility for the controlled corporations. Consolidated balance 126. FRANKLIN D. ROOSEVELT, MESSAGE FROM THE PRESIDENT OF THE UNITED STATES TRANSMITTING RECOMMENDATIONS RELATIVE TO THE STRENGTHENING AND ENFORCEMENT OF ANTI-TRUST LAWS, S. DOC. NO. 75-173, at 9 (3d Sess. 1938). 127. COMM. ON TAXATION OF THE TWENTIETH CENTURY FUND, INC., FACING THE TAX PROBLEM: A SURVEY OF TAXATION IN THE UNITED STATES AND A PROGRAM FOR THE FUTURE 182 (1937). 128. LEFF, supra note 92, at 273. 129. See Maimone & Riley, supra note 4, at 782. Consolidated returns were actually permitted again starting with the Revenue Act of 1940, but only for purposes of the excess profits tax. Mundstock, supra note 4, at 10.
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
61
sheets and tax exemption for intercorporate dividends permit free use of this device.” 130 As a consequence, even before the ban on consolidated returns was lifted, one practitioner pointed out that reviving the consolidated return would make the intercorporate dividend tax incoherent: “if provision for consolidated returns of affiliated corporations should be restored to our taxation system, intercompany dividends within an affiliated group would be eliminated from tax consideration along with other intercompany transactions . . . .” 131 With consolidated returns once again permitted, this meant that intercorporate dividends between corporations affiliated by 95% stock ownership were completely exempt (beyond the 2% tax for the privilege of filing the return), while intercorporate dividends to stockholders owning less than 95% of the stock were only 85% exempt. In 1964, the additional 2% penalty tax on consolidated returns was repealed, and consolidated returns once again became fully available. 132 This was part of a broader program to aid small business. Under the Small Business Investment Act of 1958, dividends received by small business investment companies were made 100% exempt.133 In his 1963 tax message, President John F. Kennedy announced a proposal to further advance this policy. 134 Under the existing scheme, corporations were subject to a total rate of 52%, consisting of a 30% normal rate and a 22% surtax rate on earnings in excess of $25,000. Kennedy proposed to “flip” the normal and surtax rate, so that the first $25,000 of taxable corporate earnings—“the entire earnings of almost half a million small corporations” according to Kennedy—would realize a 27% rate reduction, while total taxes applicable to larger corporations would not change. 135 There was concern, however, that the benefit of the lower normal rate and the exemption from the higher surtax rate for the first $25,000 in income would not be confined to small businesses. 136 Large corporations already took advantage of the $25,000 surtax exemption by spreading their in130. Gerhard Colm, Conflicting Theories of Corporate Income Taxation, 7 LAW & CON281, 288 (1940). 131. Miller, supra note 54, at 304. 132. Revenue Act of 1964, Pub. L. No. 88-272, § 234(a), 78 Stat. 19, 113 (1964). 133. Emanuel S. Burstein, The Idiosyncratic Consequences of the Limits in Section 246(b) on the Dividends Received Deduction, 13 TAX NOTES 1019, 1021 (1981). For more background on small business investment companies, see Mirit Eyal-Cohen, Why Is Small Business the Chief Business of Congress?, 43 RUTGERS L.J. 1 (2012). 134. John F. Kennedy, Special Message to the Congress on Tax Reduction and Reform, AM. PRESIDENCY PROJECT (Jan. 24, 1963), http:www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/?pid=15088. 135. Id. In 1964, he proposed that the surtax rate “be reduced to 28%, thereby lowering the combined corporate rate [from 52%] to 50%,” and in 1965, the surtax and total rate would be reduced further. Id. 136. See Sheldon S. Cohen, Election of Tax Free Intercorporate Dividends Under the Revenue Act of 1964, 6 WM. & MARY L. REV. 167, 169 (1965). TEMP. PROBS.
62
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
come among multiple subsidiaries. The flipping of the normal and surtax rates, with the result that the surtax rate was much higher, only increased the incentive for abuse. Kennedy therefore explained that “[s]ince the $25,000 surtax exemption and the new 22% normal rate are designed to stimulate small business, this reduction should be accompanied by action designed to eliminate the advantage of the multiple surtax exemptions now available to large enterprises operating through a chain of separately incorporated units.” 137 He proposed limiting affiliated corporate groups with 80% common control to one surtax exemption, which would effectively treat them as a single entity.138 As enacted, multiple surtax exemptions were permitted, but at a cost of a 6% penalty, increasing the normal rate from 22% to 28% in these instances.139 In return, the 2% penalty on consolidated returns was removed. As Kennedy explained, “if affiliated corporations are treated as an entity for the surtax exemption and other purposes, they should be permitted to obtain the advantages of filing consolidated returns without incurring the present tax of 2% on the net income of all corporations filing such returns.” 140 Much like the shift in attitude toward the consolidated return, Congress shifted from taxing intercorporate dividends under an antiavoidance and anti-holding company rationale to permitting a more liberal dividends received deduction under an enterprise rationale, premised on the notion that the income was earned by a single enterprise. 141 Thus, at the same time that the penalty tax was dropped from the consolidated return, Congress de-linked the 100% dividends received deduction from the filing of a consolidated return, making it an elective stand-alone provision. 142 As enacted, the provision permitted corporations to receive dividends tax-free from a member of the same affiliated group, which was defined to include an 80% owned subsidiary. 143 In theory, this equalized the treatment of intercorpo137. Kennedy, supra note 134. 138. Id. 139. Revenue Act of 1964, Pub. L. No. 88-272, § 235(b), 78 Stat. 19, 125 (1964); Thomas D. Terry, Attorney, Internal Revenue Service, Panel Discussion on Certain Problem Areas Under the Revenue Act of 1964 at the William & Mary Annual Tax Conference 83-84 (1964), available at http://scholarship.law.wm.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1646 &context=tax. For all affiliated groups but those with aggregate incomes close to $25,000, it was more advantageous to elect to incur the penalty in order to take multiple surtax exemptions. Charles L.B. Lowndes, The Revenue Act of 1964: A Critical Analysis, 1964 DUKE L.J. 667, 678. 140. Kennedy, supra note 134. 141. See ANTONY TING, THE TAXATION OF CORPORATE GROUPS UNDER CONSOLIDATION 71-72 (2013). There was some legislation designed to address abuse of the dividends received deduction itself, but the focus on the perceived corporate governance abuse of the pyramidal structure had disappeared. See Mundstock, supra note 4, at 13-16. 142. See Mundstock, supra note 4, at 13-14. 143. Id.; Revenue Act of 1964, Pub. L. No. 88-272, § 214(a), 78 Stat. 19, 52 (1964) (en-
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
63
rate dividends for separate filers and consolidated return filers. In practice, however, the price for making such an election for separate filers was high and roughly equivalent to, or higher than, the costs of filing a consolidated return itself. 144 This led at least one contemporary observer to predict that “[i]t provides for an election to claim the 100% deduction, but the price in terms of disadvantages which must be accepted is so high that it is doubtful whether the provision will be used to any substantial extent.” 145 Nevertheless, the move paved the way for the modern dividends received deduction that is scaled according to size of ownership percentage. Corporations owning 80% or more of another corporation were eligible for the 100% dividends received deduction, while corporations owning less than 80% of another corporation were eligible for the pre-1964 Act deduction of 85%.146 In the Tax Reform Act of 1986 and the Omnibus Budget Reconciliation Act of 1987, Congress put the finishing touches on the modern scheme. In 1986, the general intercorporate dividends received deduction was reduced from 85% to 80% for corporations that owned less than 80% of a subsidiary. 147 As both the House Ways and Means and Senate Finance Committee reports to the 1986 Act explained, the rationale for this change was that it was necessitated by the broader changes in tax rates under the 1986 Act.148 Prior to 1986, the top corporate rate was 46%, and corporations eligible for the 85% dividends received deduction (i.e., those owning less than 80% of the shares of the subsidiary paying the dividend) were therefore subject to an effective rate of 6.9% (15% of the dividend subject to a 46% rate). 149 In the 1986 Act, the top rate was lowered to 34%. If instead the dividends received deduction had been maintained at 85% under the new lower top corporate rate, the effective rate on intercorporate dividends would have fallen to 5.1%. 150 The Staff of the Joint Committee on Taxation explained: Congress did not believe that the reduction in corporate tax rates generally should result in a significant reduction in this effective rate. Thus, the dividends received deduction has been reduced to acting I.R.C. § 243). 144. E. Randolph Dale, 1964 Act: Climate Improved for Multiple Corporations Despite Penalty Tax, 20 J. TAX’N 264, 266-67 (1964). The price included a limit of only one surtax exemption for the affiliated group, one accumulated earnings credit, and one $100,000 estimated tax exemption. See id.; Cohen, supra note 136, at 179-80. 145. Dale, supra note 144, at 266. 146. See Burstein, supra note 133, at 1020-21. 147. Tax Reform Act of 1986, Pub. L. No. 99-514, § 611(a)(1), 100 Stat. 2085, 2249. 148. H.R. REP. NO. 99-426, at 244 (1985) [hereinafter 1985 HOUSE REPORT]; S. REP. NO. 99-313, at 221 (2d Sess. 1985) [hereinafter 1985 SENATE REPORT]. 149. 1985 SENATE REPORT, supra note 148, at 221. 150. JAMES S. EUSTICE ET AL., THE TAX REFORM ACT OF 1986: ANALYSIS AND COMMENTARY 2-64 (1987).
64
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
80 percent, resulting in a maximum rate of 6.8 percent on dividends subject to the reduced top corporate rate (20 percent of the top corporate rate of 34 percent). 151
In 1987, Congress completed the reform of intercorporate dividend taxation when it adopted a new 70% dividends received deduction for corporations receiving dividends from corporations in which they had less than a 20% stake. 152 During consideration of the 1986 Act, the House had considered a bill that created three tiers: 100% for dividends received from affiliates (i.e., 80% owned subsidiaries), 90% for dividends received from a small business investment company (down from 100% when the provision was enacted in 1958), and 80%, transitioning to 70% after the phase-in period, for all other intercorporate dividends.153 In Conference, however, the Senate version was chosen.154 In the fall of 1987, the combination of the federal deficit concerns and the looming automatic budget cuts that would be triggered in the absence of new revenue led to a revival of interest in tax increases.155 At first, President Ronald Reagan stood his ground “stumping the country saying he wants no tax increases.”156 The stock market crash in October, however, changed his tune.157 Declaring that “I’m putting everything on the table,” Reagan “abandoned his vow never to raise taxes and ordered his top aides to work with Congress in developing a deficit-reduction plan that ‘keeps spending and taxes as low as possible.’ ” 158 Among the revenue raising proposals was to reduce the dividends received deduction from 80% to 75% for dividends from less than 20%-owned corporations. The House Ways and Means Committee justified the change under the enterprise rationale for the dividends received deduction, explaining that it “believe[d] that the present-law dividends received deduction is too generous for corporations that are not eligible to be treated as the alter ego of the distributing corporation because they do not have a sufficient ownership
151. STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, 99TH CONG., GENERAL EXPLANATION OF THE TAX REFORM ACT OF 1986, at 274 (Comm. Print 1987). 152. See Omnibus Budget Reconciliation Act of 1987, Pub. L. No. 100-203, § 10221(a)(1), 101 Stat. 1330, 1330-408. 153. 1985 HOUSE REPORT, supra note 148, at 244-45. 154. H.R. REP. NO. 99-841, at II-161 (1986) (Conf. Rep.). 155. Jeffrey H. Birnbaum, Reagan Faces Deficit Showdown with Congress, Hard Choices of Paring Military or Raising Taxes, WALL ST. J., July 16, 1987, at 56. 156. Id.; John H. Cushman, Jr., Fee Rise Suggested to Reduce Deficit, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 28, 1987, at A1. 157. The Budget Deficit Disgrace, N.Y. TIMES, Nov. 20, 1987, at A38. See generally DIV. OF MKT. REG., U.S. SEC. & EXCH. COMM’N, THE OCTOBER 1987 MARKET BREAK xi (1988) (describing the volatility of the market in October 1987). 158. Jack Nelson, Reagan Backs Off His Stand Against Increase in Taxes: Aides Will Meet with Leaders of Congress on Debt, L.A. TIMES, Oct. 23, 1987, at 16.
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
65
interest in that corporation.” 159 The Senate included no such reduction in the rate for intercorporate dividends, but in conference they agreed to adopt the House provision, with a reduction in the rate from 75% to 70%.160 IV. FUTURE The reforms to the taxation of intercorporate dividends in the 1960s and 1980s primarily reflect the move away from the antiholding company rationale of the New Deal and toward an approach influenced most prominently by a need for revenue. To the extent that the enterprise rationale continues to buttress the scheme, it does so in a blunt and largely unsatisfying fashion, with no differentiation in the percentage exclusion available for 79% corporate owners and 20% corporate owners. In 2007, the Department of Treasury’s Office of Tax Policy examined the dividends received deduction and found it particularly problematic because of the tax cascading effect.161 This is the problem of running income up through multiple tiers of corporate ownership, each of which is only eligible for a partial dividends received deduction. According to the Office of Tax Policy’s report: By failing to allow a full 100-percent deduction for all intercorporate dividends, the tax system can impose multiple layers of tax on intercorporate dividends, which leads to distortions in the allocation of investment by discouraging corporations from investments in other corporations that would be profitable in the absence of the cascading levels of taxes. 162
The Office of Tax Policy calculated that under the 70% dividends received deduction, the additional layer of tax imposes an extra $6.83 burden on every $100 of corporate earnings. 163 The evidence the Office of Tax Policy marshaled regarding intercorporate dividends supports the notion that the partial dividends received deduction is not all that productive. Of almost $280 billion in intercorporate dividends issued in 2004, only $51 billion, or less than 19%, were subject to taxation—and that includes dividends not eligible for the dividends received deduction at all, such as dividends from foreign corporations. 164 Of the nearly $100 billion in intercorpo159. H.R. REP. NO. 100-391, pt. 2, at 1094 (1987). 160. See H.R. REP. NO. 100-495, at 965 (1987) (Conf. Rep.). 161. See OFFICE OF TAX POLICY, U.S. DEP’T OF THE TREASURY, APPROACHES TO IMPROVE THE COMPETITIVENESS OF THE U.S. BUSINESS TAX SYSTEM FOR THE 21ST CENTURY 76-77 (2007). 162. Id. at 76. 163. Id. at 77. 164. Id. at 78.
66
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
rate dividends eligible for either the 100, 80, or 70% dividends received deduction, only $16.8 billion in intercorporate dividends were eligible for the 80 and 70% deductions. 165 There appear to be several alternative methods that have been proposed regarding the taxation of intercorporate dividends. One possibility is to provide a 100% dividends received deduction for all intercorporate dividends. This was the system in place prior to 1935. In 1979, the American Bar Association’s Committee on Affiliated and Related Corporations proposed returning to this approach, noting that the original purpose of the move away from a 100% deduction “was twofold: (1) to prevent the use of graduated corporate income tax rates by members of a single corporate group, that is, to prevent the use of multiple surtax allowances; and (2) to discourage the use of elaborate chains of public utility holding companies.” 166 The Committee explained, “[i]t is highly doubtful whether the slight reduction in the dividends-received deduction from 100 percent to 85 percent achieved either purpose.” 167 Moreover, at least in the case of the latter explanation, the culmination of the successful battle to eliminate public utility holding companies, which coincided with the repeal of the ban on consolidated returns, effectively shifted the focus away from anti-bigness. 168 With respect to the concern that an unlimited dividends received deduction would be abused, several provisions have been enacted that target such abuse more effectively than the declining dividends received deduction percentage. In 1969, Congress moved to shut down one problem with affiliated groups of corporations in a graduated corporate rate scheme—the multiple surtax exemption. 169 The Revenue Act of 1964 had taken some steps against this practice by imposing a penalty tax for the privilege of claiming multiple surtax exemptions,170 but in the Tax Reform Act of 1969, Congress shut it down altogether by limiting controlled corporations to one surtax ex165. Id. 166. Comm. on Affiliated & Related Corps., Summaries of Proposed Legislative Recommendations to Amend the Internal Revenue Code of 1954 to Apply a 100 Percent Dividends-Received Deduction to All Dividends Received by a Corporation from a Domestic Corporation, 32 TAX LAW. 863, 864 (1979). 167. Id. 168. See Steven A. Bank, Taxing Bigness, 66 TAX L. REV. (forthcoming 2014) (manuscript at 36-37) (on file with author). But see Randall Morck, How to Eliminate Pyramidal Business Groups: The Double Taxation of Intercorporate Dividends and Other Incisive Uses of Tax Policy, 19 TAX POL’Y & THE ECON. 135, 169 (2005) (suggesting the taxation of intercorporate dividends might be used in other countries to combat the corporate governance problems of pyramidal structures). 169. Thomas R. White III, The Tax Reform Act of 1969: Demise of Multiple Surtax Exemptions—When Too Much of a Good Thing Proved Its Own Undoing, 16 WAYNE L. REV. 1353, 1358-60 (1970). 170. See supra text accompanying notes 136-39.
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
67
emption.171 Of course, this type of abuse is driven primarily by the existence of graduated corporate rates that reward the splitting of income among multiple subsidiaries so none of them have incomes beyond the lowest rate. 172 Repealing the graduated rate scheme would reduce the tax incentives for utilizing such a structure. 173 In the 1980s, Congress further strengthened protections against several other schemes designed to abuse the dividends received deduction, such as extraordinary dividends on stock held for less than two years. 174 These schemes were called “milking transactions” because the goal is to milk the profits of the subsidiary in a tax-free intercorporate dividend.175 Congress also limited the ability of corporate parents to extract tax-free intercorporate dividends through debtfinanced subsidiary portfolio stock purchases. 176 These transactions were concerning because the combination of an interest deduction and the dividends received deduction appeared to permit the corporation to shelter unrelated income or to subsidize a takeover.177 A second possible reform that has been proposed as an alternative to the current scheme for taxing intercorporate dividends, which stands at the opposite end of the spectrum from the first, would eliminate the partial deduction altogether. 178 The partial dividends received deduction was always an awkward combination with the repeal of the consolidated return, since the rhetoric of an intercorporate dividends tax was, in reality, still a 90% and then 85% dividends received deduction for corporations that were supposed to be considered separate in the absence of the consolidated return. A version of this alternative was offered by Harvard professor William Andrews in his Reporter’s Study on Corporate Distributions for the American Law Institute’s Federal Income Tax Project on Subchapter C. 179 Andrews highlighted the difference between direct investments in controlled subsidiaries and portfolio investments in 171. See Tax Reform Act of 1969, Pub. L. No. 91-172, § 401(a), 83 Stat. 487, 599-604. 172. See Michael Aikins, Note, Common Control and the Delineation of the Taxable Entity, 121 YALE L.J. 624, 651-52 (2011). 173. See Bank, supra note 168, at 44-45 (suggesting that other incentives, such as those targeted at small businesses, would remain). 174. See Mundstock, supra note 4, at 15-17. 175. Id. at 12. 176. STAFF OF THE JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, 98TH CONG., GENERAL EXPLANATION OF THE REVENUE PROVISIONS OF THE DEFICIT REDUCTION ACT OF 1984, at 128-29 (Comm. Print 1984). 177. Id. 178. See, e.g., Maimone & Riley, supra note 4, at 778-79 (proposing a repeal of the partial dividends received deduction for non-affiliated corporations, while retaining the 100% deduction for affiliated corporations). 179. See generally William D. Andrews, Reporter’s Study on Corporate Distributions, in AM. LAW INST., FEDERAL INCOME TAX PROJECT: SUBCHAPTER C 487 (1982).
68
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
non-controlled corporations, suggesting that a full dividends received deduction made sense for the former type of investment, while there was no justification for a dividends received deduction for the latter type of investment. 180 According to Andrews, the problem with allowing even a partial dividends received deduction for portfolio investments is that it distorted investment decisions by preferring investments in corporate equity over other fully taxable forms of investment. 181 By contrast, for a direct investment, “the dividend-received deduction is not enough to effect a consistent and uniform elimination of double corporate taxation.” 182 Rather than setting the dividing line between these two investments at the 80% ownership percentage under the current rules, however, Andrew proposed a more complicated scheme that would have allowed even a 10% ownership stake to be classified as a direct investment. 183 The American Law Institute, however, never adopted the recommendations contained in his Reporter’s Study. 184 There have been some proposals to tinker with the current partial dividends received deduction, but much like the 1987 reform they appear to be revenue-driven rather than based upon any conceptual notion of the proper tax treatment. In 2007, Charlie Rangel proposed reducing the 80% deduction to 70%, and reducing the 70% deduction to 60%. 185 Much like in 1986 and 1987, this was part of a proposal to reduce the general corporate rate from 35% to 30.5%. 186 In this case, however, the focus was not on maintaining the same effective tax rate, but on making the overall reduction in rate revenue-neutral. Nevertheless, this proposal has never been acted upon. Given the current push to reduce the corporate income tax rate in a manner that is either revenue-neutral or is part of a reform of business taxation that produces increased revenue,187 however, Rangel’s proposal or something similar may soon be revived by politicians seeking to pay for their own bills. 180. See id. 181. See id. at 494. 182. Id. at 496. 183. Id. at 490. Andrews classified an investment as “direct” if “(i) the investor corporation own[ed] more than 50 percent of the common stock of the issuer for . . . [at least] one year; or (ii) the investor corporation own[ed] 10 percent or more of the common stock of the issuer and designat[ed] the holding as a direct investment; or (iii) the investment ha[d] ever been a direct investment [for at least one year] and ha[d] not been subsequently completely terminated . . . .” Id. 184. Maimone & Riley, supra note 4, at 790 n.46. 185. See H.R. 3970 Tax Reduction and Reform Act of 2007, COMMITTEE ON WAYS & MEANS (Oct. 29, 2007), http://waysandmeans.house.gov/media/pdf/110/summary%20for% 20distribution.pdf. 186. See id. 187. See Obama’s ‘Grand Bargain’ with Obama, WALL ST. J., July 31, 2013, at A12.
2013]
WHEN WE TAXED THE PYRAMIDS
69
A complicating factor in any proposal for reform of the dividends received deduction is the globalization of modern corporations. 188 The basic rules limit the dividends received deduction to taxable domestic corporations. 189 There are exceptions, however, for dividends from foreign corporations arising out of earnings and profits accumulated while the corporation was still a domestic taxable corporation, and for dividends from a 10% owned foreign corporation with respect to the portion of the dividends that is U.S.-sourced.190 Some companies have invoked these exceptions in the context of so-called “sandwich” structures involving a domestic corporation owning a foreign corporation that owns a domestic corporation. 191 Eventually, the Internal Revenue Service issued a private letter ruling to provide guidance for intercorporate dividends in this type of structure. 192 More recently, however, the Service has had to issue additional guidance to disallow abusive uses of the dividends received deduction involving controlled foreign corporations. 193 With reports suggesting that an increasing number of domestic companies are relocating outside the U.S. through reincorporation mergers, with either existing companies or shell companies, 194 these types of structures may become more important. Indeed, if an anti-holding company sentiment prompts a move to a less generous scheme for taxing intercorporate dividends, it is likely that multinational holding companies will be the twentyfirst century version of the original corporate pyramids.
188. See Steven A. Bank, The Globalization of Corporate Tax Reform, 40 PEPP. L. REV. 1307, 1308-09 (2013) (describing the growth of multinational corporations and the globalization of corporate profits for domestic corporations). 189. See I.R.C. § 243(a). 190. See id. §§ 243(e), 245. 191. See, e.g., Hal Hicks et al., Sandwich Structures: The IRS Illuminates the Application of the DRD and Other Provisions, INT’L TAX J., July-Aug. 2010, at 61, 61; John D. McDonald et al., The Dividends-Received Deduction and Sandwich Structures, TAXES, May 2010, at 5, 5. 192. See I.R.S. Priv. Ltr. Rul. 200952031 (Dec. 24, 2009). 193. I.R.S. Chief Couns. Mem. 201320014 (Jan. 18, 2013); see also Jasper L. Cummings, Jr., The Substance of Dividends Received Deductions, 140 TAX NOTES 603 (2013); Jeffrey L. Rubinger & Nadia E. Kruler, Service Applies Substance Over Form Doctrine to Disallow Dividends-Received Deduction, 119 J. TAX’N 13 (2013). 194. See Mark Koba, Avoid U.S. Taxes by Forming a Merger Abroad, NBCNEWS.COM (July 31, 2013, 5:23 PM), http://www.nbcnews.com/business/avoid-us-taxes-formingforeign-merger-6C10810789.
70
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:39
SOME INCOME TAX SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS JOSEPH M. DODGE * I. II. III.
INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................ SIMPLIFICATION AS AN AGENDA ...................................................................... SIMPLIFICATION WITHOUT REFORM ................................................................ A. Taxpayer Relief from Arithmetic ............................................................... B. Checklists for Tax-Benefits Eligibility Requirements ................................ C. Tax Credits to be “Off Tax” ........................................................................ D. Rate Schedules ........................................................................................... E. Subsistence Income .................................................................................... 1. Eliminate the Standard Deduction...................................................... 2. The Personal Exemption Amount ........................................................ 3. Dependency Exemption Amounts ......................................................... 4. The Definition of “Dependent”.............................................................. 5. Eliminate the Child Tax Credit ........................................................... F. The Working Poor ...................................................................................... 1. No Separate Rate Schedules for Unmarried Individuals and Heads of Household ........................................................................................ 2. Replace the Child Tax Credit, the Earned Income Tax Credit, and the Household and Dependent Care Credit with a Single Dependent Care Allowance .................................................................................... G. The Taxable Income Computation ............................................................. 1. Equal Status Among Deductions ......................................................... 2. Personal Deductions Subject to Floors................................................. 3. Deduction Phase-Out Rules ................................................................. 4. The Proper Function of the AMT ......................................................... H. Social Security Retirement Benefits........................................................... I. Educational Tax Benefits .......................................................................... J. Borderline Personal/Business Deductions ................................................ 1. Marginal Business and Investment Deductions Generally ................. 2. Business Meal Costs ............................................................................. 3. Business Lodging Costs ....................................................................... 4. Not-for-Profit Activities ........................................................................ (a) Accounting .................................................................................... (b) Definition of “Not-for-Profit Activity” ........................................... 5. Rental or Business Use of Personal Residence..................................... (a) Integrate the Rental Aspect of § 280A with § 183......................... (b) Disallowance of Deductions for Costs of a Residence Used in a Business......................................................................................... (c) Travel Expenses to Maintain a Residence .................................... 6. Tangible Personal Property Available for Personal Use ...................... 7. Credit Card Interest ............................................................................. K. Cancellation-of-Debt Income ...................................................................... L. Alimony vs. Child Support ........................................................................ M. Small Business Tax Accounting ................................................................ 1. Expand Use of the Cash Method .......................................................... 2. Opting Out of Inventory Accounting ....................................................
73 73 76 76 77 77 77 77 78 78 79 79 80 81 81 82 84 84 85 85 85 86 87 87 87 88 88 90 90 91 92 92 93 94 94 95 95 96 97 97 98
* Stearns Weaver Miller Weissler Alhadeff & Sitterson Professor of Law, Florida State University College of Law. The author wishes to thank Norman Stein, Joseph Bankman, Calvin Johnson, and participants of the Symposium on the 100th Anniversary of the Federal Income Tax, held at Florida State University College of Law on March 1 and 2, 2013.
72
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
IV.
[Vol. 41:71
3. Simplified Asset Accounting ................................................................ N. Book-Tax Conformity for Public C Corporations....................................... O. Gratuitous Transfers ................................................................................. 1. What is a “Gift” .................................................................................... 2. Repeal § 274(b) ..................................................................................... 3. Repeal the Basis-Disallowance Rule for Gifts of Depreciated-Value Property ............................................................................................... 4. Repeal the § 691(c) Deduction and the § 1015(d)(6) Basis Adjustment .......................................................................................... 5. Grantor Trusts ..................................................................................... 6. A “Simple Estate” Income Tax Regime ................................................ 7. Repeal the Rule that the In-Kind Satisfaction of a Fixed-Sum Bequest is a Deemed Sale of the Property............................................ P. Transactional Accounting Issues ............................................................... 1. Basis of In-Kind Income Items ............................................................. 2. Repeal § 1341 ....................................................................................... Q. Portfolio Accounting for Publicly Traded Securities ................................. 1. Mechanics............................................................................................. 2. No Disallowance of Portfolio Net Loss ................................................. 3. Partial Repeal of § 1014 ....................................................................... TAX REFORMS CONTRIBUTING TO SIMPLIFICATION ......................................... A. Tax Expenditures ....................................................................................... B. Capital Gains ............................................................................................. 1. Plan A: Eliminate Special Rates for Net Capital Gain ....................... 2. Plan B: Simplify the Benefits Conferred on Net Capital Gain ............ 3. Eliminate the Category of “Collectibles” Gain ..................................... 4. Full Depreciation Recapture for Real Estate ....................................... 5. Repeal § 1231 ....................................................................................... C. Losses on Sales and Exchanges ................................................................. 1. Restrictions on the Current Deductibility of Net Transactional Losses ................................................................................................... 2. Simplifying the Rules Defining Gains and Losses Subject to the Anti-Cherry-Picking Rule .................................................................... D. The Personal Deductions ........................................................................... 1. Residential Mortgage Interest .............................................................. 2. State and Local Taxes .......................................................................... 3. Personal Casualty and Theft Losses .................................................... 4. Charitable Contributions ..................................................................... 5. Medical Care ........................................................................................ 6. Costs of Tax Planning and Compliance............................................... E. Personal Injury Recoveries......................................................................... F. Retirement Savings .................................................................................... 1. Qualified Tax-Deferral Retirement Plans ............................................ (a) Complexity in the Service of an Ineffective Policy Design ............ (b) Plan A: Mandatory Retirement Contributions ............................. (c) Plan B: Tax Subsidies at the Margin ........................................... (d) Defined Benefit Plans ................................................................... (e) Mandatory Annuity Pay-Outs Under All Tax-Favored Plans ...... (f) Other Issues ................................................................................... (g) Roth IRAs ..................................................................................... 2. Nonqualified Tax-Deferral Arrangements ........................................... (a) Restricted Property Transfers and Funded Nonqualified Plans . (b) Non-Funded Plans ....................................................................... 3. Rabbi Trusts ........................................................................................
99 99 100 100 100 101 101 102 103 104 104 104 105 106 106 107 108 108 108 109 109 110 110 110 111 112 112 113 114 114 115 117 118 120 121 122 123 123 123 127 127 129 129 130 130 131 131 133 134
2013]
V.
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS G. Foreign Income of U.S. Nationals.............................................................. 1. Repeal the Exclusion for Foreign-Source Earned Income.................... 2. Expand the Simple Version of the Foreign Tax Credit ........................ H. Entity Taxation .......................................................................................... 1. Mandatory Pass-Through Regime for All Non-Publicly Traded Business Entities ................................................................................. 2. A Simplified Pass-Through Regime..................................................... 3. Nondeductibility of C Corporation Interest ......................................... 4. Eliminate Capital Gains Treatment of Dividends............................... 5. Repeal the Earnings and Profits Apparatus ........................................ CONCLUSION ...................................................................................................
73 134 134 135 136 136 137 138 138 139 141
I. INTRODUCTION This Article proposes various moves for simplification of the task of computing the tax base under the individual income tax, 1 with a principal view of making the income tax capable of compliance by “ordinary” individuals without the aid of tax preparation software or outside assistance. 2 Part II offers a brief overview of the pros and cons of simplification as a reform agenda or project. Part III deals with simplification moves that can be carried out independently of conventional tax reform proposals. Part IV considers simplification benefits that are attendant upon plausible tax reform (or revenue-raising) proposals. Part V offers some concluding remarks. II. SIMPLIFICATION AS AN AGENDA An obvious aim of simplifying the federal income tax is to save on taxpayer compliance costs, especially time spent on filling out tax returns. It is reported that individual taxpayers spend not insignificant amounts of money and more than twenty-four hours on filing federal tax returns. 3 Such short-form tax returns as currently exist, the Form 1040-EZ and the Form 1040-A, do not appear to simplify matters significantly because taxpayers would still need to consider 1. Simplification of rate structures (such as moving to a flat rate system) is not a “simplification” issue, since applying a tiered rate structure to the tax base is a simple arithmetic operation easily performed by a computer, including a program found on a website. Complexity in the rate structure should be equated with lack of transparency (disguised changes in marginal rates), such as occur with the deduction phase-out provisions found in I.R.C §§ 68 and 151(d)(3), both of which were revived by the American Taxpayer Relief Act of 2012, Pub. L. No. 112-240, 126 Stat. 2313 (2013). 2. Previous collections of simplification proposals are found in AM. LAW INST. ET AL., FEDERAL INCOME TAX SIMPLIFICATION (Charles H. Gustafson ed., 1979); STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, 107TH CONG., STUDY OF THE OVERALL STATE OF THE FEDERAL TAX SYSTEM AND RECOMMENDATIONS FOR SIMPLIFICATION, PURSUANT TO SECTION 8022(3)(B) OF THE INTERNAL REVENUE CODE OF 1986 (Comm. Print 2001). 3. William Gale & Benjamin Harris, Tax Simplification: How Costly Is Complexity?, TAX POLICY CTR., http://www.taxpolicycenter.org/briefing-book/improve/simplification/ cost.cfm (last updated Dec. 14, 2007) (reporting and extrapolating from other studies).
74
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
items omitted from these returns in order to determine eligibility to file them.4 Computerized tax preparation services save on computation time (at a cost), but still require the entering of all relevant data and (often) the plowing through of checklists relating to numerous obscure deductions and tax credits. Ownership of rental property (or property partly devoted to business use) alone adds significantly to taxpayer burdens.5 Complex and data-heavy tax returns also place burdens on government enforcement agencies. A second aim of simplification is to render taxpayers’ perception of the federal income tax as being internally coherent, and not as a Christmas tree showering an array of goodies (and baddies) to the highest (and lowest) bidders. Simplification is offered here as a “good government” project that would increase taxpayer morale and compliance rates through improved transparency and comprehensibility. A third aim would be to reduce dispute-resolution costs. The way to further this aim is to clarify borderlines and reduce (where possible) the necessity for factual inquiries. The opposite of simplification is complexity, and complexity in turn partly results from the dynamics of political economy, which produces a legislative output wherein it is easier to deliver government programs through the tax system (sometimes referred to as “tax expenditure” provisions) as opposed to the “normal” means of direct federal subsidies or regulation. Politics also dictates that provisions benefitting political constituencies be numerous (perhaps to the point of overlap and duplication) and salient,6 whereas provisions cutting back on taxpayer benefits be obscure and backhanded.7 Addi4. The Form 1040-EZ is for joint and single filers with no dependents, who have no investment income (other than up to $1500 of interest income), no business, rent, or royalty income, and who do not itemize. Form 1040EZ: Income Tax Return for Single and Joint Filers with No Dependents, INTERNAL REVENUE SERVICE (2012), available at www.irs.gov/pub/irs-pdf/f1040ez.pdf. The Form 1040-EZ includes a line for the earned income credit (EIC), which requires a worksheet computation. Id. The Form 1040-A is a two page form that resembles the Form 1040 but with no schedules (except possibly Schedule B and Schedule 8812) and certain deductions and credits omitted. Form 1040A: U.S. Individual Income Tax Return, INTERNAL REVENUE SERVICE (2012), available at www.irs.gov/pub/irs-pdf/f1040a.pdf. These forms may lull taxpayers into ignoring relevant items (income, deductions, and credits) that should be reported and which might well reduce net tax liability. 5. Such property entails computation of depreciation, allocation of deductions to rental or business activity, and disallowance (or limitation) under I.R.C. §§ 183, 280A, 280F, 465, 469. 6. For a public choice theory “take” on tax legislation, see Richard L. Doernberg & Fred S. McChesney, Doing Good or Doing Well?: Congress and the Tax Reform Act of 1986, 62 N.Y.U. L. REV. 891 (1987) (book review). 7. For example, instead of repealing the itemized deductions, said deductions are diluted by floors (see I.R.C. §§ 67, 165(h), 213(a)), ceilings (see id. § 170(b)), phase-outs (see id. § 68), and overlays (the Alternative Minimum Tax, see id. §§ 55(a), 56(b)(1)). See also statutes cited supra note 5 for provisions diluting deductions with regard to rental or business use of property.
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
75
tionally, certain groups possess a vested interest in tax complexity.8 This Article, however, does not address the political obstacles to simplification. Nevertheless, certain simplification measures proposed herein might be immune from one or more of the political dynamics just described. At the technical level, complexity in tax is mostly driven by a faith in “accuracy.” Accuracy is in part a function of one’s preferred concept of income. Thus, if one thinks that “income” requires adjustment for such items as sales taxes, casualty losses, medical expenses, unrealized gains and losses, imputed income, and off-market benefits, then the computation of the tax base becomes more complex than in the absence of such adjustments. Many of these adjustments are justified under the framework of welfare economics (“welfarism”), which posits that the tax base should be adjusted directly or indirectly (through proxies) for non-market changes in individual utility or well-being. However, a comprehensive welfarist tax system is impossible (apart from political resistance to a welfarist state), because welfarism ultimately refers to individual subjectivity. Determinations of subjective states entail enormous transaction costs and are unreliable. Proxies for subjective states are crude and insufficient. Finally, welfarist adjustments to the tax base are piecemeal. 9 A partial and flawed welfarist tax base must be unfair in terms of taxing “likes” (even in terms of well-being) alike. Accuracy also entails a belief that even realized changes in wealth can be accurately accounted for, i.e., that capital expenditures can be distinguished from expenses, that depreciation and capital recovery can be accurately measured, that costs of income production can be distinguished from costs of personal consumption, and that accrual accounting is more accurate than cash accounting. 10 The mere list of these issues conjures up complex Code provisions and issues of a factual nature that are frequently disputed and litigated.
8. See Liz Day, How Maker of TurboTax Fought Free, Simple Tax Filing, PROPUBLI(Mar. 26, 2013, 4:00 A.M.), http://www.propublica.org/article/how-the-maker-ofturbotax-fought-free-simple-tax-filing; Evan Halper, Maker of Tax Software Opposes State Filing Help; The Government’s Offer to Fill Out Forms Is a Hit with Poor and Elderly, but Not with Intuit, L.A. TIMES, May 5, 2006, at A1. 9. The exclusion for physical personal injuries, I.R.C. § 104(a)(2), is a good example of a piecemeal welfarist tax provision, tied to the objective fact of a monetary recovery. Non-compensated injuries do not (and practically could not) give rise to reductions in the tax base. 10. Accounting for changes in wealth could, in theory, be rendered accurate under a mark-to-market (“accretion”) income tax, but only if valuation itself is accurate—an unattainable goal. In the case of unique assets, accurate valuation is an illusion: only an actual sale can reveal what a willing buyer would pay to a willing seller. An accretion income tax does not exist anywhere on the globe, and the chance that it would be enacted in the United States appears remote. CA
76
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
At some point, accuracy is not worth the effort. 11 Simplicity requires that the individual income tax base be constituted by objective outcomes (not estimates or conjectures) that can be attributed to individual taxpayers without government intrusions into personal privacy. That is, market transactions (outcomes) should be the data set for figuring the tax base of individuals. Simplicity also possesses a cognitive aspect, as distinguished from a mechanical aspect. What is desirable is an internally coherent tax base principle that relates to the taxation function of raising revenue. The principle should be graspable by non-sophisticated individual taxpayers. The principle that is most compatible with mechanical and cognitive simplicity—as well as substantive tax fairness—is what I call “objective ability to pay” (as distinguished from a “utility” concept of sacrifice), determinable on an annual basis. This principle translates into an income tax base constituted by net realized increases in wealth (disregarding realized decreases in wealth that are not costs of income production). However, the task of justifying and elaborating upon the concept of an objective ability-to-pay tax base is a separate project in itself, and accordingly this Article will generally attempt to maintain a primary focus of simplification without pushing a particular tax reform agenda. III. SIMPLIFICATION WITHOUT REFORM The proposals discussed below do not, in the main, entail significant policy or revenue-driven changes. Familiar “tax reform” options that would advance the simplification agenda are discussed in Part IV. Items that appear to serve no purpose at all are discussed in this Part. A. Taxpayer Relief from Arithmetic Since the IRS performs the necessary calculations in reviewing returns, taxpayers should be allowed to forego this task (in whole or in part), if they so desire. A taxpayer would be allowed to attempt the calculations herself for informational purposes. 12
11. See generally Louis Kaplow, Accuracy, Complexity, and the Income Tax, 14 J.L. ECON. & ORG. 61 (1998) (assuming that accuracy entails complexity, and providing framework for a trade-off between simplicity and accuracy). 12. A more comprehensive version of this approach is the pro-forma return; the government itself prepares a tax return, reviewable by the taxpayer, in which all known thirdparty data is entered, with the government performing the tax calculation. See, e.g., Joseph Bankman, Simple Filing for Average Citizens: The California ReadyReturn, 107 TAX NOTES 1431 (2005).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
77
B. Checklists for Tax-Benefits Eligibility Requirements Where possible, the eligibility requirements for a tax benefit should take the form of a checklist allowing a “yes” or “no” answer for each eligibility requirement. These checklists would mostly be located in the instructions to the Form 1040 and other schedules and forms, and would render these instructions more user-friendly. C. Tax Credits to be “Off Tax” Tax credits for individuals (other than the foreign tax credit and credits for income taxes already paid by the taxpayer) are government subsidies. As subsidies delivered by the IRS, these credits should be dealt with on a separate page of the return or otherwise clearly separated (or even detached) from the tax calculation itself. Subsidy-type credits should not be labeled as “reductions in tax liability” or “tax credits,” but instead they should be called “federal government payments” that happen to be obtainable as an adjunct to filing a federal income tax return. Additions to tax liability can take the form of other federal taxes, tax-related interest, fines, penalties, and refunds of excessive tax credits,13 and should be similarly segregated from the computation of the income tax. D. Rate Schedules Since the rates and brackets involve political decisions, no opinion is advanced herein as to the rate schedules themselves. Nevertheless, it can be observed that moving to a single rate (or to fewer rate brackets) is not, by and large, a significant simplification move in itself, especially if taxpayers are not required to perform calculations. E. Subsistence Income Subsistence income should not be taxed,14 but exempting subsistence income can be done in a much simpler fashion than under current law. Since subsistence levels appear to vary only with the size of a household, a simple table could be designed to set out the subsistence allowance per size of household. 13. Additions to tax are labeled “Other Taxes” on page 2 of the Form 1040. Form 1040A: U.S. Individual Income Tax Return, supra note 4, at 2. 14. Income up to the subsistence level is unable to contribute to the government under liberal political theory. The centerpiece of a super-simplification proposal made in Michael J. Graetz, Essay, Taxes That Work: A Simple American Plan, 58 FLA. L. REV. 1043 (2006), is to raise the exemption level of the income tax far above the subsistence level to $100,000 (or more) and to make up the lost revenue through a value-added tax, which is a tax on business activity. This Article assumes that no significant new federal tax would be enacted, so that simplification would be confined to the individual income tax, where the notion of off-the-bottom allowances has been widely accepted.
78
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
1. Eliminate the Standard Deduction The standard deduction (roughly $6000 per individual) 15 serves two purposes that can be better carried out separately. The first function is to constitute, along with the personal exemption (roughly $4000 per individual), 16 a universal low-income allowance; but this function can be better served by increasing the personal exemption itself. The second function is to provide a floor under “itemized deductions” as a group,17 which (1) eases accounting burdens and (2) avoids duplication with the off-the-bottom allowances. However, this function can be performed better by separate floors under certain deductions. 2. The Personal Exemption Amount The personal exemption amount should approximate the subsistence level of income for a household consisting of one individual. A starting point for calculating subsistence levels is the official poverty level, but that amount could be rounded up and adjusted to take into account such universal costs as state, local, and gasoline taxes and the cost of medical care. A reasonable figure (for 2014) might be $12,000 for an unmarried individual. An issue is what the personal exemption amount should be for married couples under the present system, which allows married couples to file joint returns for aggregate taxable income. Statistics indicate that the subsistence level is a function of the number of persons in a common household, and does not depend on the age of household members or whether the “second” member of the household is married to the “first” member.18 Proceeding on the (optimistic) assumption that the tax law is to be adapted to the household concept, then, if the personal exemption for an individual is set at
15. The standard deduction for 2013 eliminated tax on the first $12,200 of taxable income for a married couple filing jointly, $6100 for an unmarried individual (or married person filing separately), and $8950 for a “head of household.” Rev. Proc. 2013-15, 2013-5 I.R.B. 444, 447-48. 16. In 2013, the personal (and dependency) exemption amount was $3900 per individual. Id. at 448. Both the standard deduction amounts and the personal (and dependency) exemption amounts are indexed for inflation, resulting in increased amounts from year to year. 17. An individual takes the greater of (1) the standard deduction, see I.R.C. § 63(c), or (2) aggregate allowable itemized deductions, but not both. Id. § 63(b). The term “itemized deductions” means deductions other than (1) the standard deduction, (2) deductions listed in § 62 that are taken in arriving at adjusted gross income, and (3) the deductions for personal and dependency exemptions allowed by § 151. Id. § 63(d). 18. For 2013, the official (rounded off) poverty level as determined by the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services was $11,490 for an individual, increasing by roughly $4800 for each additional family member. Annual Update of the HHS Poverty Guidelines, 78 Fed. Reg. 5182-83 (Jan. 24, 2013).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
79
$12,000, a reasonable figure for a married couple living together would be $18,000. The scheme suggested immediately above might be politically “off the table” on the ground that it would be perceived as reintroducing a marriage penalty, 19 but this perception would be inaccurate if unmarried, committed couples occupying the same household were treated as being married. 20 In any event, if it is politically necessary that the personal exemptions for a married couple be twice that of an unmarried individual, plausible exemption amounts for 2013 would be in the neighborhood of $20,000 for a married couple and $10,000 for an unmarried person. 3. Dependency Exemption Amounts The purpose of the dependency exemption is to allow for the costs of supporting dependents. Accordingly, the dependency exemption should be a lesser amount than the augmented personal exemption for a single-person household, because the dependent is free of having to maintain a household. The current dependency exemption amount (roughly $4000) is almost the same as what the poverty-level statistics suggest is appropriate, but (again) the poverty level amount would only be a starting place for obtaining an appropriate figure. 21 A person claimed as a dependent by another should have a zero personal exemption. A personal exemption on top of the income exclusion for support received by the dependent entails a double tax benefit for subsistence to the same taxpayer. The dependency exemption, coupled with the exclusion for support received and the loss of the dependent’s personal exemption, effectively shifts the dependent’s tax existence to that of the support provider, except for the dependent’s separate economic activity. 4. The Definition of “Dependent” The tests for determining “dependent” status that involve “support provided” (by the dependent or the claimant, as the case may be), relative to total support,22 are unworkable. 23 The relevant distinction 19. Currently, the standard deduction for a married couple is twice that for an unmarried individual. See supra note 15. 20. Two unmarried taxpayers maintaining separate households would have aggregate personal exemptions of approximately $18,000, but that would presumably be justified by the fact that separate households are being maintained. 21. Annual Update of the HHS Poverty Guidelines, supra note 18, at 5183. 22. I.R.C. § 152(c)(1)(D) (“qualifying child” must not provide more than one-half of own support), (d)(1)(C) (“qualifying relative” must receive more than one-half of support from claimant). 23. Support for this purpose includes economic resources that are not gross income and that often take the form of in-kind room, board, and other items, and exclude items that are not spent on living costs. These facts are intrinsically hard to ascertain, are not
80
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
should be between dependents living in the taxpayer’s household (“household dependents”) and those that are not (“other dependents”). A person living in the taxpayer’s household should be deemed to be a household dependent 24 unless she (a) is not within a specified degree of relationship (or registered domestic partner), 25 or (b) has “income” above a certain threshold amount. 26 For this purpose, the income threshold amount should be an amount greater than the dependency exemption amount, but certainly not greater than the personal exemption amount. To be an “other dependent,” the person should be required to satisfy a somewhat stringent “relationship” test. Additionally, the claimant must have provided, by cash transfers or payments,27 an amount that exceeds the greater of the exemption amount or the putative dependent’s “income.” Finally, the person would be disqualified if (a) she is an owner of her place of abode or (b) her “income” exceeds the personal exemption amount. An issue is how “income” should be defined for each category of dependent. A possible construct would be “adjusted gross income” (AGI), plus the untaxed portion of Social Security retirement benefits and excluded interest, personal injury recoveries, non-taxable distributions from trusts and estates, and amounts received on account of disability. 5. Eliminate the Child Tax Credit This ($1000 per qualifying child) tax credit, 28 which appears to be simple on its face, is complicated by phase-out rules, the linking of refundability to the taxpayer’s earned income over $3000, and its interaction with other tax credits. The purported rationale is to augment the dependency exemptions (but only for children under the age of seventeen living in the taxpayer’s household), 29 but circumstantial public, and cannot be provided by disinterested third parties. 24. The idea is that the claimant should be deemed to have supplied value at least equal to the dependency exemption amount. 25. The purpose here is to weed out persons who cohabit for convenience or pleasure. 26. The purpose here is to weed out persons who are basically self-supporting. 27. If the taxpayer allows the putative dependent to live in a dwelling owned by the taxpayer (other than the taxpayer’s residence), the taxpayer can be deemed to have spent cash on the dependent at the rate of, say, 5% of the dwelling’s cost. 28. I.R.C. § 24(c). 29. The legislative history states only: The Committee believes that the individual income tax structure does not reduce tax liability by enough to reflect a family’s reduced ability to pay taxes as family size increases. In part, this is because over the last 50 years the value of the dependent personal exemption has declined in real terms by over one-third. The Committee believes that a tax credit for families with dependent children will reduce the individual income tax burden of those families, will better recognize the financial responsibilities of raising dependent children, and will
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
81
evidence suggests that this credit is a kind of federal “workfare” supplement for the working poor with dependent children. 30 The credit is a wasteful squandering of government revenues to the extent that it does not allow for, or subsidize, incremental costs of child care. The aims of this credit can better be accomplished by (1) aligning the dependency exemption amount with the amount necessary to support a household dependent 31 and (2) providing tax credit(s) for the working poor with children. 32 F. The Working Poor 1. No Separate Rate Schedules for Unmarried Individuals and Heads of Household The existing system providing for four categories of filing status can be easily reduced to two, namely, married couples filing jointly and everyone else. The current rate schedule for an unmarried individual is the same as for a married person filing separately up to a taxable income of about $75,000, but, above that level, two unmarried persons with evenly split incomes (and living together) pay less tax than a married couple filing jointly having the same aggregate income.33 This disparity could influence marriage decisions of high-income couples. The disparity is presumably based on economies of scale available to married couples. However, marriage status is an extremely crude indicator of economies of scale. Moreover, it is hard to justify implicit (incremental) cost-of-living allowances at high-income levels. Indeed, cost-of-living differentials that result from taxpayer choice, apart from being inscrutable to being measured on a case-by-case basis, promote family values. H.R. REP. NO. 105-148, at 310 (1997). The stated rationale suggests a deduction rather than a credit. The credit has since been liberalized so as to be available for a “qualifying child” (the taxpayer’s descendant, sibling, or sibling’s descendant) living in the taxpayer’s household but under the age of seventeen. See I.R.C. § 24(c)(1) (referencing id. § 152(c)). 30. The existing federal cash-transfer program for families with dependent children is Temporary Assistance for Needy Families (TANF), which replaced the Aid for Dependent Children (AFDC) program in 1997, the same year that the child tax credit was enacted. See Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Reconciliation Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104193, 110 Stat. 2105. TANF is designed to encourage welfare recipients to enter the workforce, and the child tax credit is refundable only if (and as) earned income (wages) exceeds $3000. See 42 U.S.C. § 601 (2006); I.R.C. § 24(d)(1), (d)(4). Since the benefit level of TANF is largely decided by the states, the child tax credit amounts to a federal supplement to TANF. 31. See supra pp. 6-7. 32. See infra pp. 8-11. 33. See I.R.C. § 1(c), (d), (f)(8), and the rate tables for 2013, published in Rev. Proc. 2013-15, 2013-5 I.R.B. 444, 445 (showing a divergence above a taxable income amount of $73,200).
82
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
should (arguably) not be taken into account at all.34 Certainly, any adjustments of this sort would complicate the system. Thus, the rate schedule for unmarried persons—which has already been partially repealed—should be wholly eliminated, so that the same rate schedule would apply both to unmarried individuals and to married individuals filing separately. A head of household is an unmarried individual with one or more dependents living at home. 35 Both the head-of-household rate schedule 36 and the head-of-household standard deduction 37 are more favorable than that of an unmarried individual (but not as favorable as for a married couple filing jointly). No reason exists for taxing uppermiddle-class (and wealthy) individuals at favorable rates just because they have one or more live-at-home dependents, or for why the first dependency exemption should (in effect) be significantly greater for an unmarried person with a live-at-home-dependent relative to other taxpayers with a dependent. 38 The legitimate aim of the special rate schedule to account for incremental work and child-care costs can be better accomplished by some increase in the dependency exemptions and a tax allowance for working taxpayers with live-at-home dependents (see item 3 below). 2. Replace the Child Tax Credit, the Earned Income Tax Credit, and the Household and Dependent Care Credit with a Single Dependent Care Allowance The child tax credit is not linked to any costs of child care over and above the routine support that is already deducted by reason of the dependency exemptions.39 The earned income credit (EIC) 40 is extremely complex and serves two goals—refunding part of the payroll tax and subsidizing the working poor with dependents—that can better be accomplished separately. The household and dependent care credit 41 has a clear enough purpose, but it (uniquely) requires 34. See Calvin H. Johnson, The Inequities in Cost of Living Adjustments, 28 A.B.A. SECT. TAX’N NEWS Q. 24 (2009); Michael J. McIntyre & Oliver Oldman, Taxation of the Family in a Comprehensive and Simplified Income Tax, 90 HARV. L. REV. 1573 (1977). In welfarist terms, adjustments for higher costs of living are incoherent, because the incremental monetary costs are incurred voluntarily to obtain higher non-monetary benefits. 35. I.R.C. § 2(b). 36. Id. § 1(b). 37. The head-of-household standard deduction is $8950 for 2013, compared to $6100 for other individuals. Rev. Proc. 2013-15, 2013-5 I.R.B. 444, 448 (2013). 38. A non-itemizing head of household with one dependent effectively obtains approximately an extra $3000 of allowance off the bottom relative to other taxpayers (for 2013, the precise amount is $2850, the difference between standard deductions of $8950 and $6100). See id. 39. Thus, single-earner couples obtain a windfall: a subsidy for non-existent (or wholly discretionary) expenses, such as private schooling. 40. I.R.C. § 32. 41. Id. § 21.
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
83
accounting for eligible costs, confers an unwarranted subsidy for high-income taxpayers while (as a nonrefundable credit) being useless for low income individuals, and is overly broad in allowing tax benefits for discretionary personal household expenses (e.g., housekeeping costs). All of these credits are keyed to wage income while being subject to phase-out or cut-back rules, indicating that they are aimed at those low-to-moderate income households with a wageearner and live-at-home dependents. The phase-out rules for the EIC are especially complex and kick in at low amounts of earned income (or AGI), rendering compliance difficult for that portion of the population that is likely to be poorly educated. First, a refundable credit should be available for wage earners equal to the Social Security tax rate (currently 6.2%) times earned income up to, say, $10,000, for a maximum credit of $620.42 This credit (the Wage Earner Credit, or WEC) would not be conditioned on having household dependents, but would be subject to the same phase-out rule as the Household Dependent Allowance (HDA), described below. Since dependency exemptions would already allow for the “normal” cost of supporting dependents, any additional tax benefits should be keyed to the incremental costs of caring for household dependents where the taxpayer is unable to provide the care herself by reason of being disabled or employed. 43 Thus, to be eligible for this allowance (the HDA), the taxpayer must be disabled or a full-time student, or must have worked more than, say, 1200 hours during the year. If the eligible taxpayer is married (broadly defined), the spouse must be disabled, a full-time student, or must also have worked the same minimum total hours. Additionally, the taxpayer must have at least one dependent living at home for more than, say, half the year. The live-at-home dependent should occupy a specified degree of relationship to the taxpayer and be under a certain age, disabled, or over a certain age. Design issues for the HDA abound. First, should the allowance take the form of a deduction or a tax credit? In internal-to-tax terms, any allowance off the bottom or cost of earning income should take the form of a deduction. The opposing view is that the allowance should be viewed as a government subsidy for part of the costs of in42. Topic 751 – Social Security and Medicare Withholding Rates, IRS.GOV, http://www.irs.gov/taxtopics/tc751.html (last updated Oct. 23, 2013). This is similar to the Making Work Pay credit of I.R.C. § 36A, which has expired. Also, the credit should not exceed the Social Security taxes actually paid. 43. THE PRESIDENT’S ADVISORY PANEL ON FED. TAX REFORM, SIMPLE, FAIR, AND PROGROWTH: PROPOSALS TO FIX AMERICA’S TAX SYSTEM 60 (2005), available at http://govinfo.library.unt.edu/taxreformpanel/final-report/TaxPanel_5-7.pdf, proposed a Family Credit (without phase-out) for taxpayers with certain amounts or types of income and a separate Work Credit (with phase-out).
84
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
cremental dependent care and that a refundable tax credit delivers a uniform subsidy that is not a function of the taxpayer’s marginal tax rate. Indeed, a deduction is worthless to a taxpayer having a net income below the “standard” low-income allowances. On the other hand, a refundable tax credit requires the filing of a tax return where one would not otherwise be required.44 Since the HDA would replace tax credits, the HDA would also presumably take the form of a tax credit. The eligibility requirements would be a virtual guarantee that eligible costs are incurred. Therefore, it would not be necessary to account for actual costs of incremental dependent care. Accordingly, an eligible taxpayer would be entitled to a refundable tax credit of, say, $6000 (40% of $15,000) for the first eligible dependent, with decreasing amounts for a second dependent (say, $4000), and third dependent (say, $2000). A credit of $6000 compares with the sum of: (1) a child tax credit of $1000, (2) a household and dependent care credit of $3000, 45 and (3) a $3250 (in 2013) credit for the first dependent under the EIC.46 Both the HDA and the WEC should be phased out at a uniform rate above, say, $50,000 of AGI. 47 G. The Taxable Income Computation The task of calculating the taxable income of individual taxpayers is unnecessarily convoluted and can be simplified under the proposals set forth below. 1. Equal Status Among Deductions The distinctions among various categories of deductions (§ 62 deductions, itemized deductions, and miscellaneous itemized deductions) 48 pose unnecessary (and confusing) line-drawing issues, complicate the taxable income computation, 49 and obfuscate the simple notion that taxable income equals gross income less deductions. 44. An individual income tax return is required only if gross income exceeds the sum of the personal exemption amount and the standard deduction amount. I.R.C. § 6012. 45. Id. § 21(c). This credit cannot exceed $6000 in the aggregate, however. 46. Id. § 32(b). In 2013, the maximum incremental credit for a second dependent was $2122 and for a third dependent was $672, but no additional amounts were allowed for additional dependents. See Rev. Proc. 2013-15, 2013-5 I.R.B. 444, 445 (maximum EIC for a taxpayer with one, two, or three qualified children). 47. Taxpayers with substantial income have the option of providing home care themselves. Stated differently, above a certain income level, paying for dependent care becomes a lifestyle choice. Finally, if the allowance takes the form of a tax credit, then it is wasteful to subsidize taxpayers with substantial incomes. 48. I.R.C. §§ 62(a), 63(d) (itemized deductions), 67(b) (miscellaneous itemized deductions). 49. Aggregate miscellaneous itemized deductions are subject to a 2% floor, id. § 67(a),
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
85
As noted above, the standard deduction would be removed, eliminating a major reason for having a separate category of itemized deductions. All deductions (including the personal and dependency exemptions) would be allowed in full, without phase-out rules. Floors and ceilings would attach only to certain specified deductions. Such floors and ceilings would be computed with reference to “net income,” meaning gross income reduced by the deductions (other than the personal and dependency exemptions) not subject to any floor. 2. Personal Deductions Subject to Floors The purpose of the floors under the personal deductions is to eliminate duplication with costs already deemed to be covered by the personal and dependency exemptions, so that only extraordinary costs within a certain category are eligible for additional deduction. Floors already exist under the deductions for personal casualty losses 50 and for medical expenses.51 It is appropriate to consider a floor under each of the remaining personal deductions, but the issues of repeal of and/or floors under the personal deductions are deferred to Part IV. 3. Deduction Phase-Out Rules Deduction phase-outs create hidden tax rate bubbles that lack transparency and cannot be justified under any theory of progressivity. 52 Deduction phase-outs require the filling out of a worksheet. In contrast, tax credits that are subsidies for the non-wealthy are appropriately circumscribed by phase-outs. It is not inappropriate to require a taxpayer eligible for a government subsidy to expend some effort to obtain it. 4. The Proper Function of the AMT The Alternative Minimum Tax (AMT) was originally designed to reach high-income taxpayers who paid no or little tax on account of “excess” deductions. 53 The current AMT appears to be a kind of ad hoc revenue raiser that bears no relationship to any normative concept of income, but instead, for most individual taxpayers, operates as a sort of “stealth” partial repeal of certain itemized deductions.54 and itemized deductions are subject to a phase-out rule (up to 80% thereof), id. § 68, as well as being effectively disallowed unless the aggregate amount thereof exceeds the standard deduction. See Form 1040A: U.S. Individual Income Tax Return, supra note 4. 50. I.R.C. § 165(c)(3), (h). 51. Id. § 213. 52. The American Taxpayer Relief Act of 2012, Pub. L. No. 112–240, 126 Stat. 2313 (2013), revived phase-out rules for the personal and dependency exemptions, I.R.C. § 151(d)(3), and for aggregate itemized deductions, id. § 68. 53. See H.R. REP. NO. 91-413, at 4628 (1969). 54. The AMT disallows, inter alia, the standard deduction, personal and dependency
86
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
On the merits, if a deduction is justified in the first place— particularly as it records a reduction in a taxpayer’s ability to pay— no justification exists for reducing or eliminating the deduction explicitly or implicitly. The same end can be attained by other (and more transparent) means, such as the repeal of unwarranted deductions, the imposition of floors, and the foreclosing of avenues of abuse, as is considered in Part IV. Ceilings appear to be appropriate only in the case of wholly “discretionary” personal deductions, but the only such deduction that is truly discretionary appears to be the charitable deduction,55 which is already subject to a ceiling.56 The AMT could be reformed to better accord with its original purpose, 57 but that is not a simplification issue. H. Social Security Retirement Benefits The existing rules governing the inclusion in income of Social Security retirement benefits 58 are so complex that a worksheet is required to figure out the taxable amount. 59 Also, the rules appear to be disconnected from any theory of partial exclusion. Yet a taxable amount can be figured by viewing the benefits as entailing a recovery of (all or a portion of) 60 nondeductible contributions (Social Security taxes). 61 A person’s contribution history is contained in computerized records of the Social Security Administration (SSA), and this history is periodically mailed to individuals eligible to receive retirement benefits. exemptions, state and local taxes, allowable miscellaneous itemized deductions, interest on home equity loans, and a portion of the medical expense deduction. See I.R.C. § 56(b). The first two of these are a trade-off for the generous AMT exemption amounts (in 2013, $80,800 for married couples filing jointly and $51,900 for unmarried individuals), I.R.S. News Release IR-2013-4 (Jan. 11, 2013); but perhaps the exemption amounts should be raised somewhat. For a critique of the AMT, see Linda M. Beale, Congress Fiddles While Middle America Burns: Amending the AMT (and Regular Tax), 6 FLA. TAX REV. 811 (2004). 55. I.R.C. § 170. Self-inflicted casualty losses are not deductible at all, id. § 165(h)(4), the mortgage interest deduction is limited to two residences (and contains ceilings on principal debt), id. §§ 67(b), 163(h)(4), and the medical expense deduction excludes costs of most cosmetic surgery, id. § 213(d)(9). Nevertheless, further restrictions on abuse of these deductions are considered infra Part IV. 56. Id. § 170(b). 57. The current AMT disallows the exclusion for the exercise of “incentive stock options” but leaves out of account the capital gains preference (which currently is neither an exclusion nor a deduction), as well as § 103 (tax-exempt) interest (except with respect to private activity bonds). Id. § 56(b)(3). 58. Id. § 86. 59. Form 1040: Social Security Benefits Worksheet—Lines 20a and 20b, IRS.GOV (2013), http://apps.irs.gov/app/vita/content/globalmedia/social_security_benefits_worksheet _1040i.pdf. 60. An issue is whether such basis should be reduced to account for the share of Social Security taxes used to fund the Social Security disability program. 61. An alternative simplification/reform option would be to allow a deduction for taxes paid, with inclusion of the full amount of benefits. This approach would presumably be off the table on account of current revenue considerations.
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
87
The basis recovery system can be modeled on (a) a recovery-ofbasis-first system, (b) the annuity rules of I.R.C. § 72, or (c) the tax treatment accorded to mortgage loans.62 Since the SSA has all the requisite information, it would be able to send a computer-generated tax information return to both the IRS and the taxpayer indicating the taxable portion of benefits. I. Educational Tax Benefits The multiple tax benefits for higher educational expenses variously take the form of deduction, exclusion, tax credit, and exempt trust.63 All these provisions contain overlapping definitions of qualified educational expenses, 64 and most of them contain needs tests and maximum benefit limitations. Those that do not contain needs tests and limitations on benefits (the scholarship exclusion and state tuition programs) essentially amount to exclusions for higher education obtained at a bargain price. Gift-financed education is tax-free by reason of § 102(a). 65 At a minimum, a universal definition of qualified higher education costs should apply for all purposes. Similarly, a universal needs test (phase-out for high income taxpayers) should apply in all cases in which the tax benefit is contingent on need. J. Borderline Personal/Business Deductions Categorical rules for sorting out borderline tax issues are preferable, in administrative-efficiency terms, to fact-intensive case-by-case determinations. 1. Marginal Business and Investment Deductions Generally Current § 67 disallows “miscellaneous itemized deductions” (MIDs) to the extent of 2% of AGI.66 An MID is an “itemized deduction” that is not listed in § 67(b). 67 This “anything not on the approved list” rule has deprived taxpayers of rightful deductions in unanticipated circumstances, such as plaintiff transaction costs in ob62. Any unused basis of a deceased individual would carry over to persons receiving Social Security survivor benefits. Unused basis would simply expire. 63. See I.R.C. §§ 25A (Hope and Lifetime Learning Credits), 117(a) (qualified scholarships), 221 (interest on education loans), 222 (qualified tuition and related expenses), 529 (qualified tuition plans, known as QTPs), and 530 (Coverdale education savings accounts, known as ESAs). Additionally, educational employee fringe benefits are provided for by §§ 117(d) and 127. 64. QTPs can uniquely provide for room and board costs. Id. § 529(e)(3)(B). ESAs can uniquely provide for pre-college education. Id. § 530(b)(2)(A)(ii). These features are hard to justify on policy grounds. 65. Id. § 102(a). 66. Id. § 67(b). 67. Id.
88
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
taining includible damages recoveries and deductions allowed under § 183(b)(2), discussed immediately below. 68 Recall that, under the proposal offered above, the category of “itemized deduction” would be eliminated. Instead, the floor should apply only to those specified deductions (as a group) for which Congress deems that the connection of the expense to income production is tenuous. Leading candidates are unreimbursed employee deductions and “investment” deductions that are only indirectly connected to income production and that typically involve small amounts. Indeed, to supplement such a percentage-ofAGI disallowance rule, consideration could be given to simply disallowing small-amount (say, under $200) borderline items, such as subscription costs to the Wall Street Journal. 69 2. Business Meal Costs Costs of consuming food and beverages are inherently personal and should be disallowed in full, except where the consumption is directly related to an active business of the taxpayer (such as being a food critic or a professional food preparer). 70 In the case of employer-reimbursed business meals, the employer is the real spender, and, since it is not consuming the meals itself, should not be subject to the existing 50% disallowance rule,71 which is meaningless in the case of employers that are exempt from income tax. Any perceived abuse in this area can be dealt with by deeming reimbursed employee meal costs (perhaps in excess of a specified per diem amount) as additional compensation income of the employee. 3. Business Lodging Costs Section 162(a)(2) currently allows a deduction for business-related “away from home” lodging costs. 72 However, the doctrine relating to the “away from home” requirement is confused and arbitrary.73 As with food and beverage costs, costs of lodging are inherently personal and should generally be denied unless clearly justified. One such exception would be reimbursement by an employer. (However, compensation that is disguised as a reimbursement should be treated as 68. See Jeffrey H. Kahn, Beyond the Little Dutch Boy: An Argument for Structural Change in Tax Deduction Classification, 80 WASH. L. REV. 1 (2005). 69. Cf. I.R.C. § 165(h)(1) (allowing casualty losses only to the extent they exceed $100 per casualty). 70. Under current law, 50% of business meal costs are disallowed. Id. § 274(n)(1). 71. In an employer-reimbursement situation, the 50% disallowance rule falls on the employer, not the employee. See id. § 274(n)(2)(A) (cross-referencing id. § 274(e)(3)). 72. Id. §162(a)(2). 73. E.g., JOSEPH M. DODGE ET AL., FEDERAL INCOME TAX: DOCTRINE, STRUCTURE, AND POLICY 256-68 (4th ed. 2012) (describing this doctrine).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
89
compensation.) Another would be for core-of-the-business lodging costs (say, of a travel writer). 74 Apart from the foregoing, a business deduction for lodging costs is justified insofar as (1) a plausible business reason exists for maintaining at least one residence at the base location (such as being near a place of work that is used for, say, at least sixty days a year), and (2) a clear business reason also exists for the away-from-base-location lodging. Spouses should be treated as separate taxpayers for this purpose. The “second” lodging should be “away from home” in an objective sense, such as more than 100 miles from both the taxpayer’s residence and her business office. These principles should operate to ensure that only incremental (or duplicative) business-driven lodging costs are deductible. Using these criteria, the outcomes of certain recurring scenarios would be resolved as follows: (1) Husband and wife maintain homes in different locations to be close to their respective business locations. No deduction would be allowed for either residence because no business reason exists for one spouse to reside in the other spouse’s residence. (2) Itinerant business (salespersons, pro golfers and tennis players, entertainers). In most of these cases no business reason exists to maintain a “base” home in any particular location, and therefore the deduction for lodging costs would be denied. (3) Two business locations of the same taxpayer (ongoing). Here a business reason should exist for having separate residential locations. A ski instructor in Lake Placid should not be able to deduct lodging costs in Naples, Florida, with respect to a computer consulting business that could be based anywhere. (4) Non-recurring extended leaves and reassignments. No deduction should be allowed if the taxpayer’s family accompanies the taxpayer to the temporary job location, because in that case the taxpayer can avoid duplicative housing costs by renting out the first home. Otherwise, lodging deductions would be allowed only if (and so long as) (1) the taxpayer has not changed employers (or has not been terminated), (2) has not purchased a home in the temporary location, and (3) could reasonably expect to return to her base home location at the end of the “away” period. However, “away from home” status would expire at the end of the first full calendar year following the year of taking up residence at the second location.
74. Such a business might be a not-for-profit activity under I.R.C. § 183, however.
90
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
On no account should depreciation be allowed on a taxpayer’s principal residence as defined in § 121, 75 because depreciation (by reducing basis) creates tax-favored gain.76 4. Not-for-Profit Activities Section 183(a) disallows all deductions from “not-for-profit activities,” but § 183(b)(2) allows deductions to the extent of the income from any such activity.77 (a) Accounting Under present law, it is necessary to account for the costs giving rise to the deductions that initially are allowed by § 183(b)(2), because at least some § 183(b)(2) deductions are then subject to disallowance as miscellaneous itemized deductions, and depreciation allowed under § 183(b)(2) reduces the basis of taxpayer-owned assets.78 Accordingly, depreciation must be calculated (and perhaps pro-rated between personal and not-for-profit use), and then it needs to be determined what portion of the depreciation is allowed under § 183(b)(2) after considering other deductions allowable under § 183(b)(2). 79 Accounting for such depreciation and attendant basis reductions is not worth the effort, especially in instances such as hunting, fishing, prospecting, amateur artistic ventures, amateur inventing, and sporadic renting of personal-use property. Therefore, § 183 should be reconstituted so as to disallow depreciation (and other cost-recovery deductions) completely with respect to any asset used in a not-for-profit activity. It follows that no basis adjustments would be required for such assets on account of depreciation (and cost recovery) deductions. Other income-production costs would be allowed under § 183(b)(2) up to the amount of gross income 75. I.R.C. § 121(a) generally excludes up to $500,000 of gain on a taxpayer’s personal residence, defined as a residence that the taxpayer has used as her primary residence for 730 days (“periods aggregating two years or more”) out of the last five years of ownership. However, only gain attributable to principal residence use (after 2008) qualifies for the exclusion. See id. § 121(b)(4). This rule renders it difficult to obtain full exclusions for more than one residence of a taxpayer. 76. Under present law, the depreciation is allowed and the gain resulting from such depreciation is included as unrecaptured § 1250 capital gain, subject to a maximum rate of 25% under § 1(h)(1)(D), rather than as excluded gain. Id. § 121(d)(6). It would be easier to disallow the depreciation and forego the basis adjustments. 77. Actually, § 183(b)(2) allows deductions that would otherwise require a business or investment nexus to the extent that the gross income from the activity exceeds deductions (such as property taxes, mortgage interest, and casualty losses allocable to the activity) that do not require a business or investment nexus. Id. § 183(b)(2). The principal effect of this rule is to remove the personal deductions from the possibility of § 183(a) disallowance. The secondary effect is to (possibly) reduce the deductions allowed by § 183(b)(2). 78. Id. § 1016(a)(2). 79. See Treas. Reg. § 1.183-1(b).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
91
from the activity (reduced by allowable personal deductions). Loss carryovers should continue to be disallowed. The net effect of these changes would be to simplify accounting greatly under § 183(b). In most cases, § 183 would operate to allow the taxpayer simply to ignore income and deductions with respect to not-for-profit activities. (b) Definition of “Not-for-Profit Activity” The category of “not-for-profit activity”—which triggers § 183— has been often narrowly construed by the courts to allow marginal activities to operate as tax shelters.80 The factual nature of the § 183 inquiry encourages taxpayers to frequently litigate the matter 81 with the knowledge that penalties are unlikely. The multi-factor test contained in the regulations 82 invites unpredictable judging. The worst abuses in this area involve real estate used in farming and ranching activities. 83 If the multi-factor approach is retained, § 183 should be amended so that the possibility of appreciation in property used in, or which is the location of, an activity shall not be taken into account as indicating a profit motive for the activity being scrutinized. Treating the appreciation potential of an asset used in a marginal activity as indicating that the activity itself is for profit is to let the tail wag the dog.84 Additionally, a stronger standard could be imposed for overriding the presumption that an activity generating a series of losses is a not-for-profit activity, such as one of “clear and convincing evidence.” An alternative to the “factor” approach would be, as a default rule, to treat any activity as a not-for-profit activity if (a) the activity is not carried on through a C corporation, 85 (b) the activity involves any meaningful element of what people normally consider to be pleasure or recreation for the taxpayer, or (c) the activity involves use of a taxpayer’s residence (a topic separately considered immediately below). Exceptions could be carved out, e.g., for activities that become profitable for a certain period, that exceed a certain gross revenue amount, that generate losses only because of favorable tax account80. See, e.g., Engdahl v. Commissioner, 72 T.C. 659 (1979), acq., 1979-2 C.B. 1; Fields v. Commissioner, 1981 T.C.M. (P-H) 1981-550, at 2114 (1981). 81. Annotations of reported § 183 cases occupy seventy-four pages of Standard Federal Tax Reports. See 2013-4 Stand. Fed. Tax Rep. (CCH) ¶ 12,170 at 26,896-969. 82. See Treas. Reg. § 1.183-2(b) (listing nine factors). 83. Discussions of I.R.C. § 183 are found in ROBERT W. WOOD, 548-2ND TAX MANAGEMENT PORTFOLIOS: HOBBY LOSSES (2d ed. 2012); PAUL R. MCDANIEL ET AL., FEDERAL INCOME TAXATION 595-609 (6th ed. 2008). 84. Personal use of an appreciation-potential asset has always defeated loss and expense deductions apart from I.R.C. § 183. See, e.g., Austin v. Commissioner, 298 F.2d 583 (2d Cir. 1962). Section 183 was not intended to reverse prior law on this point. See I.R.C. § 183(c). 85. Losses of a C corporation are confined to the corporation and do not pass through to individual shareholders.
92
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
ing rules (such as expensing research costs), or that present other objective indicators of a serious profit-making intention (such as acquiring technical expertise and serious marketing efforts). 5. Rental or Business Use of Personal Residence Section 280A, dealing with business and rental use of a taxpayer’s residence, not only potentially overlaps with § 183, 86 but it also resembles § 183 as to its operation, 87 save for the following variances: (1) instead of a for-profit fact test, the triggering mechanism is the objective one of non-residential (commercial) use of a taxpayer’s residence; 88 (2) for uses other than certain specified exclusive business uses or rental use (for more than fourteen days), deductions (other than personal deductions) are wholly disallowed; 89 (3) in the case of the specified exclusive business uses or rental use, the allowed amount is computed in the same way as under § 183 but with further disallowance in an amount equal to activity deductions not attributable to such use, but with carry-forward of disallowed losses; 90 (4) certain rentals of a principal residence escape § 280A;91 and (5), if the residence is rented for less than fifteen days, the gross rental income is excluded and for-profit deductions disallowed. 92 Apart from the statutory complexity of § 280A and its overlap with § 183, accounting under § 280A is burdensome, and the “exclusive business use” test of § 280A(c)(1) cannot be enforced without governmental intrusions into privacy. Residential property subject to significant personal use is unlikely to depreciate on account of wear and tear, as the owner will be strongly motivated to keep the property in good condition. (a) Integrate the Rental Aspect of § 280A with § 183 In the case of a rental of a residence, the likelihood is that the rental is a device to pay some of the costs of carrying property that was primarily acquired for personal use, or to extract some cash for what is basically a house-sitting function of the tenant. Under such
86. Not-for-profit rental or other activity in a personal residence could fall under both provisions. Section 280A(f)(3) appears to say that the operating rules of § 280A take precedence but that non-profit years can count for purposes of the § 183 presumption. See I.R.C. § 280A(f)(3). Section 280A also potentially overlaps with § 469 (dealing with losses from passive activities, including rental activities), and here again § 280A takes precedence. See id. § 469(j)(10). 87. Personal deductions are not disallowed, id. § 280A(b), but they reduce the amount that can be deducted (if at all) with respect to the use, id. § 280A(c)(5). 88. Id. § 280A(a). 89. See id. 90. See id. § 280A(c). 91. Id. 92. Id. § 280A(g).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
93
circumstances, it cannot be assumed that the rental is at arm’s length for a market-rate rental. Accordingly, the rental use of a residence of the taxpayer should be treated as a per se not-for-profit activity, subject to the mechanical rules of § 183(b), including the no-carryover rule and disallowance of depreciation on buildings and furnishings. The § 183 approach should not apply in cases where the personal use is insignificant or a for-profit motive is likely to exist. Possible scenarios deserving of an exception include: (1) rental for more than, say, 300 days in a year at a fair rental, 93 and (2) personal use for less than fifteen days a year coupled with at least 185 days of rental use under management by a professional rental agent. The existing rule that ignores both rental income and deductions if rental use is less than fifteen days a year 94 is overly generous, as very high daily rentals can be obtained in desirable locations and for special events (such as the Olympic Games, bowl games, football weekends, and the Santa Fe Indian Market). In the case of de minimis rental use, none of the costs of owning or maintaining the residence are truly related to the obtaining of rents, and therefore the rents should be included with no offsetting deductions. Rents (and deductions) should be ignored only if the rents are less than, say, $500 a year. (b) Disallowance of Deductions for Costs of a Residence Used in a Business Non-residential uses of a residence are likely undertaken out of personal convenience, not business necessity, and (in most cases) it could not be shown that the business-use space within the residence would not have been acquired for personal reasons. The “exclusive business use” test is unenforceable, as the typical home office can also serve as a media room, a den, a library, an extra bedroom, and a place for personal computing and bill paying. However, the mechanical rule of § 183(b) does not make sense here because costs allocable to the residence do not generate any income directly. Therefore, the appropriate solution in this scenario is simply to disallow not only depreciation but also general residence-related costs (such as utility costs and general house repairs). Total disallowance is consistent with the general tax approach to dual-purpose costs generally.95 This 93. Websites such as Zillow.com post estimated rental values of virtually all properties in the United States. 94. I.R.C. § 280A(g). 95. See, e.g., Commissioner v. Flowers, 326 U.S. 465 (1946) (commuting to work); Welch v. Helvering, 290 U.S. 111 (1933) (costs of acquiring human capital); Wrightsman v. United States, 428 F.2d 1316 (Ct. Cl. 1970) (costs relating to personal-use property with high appreciation potential); Smith v. Commissioner, 40 B.T.A. 1038 (B.T.A. 1939) (child
94
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
approach would obviate the need for allocations of gross income and deductions to the business use of the home. Here, the deduction-disallowance rule would be waived for: (1) deductions not related to the residence but related to the business activity, (2) deductions relating to in-residence non-transportable business property and supplies not adaptable for personal use (such as technical equipment and chemicals), and (3) separate structures (or attached structures that are not adaptable to personal use, such as art studios) used exclusively in the taxpayer’s trade or business. Of course, the “business” in question could itself be a not-for-profit activity subject to § 183. (c) Travel Expenses to Maintain a Residence Independently of the foregoing, the Code should be amended to disallow travel expenses relating to property used as a personal residence by the taxpayer for more than, say, fourteen days a year. Such property’s location reflects the taxpayer’s desire to visit that location, and travel expenses thereto can be assumed to be personal recreational expenses. 6. Tangible Personal Property Available for Personal Use The IRS is in no position to monitor the bona fide (non-rental) business use of items such as computers, printers, cell phones, tablets, vehicles, and other (movable) tangible property that (a) is not permanently located on the taxpayer’s business premises and (2) is available for personal use. Some of these items are currently treated as “listed property” subject to § 280F, but that section still allows deductions for depreciation and other deductions with respect to certain listed property with more than 50% of personal use. Given that even employers have difficulty in enforcing a businessuse-only rule for employees using employer property of this nature (even property located on the employer’s premises), it is wholly unreasonable to expect the IRS to enforce the distinction between business and personal use where the taxpayer receives no rental income from the property. Accordingly, deductions with respect to these items should simply be disallowed, period. The Treasury should be authorized to issue regulations allowing exceptions for situations where the IRS is confident that the property is subject to no more than de minimis personal use.
care to enable one to work); Rev. Rul. 70-474, 1970-2 C.B. 35 (work clothing adaptable to personal use).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
95
7. Credit Card Interest The IRS cannot reasonably be expected to monitor a taxpayer’s allocation of interest on credit card debt among the various categories of interest. Accordingly, such interest should be wholly disallowed unless the card is exclusively devoted to business use. K. Cancellation-of-Debt Income The courts and IRS appear to be extending the concept of cancellation-of-debt (COD) income to situations where the individual has no real increase in wealth or ability to pay. 96 Reigning in the concept of COD income to an appropriate extent can be viewed as being in the nature of “clarification of doctrine,” which would advance the cause of taxpayer comprehension and reduce unexpected (and unpleasant) taxpayer involvement with the system. 97 For purposes of this discussion, “COD income” refers to a situation where a debt disappears by operation of law (such as the running of the statute of limitations), action of the creditor, or agreement between the debtor and creditor. 98 COD income should exist only where the taxpayer is enriched by the borrowing (or credit) transaction as a whole.99 The paradigm COD scenario is where the taxpayer borrows cash and is relieved of having to pay it back. COD income should not arise in cases where a mere liability, unrelated to the taxpayer’s obtaining cash or property on credit, is cancelled or forgiven. 100 Examples are fines, penalties, tax liabilities, child support obligations, and charges for money, goods, or services never obtained by the taxpayer. In these cases, the “liability” is a mere prediction of a future expense or loss, and the avoidance of even an anticipated future decrease in wealth is not income. Second, COD income should not arise on the forgiveness of purchase money debt in cases where the taxpayer still owns the acquired property. Such a rule already exists in § 108(e)(5) for two-party pur96. See Payne v. Commissioner, 95 T.C.M. (CCH) 1253 (2008), aff’d, 357 F. App’x 734 (8th Cir. 2009) (per curiam), cert. denied, 131 S. Ct. 151 (2010); Hahn v. Commissioner, 93 T.C.M. (CCH) 1055 (2007) (forgiveness of earned interest). 97. I.R.C. § 108(a) avoids current inclusion of COD income in certain cases, but at the cost of reducing such favorable tax attributes as net operating losses carryovers and basis. See id. § 108(b). It is doubtful that an ordinary individual taxpayer would be able to comprehend or comply with this approach. 98. The term does not refer to satisfaction of a taxpayer’s debt or liability by the taxpayer or by a third party, debt cancellations that are means of paying for goods or services provided by the debtor to the creditor, or erroneous deduction accruals by accrual method taxpayers (or other scenarios that involve application of the tax benefit rule). 99. For other commentary along similar lines, see generally Richard C.E. Beck, Cancellation of Debt and Other Incidental Items of Income: Puritan Tax Rules in the U.S., 49 N.Y.L. SCH. L. REV. 695 (2004). 100. Older cases support this view. See, e.g., Commissioner v. Rail Joint Co., 61 F.2d 751 (2d Cir. 1932).
96
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
chase money debt, and it should be extended to three-party purchase money debt.101 In this type of case, the taxpayer never received cash to spend freely. Rather, the taxpayer is committing herself to pay the purchase price in future installments. Instead of the taxpayer having COD income, the basis of the property should be reduced with recapture of excessive depreciation deductions. Here, the taxpayer is merely paying a reduced amount for the property. The typical application of this approach would be to a renegotiation downwards of a residential mortgage. Taking the foregoing a step further, COD income should not arise by reason of avoiding consumer debt, including unpaid interest or rental obligations. The rationale (again) is that the taxpayer is paying a reduced price for consumption and that arm’s length bargain purchases of consumption do not give rise to income. 102 However, third-party credit card debt is distinguishable, because it essentially entails a loan of cash to the cardholder followed by an immediate cash payment to the merchant. 103 Thus, a reduction in bank credit card debt is true COD income because the taxpayer has been enriched in tax terms. L. Alimony vs. Child Support Current law allows a transactional election between two tax regimes concerning the payment of cash from one divorced spouse to another: (1) if several statutory requirements are complied with to constitute the payments as “tax alimony,” the payments are deductible by the payor and includible by the payee, or (2) otherwise, as the default rule, the payments are ignored by both payor and payee. These alternatives are supposed to be independent of state law. However, the requirement for tax alimony that the payments must terminate on the death of the payee spouse has resulted in entanglement with state law,104 as has the rule that a label of “child support” (possibly imposed by a court regardless of the parties’ intentions) also negates characterization as tax alimony. Additionally, unsophisticated divorce lawyers are often ignorant of the tax rules and their implications.
101. The IRS views this scenario as giving rise to COD income. See Rev. Rul. 91-31, 1991-1 C.B. 19. 102. In some cases, COD income is avoided under the disputed-debt doctrine of current law. See Preslar v. Commissioner, 167 F.3d 1323 (10th Cir. 1999) (holding there is no COD income where dispute is over value received). 103. Rev. Rul. 78-38, 1978-1 C.B. 68. It would be virtually impossible to allocate any reduction in bank credit card debt to particular purchases. 104. See, e.g., Preston v. Commissioner, 209 F.3d 1281 (11th Cir. 2000); Ribera v. Commissioner, 73 T.C.M. (CCH) 1807 (1997).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
97
The default rule should be that cash payments from one ex-spouse to another pursuant to an instrument of divorce or separation should be deductible by the payor and includible by the payee, regardless of state law, what the payments are called, or whether they can survive the payee spouse’s death. 105 A deduction/inclusion scheme would accord with the ability-to-pay principle. The payor spouse is typically in a higher tax bracket than the payee spouse, meaning that larger payments (than otherwise) can be made, leaving both parties better off after tax. Economically, there is virtually no difference between cash transfers labeled as alimony or as child support, as only rarely is the payee spouse held to account for misuse of the funds. The payee spouse would be entitled to any available dependency exemption. The spouses could jointly make an election into a no-deduction/noinclusion rule, in which case the payor would have superior rights to the dependency exemption. Exceptions to the deduction/inclusion scheme could lie for frontloaded payments, payments that look like they are in lieu of a property transfer, or payments that have the effect of a property purchase (which are to be disregarded under § 1041). M. Small Business Tax Accounting This proposal would allow certain small business taxpayers (however defined) to elect to use cash accounting for inventory and other items, thereby giving them the opportunity to fill out their tax returns without resorting to accountants and tax return preparers. 1. Expand Use of the Cash Method A business is currently required to use the accrual method if it (a) keeps its books according to financial accounting principles,106 (b) carries inventories, 107 or (c) is required by statute to do so. 108 Whatever might be said for accrual accounting for purposes of financial statements, it is hard to see how cash accounting can misstate income for tax purposes, as a general matter. 109 The tax base is an an105. If the payee is not the ex-spouse, the same rules should apply unless the payee is an exempt entity or non-U.S. taxpayer, in which case the payor would forego the deduction but be eligible to claim the dependency exemption. 106. I.R.C. § 446(a), (c)(2). 107. Treas. Reg. § 1.446-1(c)(2)(i). 108. See I.R.C. §§ 447, 448. 109. The legislative history to § 448 lamely states that the accrual method better conforms to financial accounting principles (especially the “matching principle”) than the cash method. No abuses of the cash method are cited. See STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, 99TH CONG., GENERAL EXPLANATION OF THE TAX REFORM ACT OF 1986 474-75 (Comm. Print 1987). On the merits, it might be said that trade receivables received on the sale of goods and services are an “accession to wealth,” but the current income tax is a realization income tax, and receivables represent unrealized income. Where the receivables are highly
98
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
nual construct, and matching is not a tax norm. 110 The cash method should be allowed, at the taxpayer’s option, unless a good reason exists to the contrary. 2. Opting Out of Inventory Accounting Under present law, the purchase (or production) and sale of inventories is required to follow inventory accounting, which entails treating inventory costs (when accrued) as capital expenditures and following a recognized convention, such as FIFO, for allocating such costs to the taxable year. However, some exceptions already exist to this approach.111 Although capitalization is a hard norm of income taxation, reasons to relax it exist in the case of small business generally. The link between any particular cost and any particular sold item is already severed by the existence of inventory-accounting conventions. The gain from inventories is not compensation for the use of money or property, nor is it in the nature of market appreciation. Sellers of inventory have a natural incentive to sell it as promptly as is feasible. Essentially, inventory gains are the product of services (buying in one market and selling in another, plus servicing customers). Noncapitalization is simpler than the approach of current law, and there appears to be little potential for tax avoidance, especially if the taxpayer is on the cash method of accounting.112 In other words, it is proposed that inventory costs be generally treated as business expenses. The option to forego capitalization should not be available to small businesses that are required to capitalize inventory costs under regulatory law or Generally Accepted Accounting Principles (GAAP) to assets that are depreciable, to inventories of investments (land and securities), to inventories of unique assets (art and collectibles), to
liquid, the merchant possesses an incentive to sell the receivables. Many receivables of service providers will never be collected, as the sellers of services have no security. 110. See Burnet v. Sanford & Brooks Co., 282 U.S. 359 (1931); Deborah A. Geier, The Myth of the Matching Principle as a Tax Value, 15 AM. J. TAX POL’Y 17 (1998). 111. See Treas. Reg. § 1.162-3T (allowing expensing of materials and supplies), § 1.1626 (expensing of outlays of professionals), § 1.162-12 (farming costs). Additionally, small resellers of goods, farmers, and artists are not required to capitalize direct and indirect costs relating to inventories. See I.R.C. § 263A(b)(2)(B), (d), (h). Similarly, businesses that perform services on a “project” basis (such as architects and plaintiffs’ lawyers) do not capitalize costs to such projects. See Treas. Reg. § 1.263(a)-4 (2004) (service projects to obtain future fees from clients generally not treated as “intangibles”). Certain costs of extracting natural resources are likewise not capitalized. See id. §§ 263(c), 616, 617. 112. In the bad old days, expense deductions could be accrued by an accrual method taxpayer simply by entering into a contract for the purchase of goods to be delivered in the future. Under current § 461(h)(2)(A)(ii), the deduction cannot be accrued any earlier than the goods are provided to the taxpayer. See I.R.C. § 461(h)(2)(A)(ii).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
99
taxpayers using long-term contract accounting, or to other businesses or items for which expensing is not appropriate (as listed in regulations). 3. Simplified Asset Accounting Except for capital expenditures currently deducted under “expensing” rules, all capital expenditures of a “small business” incurred during the year (that relate to wasting assets) would be collected into a single vintage account and depreciated on a straight line basis over, say, four years, with all assets being deemed to have been put in service on January 1 of the vintage year. No depreciation deduction would be allowed in the year of the asset’s disposal. The asset’s basis (for purposes of figuring gain or loss) would be its cost less 25% thereof for any year of depreciation. N. Book-Tax Conformity for Public C Corporations C corporations, as a general matter, compute taxable income in the same way as do individuals for purposes of the corporate income tax. 113 However, a corporation is a tax entity separate from its shareholders, and the corporate income tax is, at its core, an excise tax that takes the form of an income tax in order to accommodate marginally profitable businesses. C corporation tax accounting would be simplified if it conformed to GAAP rather than the tax accounting rules for individuals, at least if the corporation follows GAAP accounting. It might be thought that individual/corporate tax accounting uniformity (1) eliminates tax incentives as to form of business entity, (2) avoids tax disparities that would exist with respect to similarly-situated GAAP-reporting businesses (because GAAP involves principles rather than a comprehensive set of rules), and (3) avoids the tax-driven race to the bottom within the accounting profession that might occur if GAAP were followed for tax purposes. I do not find these arguments to be persuasive on their face. A strong tax incentive already exists not to incorporate: the double shareholder/corporation tax. 114 Additionally, corporate tax reform may include other features, such as lower rates and rules mandating the form of business organization, that could affect evaluation of how corporate tax accounting should work. For publicly traded C corporations, book-tax conformity would balance client demand for higher 113. See id. § 63(a). The gross income computation is the same for individuals and C corporations; some deductions are only allowed for individuals and some are only allowed for corporations, but most are allowed for both. See §§ 63(b), 151(a), and the captions to I.R.C. Subtitle A, Ch. 1, Subch. B, Parts VI, VII, and VIII (Income Taxes). 114. It should be noted that, if the C corporation tax rate is lower than the individual tax rate, and if capital gains (and dividends) are also subject to lower-than-normal individual rates, then corporate accumulations and delayed distributions can save taxes relative to a pass-through system.
100
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
earnings against the client demand for lower taxes. Book-tax conformity should itself create a demand for greater uniformity in the application of accounting standards among businesses. I conclude that this simplification option at least deserves serious study as a component of a broader package of business-entity tax reform. O. Gratuitous Transfers Various tax rules relating to the income taxation of gratuitous transfers can be simplified or eliminated. 1. What is a “Gift” Under current law, the test for the § 102(a) exclusion for “gifts” and “bequests” is whether the donor’s motive is one of “ ‘disinterested generosity.’ ”115 A test keyed to motive of a person other than the taxpayer is unworkable. Taxpayers are free to take aggressive positions on this issue without incurring a significant risk of penalties and/or tax fraud prosecution.116 The existing rule breeds costly factbound litigation. A subjective test is unnecessary and should be replaced by the objective test adopted by the gift tax (as well as the charitable contribution deduction), namely, whether a transfer of wealth has not been made for full and adequate consideration in money or money’s worth, or in an ordinary commercial transaction.117 Additionally, any receipt of money or property from a business entity should not be excludible as a gift for income tax purposes. 2. Repeal § 274(b) Section 274(b) disallows business deductions for certain items that are excluded solely as gifts. This section is badly drafted insofar as it assumes that certain items are excluded as gifts where really they are not. Additionally, this provision would be rendered moot by the change mentioned immediately above. Third, deductibility as a business deduction should not hinge on the tax treatment of another party. The tests for deductibility under § 162 are independent of the test for exclusion under § 102(a). Accordingly, this section should be repealed.
115. Commissioner v. Duberstein, 363 U.S. 278, 285-86 (1960) (quoting Commissioner v. LoBue, 351 U.S. 243, 246 (1956)). 116. See, e.g., United States v. Harris, 942 F.2d 1125 (7th Cir. 1991). 117. See Treas. Reg. § 25.2512-8.
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
101
3. Repeal the Basis-Disallowance Rule for Gifts of DepreciatedValue Property Section 1015 generally provides a carryover basis rule for inter vivos gifts, but a complex exception lies for gifts of depreciated-value property, under which the basis can “float” until the property is sold by the donee. The only conceivable purpose of this rule is to prevent the assignment of built-in losses from a lower-bracket donor to a higher-bracket donee. This scenario would appear to be uncommon, since lower-bracket donors rarely have unrealized-loss property to give away. Yet § 1015 allows the assignment of built-in gains by higher-bracket donors to lower-bracket donees, which is a much more serious problem as far as income-shifting strategems are concerned. Thus, the exception should be repealed. 4. Repeal the § 691(c) Deduction and the § 1015(d)(6) Basis Adjustment The § 691(c) deduction is available to a person acquiring a right to “income in respect of a decedent” (IRD) of an amount equal to the estate tax (if any) “on” the IRD right, when the IRD is included in income. (IRD rights, which are rights to earned but unpaid income of a decedent, do not obtain a step-up in basis under § 1014.)118 The theory of the deduction is that, if the decedent had included the income on her final return, the estate tax base would have been reduced by the income tax paid or owed by the decedent. If the income and estate tax rates are the same, the § 691(c) deduction is equal to the hypothetical estate tax savings that would have resulted from the hypothetical inclusion of the IRD in the decedent’s income. The § 691(c) deduction is not only complex, but it is also so obscure (being unrelated to any cost) as to be susceptible of being overlooked except by the cognoscenti. Moreover, it is based on a false assumption, namely that the IRD was subject to income tax of the decedent. In fact, the IRD is income of the recipient of the IRD right, not the decedent. 119 Equal treatment between estate transfers of IRD rights and ordinary cash is not appropriate, because the situations are not the same. The current rules for IRD have the effect of deferring income and of attributing the income to a person who may well occupy a lower tax bracket than that of the decedent. The income tax paid by the IRD recipient will appropriately reduce the IRD recipient’s potential transfer tax base. The § 691 deduction serves no legitimate purpose and should be repealed.
118. See I.R.C. § 1014(c). 119. See id. § 691(a).
102
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
Section 1015(d)(6) gives a donee of appreciated property an income tax basis increase equal to the gift tax (if any) on the unrealized appreciation in the gift property. Apparently, the adjustment is “for” a hypothetical income tax of the donor that would have hypothetically reduced the gift amount. 120 If so, the rationale for § 1015(d)(6) is at least as flimsy as that for the § 691(c) deduction. Not only is this scenario purely hypothetical, but no donor would realize gain that would otherwise be wiped out by the stepped-up basis rule of § 1014. 5. Grantor Trusts The rules as to what trusts are deemed to be owned by the grantor are forbiddingly complex. 121 Proposals range from treating all inter vivos trusts as grantor trusts to that of treating no such trusts as grantor trusts. 122 Here I’ll offer an intermediate proposal: a grantor trust would be a disregarded entity123 if income or corpus could be (or is required to be) distributed to the grantor or the grantor’s spouse. 124 The identity and status of the person holding such power would be irrelevant, 125 and limitations (standards) on any such distributive power would be disregarded. Because of the fact that a grantor trust is a disregarded entity for income attribution purposes, a grantor trust should not be treated as a separate taxpayer for any other income tax purpose. 126 It follows that transactions between a grantor and a grantor trust would be
120. The gift tax on the unrealized appreciation is not an acquisition cost of the donee, because the donor is liable for the gift tax. Id. § 2502(c). Even so, acquisition costs are not added to the § 1015 basis, but subsumed within it. See Treas. Reg. § 1.1015-4 (basis to the donee is the greater of the § 1015 basis or any cost of acquiring the gift). 121. See I.R.C. §§ 671-677. Section 678, treating certain trusts as owned by a beneficiary, would also be repealed. 122. See, e.g., Mark L. Ascher, The Grantor Trust Rules Should be Repealed, 96 IOWA L. REV. 885 (2011). Grantor trusts can be used to avoid the highly compressed rate schedule of § 1(e) applicable to trust and estate net income, but trusts can still be used to shift income from the grantor’s higher marginal rates to the lower marginal rates of distributees. It should be noted that the “kiddie tax,” see I.R.C. § 1(g), curbs the use of trusts to shift income to minors, but this renders § 677(b) (trust income used to discharge grantor’s support obligation) largely pointless. 123. The grantor continues to be taxed on the trust’s income, because the grantor is deemed to be the owner of the trust property. I.R.C. § 671. 124. Sections 674 and 675 (the most technical of the grantor trust rules) would be repealed, and §§ 673, 676, and 677(a) would be combined. Professor Ascher concedes that § 676 (power to re-vest corpus in grantor or grantor’s spouse) should be retained. Ascher, supra note 122, at 930. Section 677(a) extends the principle expressed in § 676 to income. Section 673 (retained reversions worth more than 5%) should be retained because nontrust retained-reversion transfers are ineffective to shift income. 125. The concept of “adverse party”—an artificial construct—would cease to play a role in this area. 126. Cf. Rothstein v. United States, 735 F.2d 704 (2d Cir. 1984) (recognizing an installment sale from a grantor trust to a grantor), nonacq., Rev. Rul. 85-13, 1985-1 C.B. 184.
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
103
disregarded. The model for such a rule is § 1041, dealing with property transfers between husband and wife.127 6. A “Simple Estate” Income Tax Regime Under current law, estates are taxed as Subchapter J trusts,128 but special rules come into play only for estates. 129 The system is complex, and its rules are often skipped over in the basic income tax and estate and gift tax courses, so that estate attorneys may be insufficiently aware of them, with the resulting incurrence of unnecessary taxes. 130 There is no policy reason to tax estate net income at the highest marginal rate (as can easily occur under present law), as estates (which result from a transferor’s death) are not illegitimate income shifting devices. A simpler income tax regime should be available for any estate that (1) possesses a net value under a certain amount (perhaps $2 million), (2) does not provide for a successive interest transfer (in trust or otherwise), and (3) is not a trust in disguise (i.e., is wound up within a reasonable time after the decedent’s death). Specific-bequest property, and the income therefrom, would be deemed to be owned by the legatee (and not the estate) for income attribution purposes starting on the day following the decedent’s death. All other estate income and deductions would be aggregated at the entity level and attributed to the residual legatees (and/or heirs) in proportion to their interests. (No estate net income would be allocated to fixed-sum legatees. 131) The estate would pay a withholding tax at the highest individual marginal rate on all estate net income, including net capital gains. (The withholding tax would be charged pro rata against the estate distributions to residual legatees or heirs.) These estate beneficiaries would, in addition to reporting their ratable share of estate net income, obtain a tax credit for their share of 127. Section 1041 treats a “sale” between marital partners as a non-realization event, and the transferor’s basis carries over to the transferee. I.R.C. § 1041(a), (b). 128. See id. § 641(a). 129. See id. §§ 642(b)(1), 663(a)(1). 130. Under current law, if the estate net income is greater than distributions to residuary legatees (and heirs), the excess is taxed to the trust under the highly compressed rate schedule of I.R.C. § 1(e). 131. A “specific property” bequest is one where the legatee is to receive specifically identified property under the will. A “fixed-sum” (or “pecuniary”) bequest is of a fixeddollar amount under a will. See Treas. Reg. § 1.663(a)-1(b). Under the law of estates, fixedsum legatees (unlike other legatees and heirs) are not entitled to a share of estate income, but they may be entitled to interest payments. See RICHARD B. COVEY, MARITAL DEDUCTION AND CREDIT SHELTER DISPOSITIONS AND THE USE OF FORMULA PROVISIONS, App. B (4th ed. 1997) (compilation of state rules on this issue). Any interest payable by the estate on account of a delayed distribution of a fixed-sum bequest would be deductible to the estate in arriving at estate net income for income tax purposes and would be gross income to the fixed-sum legatee.
104
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
the withholding tax. 132 The executor would file an information return to the IRS and the estate distributees stating the gross income amounts and the tax credit amounts for each residual beneficiary or heir. 7. Repeal the rule that the in-kind satisfaction of a fixed-sum bequest is a deemed sale of the property Under current law, the satisfaction of a fixed-sum bequest with inkind property is treated as a sale by the estate (or trust) of the asset to the legatee at its fair market value, 133 but other estate distributions entail a different set of income tax consequences. 134 These rules add unneeded complexity to the system and may be overlooked by fiduciaries. The rule as to fixed-sum bequests is conceptually misguided, because the distributee has not given any consideration in money or money’s worth for the right to the bequest. Whatever purpose might be served under probate law for treating the pecuniary obligation as a “debt”135 has no relevance for income tax purposes.136 Accordingly, all in-kind distributions should be treated alike: the distribution would not constitute a realization event, and the estate’s basis would carry over to the distributee. 137 P. Transactional Accounting Issues 1. Basis of In-Kind Income Items Under current law, some confusion exists as to whether the “tax cost” basis of in-kind property receipts should be the amount actually included in gross income or, instead, the amount includible (although not in fact included). Often this issue is dealt with by applying the complex “mitigation provisions” 138 or fact-intensive equitable doctrines, such as equitable estoppel, equitable recoupment, or the duty of consistency. 139 Resort to these provisions and doctrines assumes 132. The suggested system would do away with the distribution deduction and the computation of estate distributable net income. See I.R.C. §§ 643(a), 661, 662. Net tax exempt income would also be passed through. 133. See Kenan v. Commissioner, 114 F.2d 217 (2d Cir. 1940); Rev. Rul. 67-74, 1967-1 C.B. 194; see also I.R.C. § 267(a)(1), (b)(13) (allowance of loss to estate in this scenario). 134. See I.R.C. § 643(e) (default rule is that distribution is not a realization event). 135. Treating pecuniary bequests as “debts” is what results in the estate’s obligation to pay interest if the distribution of the bequest is unreasonably delayed. See supra note 131. 136. The proposed change is in line with that for “false” COD income, involving the forgiveness of debts not incurred for value received. See supra text accompanying notes 100-01. 137. Section 643(e) would be modified to accord with this proposal. If the distribution deduction/inclusion system of present §§ 661 and 662 continues in force for trusts (and large estates), the distribution would be “at” the trust’s basis. 138. I.R.C. §§ 1311-1314. 139. The various doctrinal strands in this area are discussed in JOSEPH M. DODGE ET
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
105
that the statute of limitations applies to basis determinations, a position that is contrary to the Supreme Court’s decision in Dobson v. Commissioner, 140 as well as the position of all courts of appeals in cases involving recoveries of amounts erroneously deducted in prior years.141 Since basis is not subject to the statute of limitations, linking basis to what the taxpayer actually reported does not involve the re-opening of barred issues. As a policy matter, taxpayers should not obtain collateral tax benefits for their own errors and omissions. Accordingly, the “tax cost” basis of any in-kind property receipt (or of any claim to a right to recovery of an item previously expended) should depend on the taxpayer’s actual prior tax treatment of the item. 2. Repeal § 1341 Section 1341 gives a taxpayer that refunds or repays a previously included item the choice between the deduction that would be allowed as a matter of course and a credit equal to the incremental taxes “caused” by the prior income inclusion of the refunded amount. This provision has bred a good deal of litigation concerning its imprecisely worded prerequisites. If applicable, § 1341 involves recalculating the tax for a year possibly closed by the statute of limitations. Section 1341 was enacted in 1954 in the wake of a Supreme Court case where the original inclusion was subject to very high marginal rates in 1944 that had decreased by the year of repayment. 142 The correct tax treatment in theory is to allow a deduction (as a matter of right) in the year of repayment, because the taxpayer has had the use of the money until then. Accordingly, § 1341 should be repealed. Section 67(b)(9) provides that the deduction “allowed by” § 1341 is not a “miscellaneous itemized deduction.” 143 However, § 1341 does not allow any deduction whatsoever. 144 Presumably, the intent here was to list the deduction referred to in § 1341, but it appears (on account of the reference to “claim of right”) that this reference applies only where the § 1341 requirements for electing into the credit are satisfied. This technical glitch becomes moot if, as suggested above, § 67 is amended to cover only enumerated borderline expense deductions AL., supra
note 73, at 654-60. 140. Dobson v. Commissioner, 320 U.S. 489 (1943). 141. Federal appeals courts that have considered the issue have uniformly held that recoveries of erroneously deducted amounts are fully includible. See, e.g., Hughes & Luce, L.L.P. v. Commissioner, 70 F.3d 16 (5th Cir. 1995). In other words, a taxpayer’s basis in the right of recovery hinges on the actual prior tax treatment, not the correct prior tax treatment. 142. See United States v. Lewis, 340 U.S. 590 (1951); H.R. REP. NO. 83-1337, at A29495 (2d Sess. 1954), reprinted in 1954 U.S.C.C.A.N. 4017, 4436. 143. I.R.C. § 67(b)(9). 144. See id. § 1341. Curiously, the deduction for the refund or repayment is viewed as a deductible “loss” under § 165(c)(2), rather than an “expense.”
106
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
and the distinction between above-the-line and itemized deductions is eliminated. Otherwise, given that the “claim of right” notion has been abandoned in the doctrinal substratum, 145 § 67(b)(9) should be amended to refer to “the deduction arising from the repayment or refund of a previously included amount.” Q. Portfolio Accounting for Publicly Traded Securities Even with brokers being required to supply basis information for securities transactions,146 accounting for basis on an item-by-item basis is onerous. 147 Consideration should be given to allowing taxpayers to use an average basis in a portfolio of publicly traded securities. An average-basis approach is conceptually correct for shares of a given stock, since all such shares are fungible. The proposed system would simply extend this concept to the taxpayer’s entire portfolio of publicly traded securities, for which a year-end valuation of the portfolio would be required. 1. Mechanics The system would operate somewhat like inventory accounting, but without a physical “closing inventory.” Thus, “portfolio security gains” for a year would be “receipts from security dispositions” less “cost of securities sold.” The cost-of-securities-sold amount would be “cost of opening securities inventory” plus “cost of new securities inventory” 148 (equaling total portfolio basis) multiplied by a fraction, the numerator of which is “gross receipts from securities dispositions” and the denominator of which is the sum of (1) such gross receipts and (2) the sum of the market quotes for all securities on hand at the end of the year.149 Conceptually, this formula produces a basis offset (against sales receipts) equal to that percentage of the aggregate year-end securities basis that reflects the decrease in value of the portfolio caused by the sales. The “opening inventory” for the next year would be “cost of opening securities inventory” plus “cost of new securities inventory,” less “cost of securities sold,” all for the prior 145. See United States v. James, 366 U.S. 213 (1961) (overruling Commissioner v. Wilcox, 327 U.S. 404 (1946), a case that had held that embezzled cash was not gross income because not obtained under a claim of right). 146. See I.R.C. § 6045(g). 147. Under current law, where shares of the same stock are purchased at different times, the taxpayer has to either identify the particular securities sold or else use the firstin, first-out convention. Treas. Reg. § 1.1012-1(c)(1). Since shares of the same stock are fungible, an average-basis approach is conceptually preferable to either of the methods sanctioned by the regulations. An average-basis approach is currently allowed only for certain mutual fund shares. See id. § 1.1012-1(e)(1). 148. “Cost of new securities inventory” would include any current-year basis adjustments attributable to tax-free exchanges, gifts, bequests, OID accruals, and so on. 149. Thus, if there is no closing inventory of securities, the basis would be 100% (gross receipts/gross receipts) of the aggregate basis.
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
107
year. Securities that have become worthless during the year would not produce transactional losses. Instead, worthlessness would have the effect of increasing aggregate basis relative to aggregate portfolio value. The existing distinction between long-term gains and losses and short-term gains and losses would, if retained, complicate the system, because separate pools of short-term and long-term publicly traded securities would need to be kept, with securities passing from a short-term pool to a long-term pool. The problem can be managed if securities are deemed to move from a short-term pool to a long-term pool only on January 1 of the taxable year that is the second taxable year following the year of purchase. Thus, securities purchased at any time in 2013 would reside in a short-term pool in 2013 and 2014,150 and any remaining security cost in this pool would shift to the long-term pool in 2015. It would still be necessary to match sales receipts to the correct vintage pool. This problem would disappear if the distinction between long-term and short-term were to be abolished. 2. No Disallowance of Portfolio Net Loss If the taxpayer elects to use this system, all publicly traded securities would be required to be accounted for within it. In that case, the system would operate in a manner that would preclude the cherry picking of losses, because the proceeds from the sale of any security would trigger the same basis recovery amount, regardless of whether that particular security had appreciated or depreciated. Sales would produce losses only where the portfolio as a whole (inclusive of the year’s transactions) is in a loss position. Since the cherry picking of losses would not be a major concern under the portfolio approach, consideration could be given to allowing any portfolio loss for the year as a current deduction, without any carry forward of losses (except for negative taxable income caused by such losses). If losses were allowed in full, the losses should carry symmetrical tax treatment to any favorable tax treatment conferred upon portfolio gain. Thus, if 30% of portfolio gain were excluded by reason of being long-term capital gain, then 30% of portfolio losses would be disallowed.
150. Securities purchased in 2013 would reside in a “vintage 2013” pool, and sales of 2013 securities would be offset by the average basis of sold 2013 securities. The 2013 pool would continue for the year 2014, and any remaining basis at the end of 2014 would pass into the long-term pool on January 1, 2015. Another pool, for securities purchased in 2014, would continue through 2015, and pass to the long-term pool in 2016.
108
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
3. Partial Repeal of § 1014 Transitioning to the next part concerning simplification aspects of certain tax reform measures, it is fair to say that academic tax commentators are unanimous in their condemnation of the rule that death wipes out unrealized asset gains and losses. 151 Repeal of this rule would also generate substantial revenue. The portfolio-basis system described above could, if mandatory, be used as a vehicle for partial repeal of § 1014 (really, of the rule that death is not a realization event for tax purposes). The usual objection to such a repeal, i.e., that historic basis is too hard to ascertain, would carry no weight, as portfolio basis would have been adjusted annually. The net portfolio gain or loss would be deemed realized in the year of the taxpayer’s death. The fair market value of the portfolio assets at the decedent’s death would fix both the amount realized by the decedent at death and the basis of the decedent’s successors in such assets. IV. TAX REFORMS CONTRIBUTING TO SIMPLIFICATION This Part deals with tax reform options that also offer simplification potential. Since this Article is not being used as a vehicle for pushing my personal tax reform agenda, the emphasis herein is on the simplification potential offered by what might be called the “usual suspects” in the vast array of possible tax reform proposals. A. Tax Expenditures It might be obvious that the place to start is with wholesale elimination of those numerous Code provisions that can be called “tax expenditures,” in the narrow sense of having been enacted to serve a programmatic goal, such as investment in a certain type of business, the creation of domestic jobs, or the subsidization of child care. (The broader issue of defining a tax expenditure as any deviation from some tax-base norm—such as Haig-Simons income—would not serve the purposes of the present discussion, which is not focused on norms. 152) All such programmatic tax expenditures must contain qualification rules that distinguish the favored activity from nonfavored activity. These qualification rules are typically detailed and 151. See Joseph M. Dodge, Why a Deemed-Realization Rule for Gratuitous Transfers Is Superior to Carryover Basis and Avoids Most of the Problems of the Present Estate and Gift Tax, 54 TAX L. REV. 421 (2001), and authorities cited therein. 152. For example, from a consumption tax perspective, capital expenditures should be expensed; from an accretion income tax perspective, capital expenditures should not be expensed, and depreciation should equal the annual decline in an asset’s value; from a realization income tax perspective, it is questionable whether depreciation should be allowed at all.
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
109
complex. 153 But, although their wholesale elimination from the tax Code would advance the cause of tax simplicity, the same programs, now “off tax,” would entail non-tax complexity and attendant compliance costs. Abolishing the programs altogether might advance the cause of “government program simplicity,” but simplicity at that level has to be weighed in the larger context of policy, which is beyond the scope of this Article. Of course, where these “programs” are not justified in policy terms, repealing them would advance the cause of simplification. In the name of transparency, I would only suggest that programmatic tax expenditures take the form of tax credits rather than deductions. Since some of the deduction provisions that are generally thought of as tax expenditures (such as accelerated depreciation154 and expensing of research and experimentation outlays 155) occupy a gray zone of accounting uncertainty, these provisions might even be justified in the name of simplification. However, simplification in this context only argues that rules are preferable to case-by-case determinations. Simplification alone does not justify one set of rules over another. B. Capital Gains The arguments for and against special rates for capital gains are well rehearsed and will not be repeated here.156 Without doubt, vast simplification of the income tax can be obtained by eliminating (to the extent possible) the apparatus regarding capital gains. Some of this apparatus, however, might be needed to cope with the problem of cherry picking capital losses, which (although tangentially considered above in connection with investment portfolio accounting) is systematically addressed here. 1. Plan A: Eliminate Special Rates for Net Capital Gain Section 1(h), providing special (low) rates for various categories of net capital gains, is so complex that its details probably cannot be grasped by even a very intelligent tax expert, so that a lengthy worksheet (or computer program) is required. Additionally, Schedule D of the Individual Income Tax Return (Form 1040) requires the entry of extensive data broken down into numerous categories. An obvious option is to provide no tax benefit for net capital gains in any form. 153. See, e.g., I.R.C. 179(d). 154. Id. §§ 168(b)(1), (k), 179. 155. Id. § 174. 156. See generally TAX ANALYSTS, THE CAPITAL GAINS CONTROVERSY (J. Andrew Hoerner ed., 1992).
110
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
2. Plan B: Simplify the Benefits Conferred on Net Capital Gain A secondary option is to replace the present “rate” approach by a “partial exclusion” approach for net capital gains. For example, some percentage of net capital gains, say, 30%, would be excluded from gross income. The existing approach essentially eliminates any progressivity in the capital gains system at the upper end of the income scale (where virtually all net capital gains are concentrated) and therefore disproportionately favors taxpayers in the very highest rate bracket.157 The exclusion approach also better accords with an “inflation adjustment” rationale for favorable treatment. Finally, the exclusion approach is compatible with the structure of the Alternative Minimum Tax (AMT), because the exclusion can (and should) be added back in computing AMT taxable income. 3. Eliminate the Category of “Collectibles” Gain Net collectibles gain is currently subject to a maximum tax rate of 28%. 158 Either net collectibles gain deserves treatment on a par with other investments in the capital gains system or it does not. In my view it does not, since collectibles are usually held for personal use or could be held for personal use without the knowledge of the IRS. Hence, it can be presumed that the acquisition and disposition of collectibles is driven more by personal taste than economic considerations. Indeed, losses on such assets are (usually) subject to disallowance as personal losses, and the activity of collecting is likely to be held to be a not-for-profit activity. 159 If any collectibles are to obtain a full capital gains benefit, strict “investment” requirements should be imposed. For example, the collectible should have been purchased for a substantial sum (say, $40,000, or perhaps more) and should be required to be stored in a vault or warehouse and barred from any personal use. 4. Full Depreciation Recapture for Real Estate The argument against recapture (as ordinary gain) of gain caused by depreciation of real estate is not convincing. 160 The argument is 157. To illustrate this point, assume that taxpayers X and Y are in the 25% and 40% marginal rate brackets, respectively, without regard to capital gains, and that each has net capital gains of $10,000. Under the rate approach of current law, both X and Y pay incremental tax of $1500 on this $10,000. Under a system in which 40% of net capital gains are excluded, X and Y would have incremental income of $6000. X, taxed at a 25% rate, would have the same $1500 incremental tax as before. However, Y would have an incremental tax of $2400. 158. I.R.C. § 1(h)(4)-(5). Actually, matters are more complicated than that, but the complications are not germane to the discussion. 159. See, e.g., Barcus v. Commissioner, 1973 T.C.M. (P-H) 1973-138, at 643 (1973), aff’d, 492 F.2d 1237 (2d Cir. 1974) (per curiam). 160. Existing § 1250 recaptures only the excess of accelerated over straight-line depre-
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
111
that real estate can appreciate and depreciate at the same time, so that the gain might result from true unrealized appreciation deserving of capital gain treatment. However, the argument is based on the derivation of depreciation from a mathematical model (changes in present values of future yields that are fixed ab initio) that inevitably shows “losses” with the passage of time. The mathematical model is only a proxy for expected mark-to-market depreciation. 161 If the asset did not in fact depreciate in value, then the asset was not a wasting asset in the taxpayer’s hands over the period it was held, and depreciation should not have been allowed in the first place. Appreciation is an “inconsistent event” relative to the depreciation deductions.162 Only one asset exists, and any gain should be attributed first to depreciation (a certain tax fact), which, by causing the basis to be reduced, directly produces gain. Gain that is clearly “caused” by ordinary deductions (that reduce basis) should always be ordinary gain. Recapture already exists under § 1245 as to equivalent gain on personal property. The less-favorable capital gains tax rate for “unrecaptured § 1250 gain”163 already amounts to a partial move in this direction. Accordingly, § 1250 should be repealed, and § 1245 should be expanded to encompass all gain attributable to depreciation (and expensing). This simplification move can also be made without any other change in the capital gains system. Elimination of the categories of “collectibles gain” and “unrecaptured § 1250 gain” would greatly facilitate a move back to a partialexclusion system. 5. Repeal § 1231 Section 1231 is a complicated provision, the main feature of which provides that net unrecaptured long-term gain from property used in a trade or business is net capital gain (but that net loss is ordinary loss). Expansion of depreciation recapture to real estate would greatly reduce the impact of this provision, so that it would only affect land and other nondepreciable property used in a business. In general, business-use property should generate ordinary gain (and loss), as is the case with other business income (and loss). ciation, but exceptions exist. Accelerated depreciation has not been allowed on real estate since 1986. Thus, virtually all gain on depreciable real property is treated as capital gain or § 1231 gain. 161. This much is evident from what many consider to be the seminal work on depreciation: Paul A. Samuelson, Tax Deductibility of Economic Depreciation to Insure Invariant Valuations, 72 J. POL. ECON. 604 (1964). 162. In the absence of Congressional preemption of depreciation rules, the inconsistentevents doctrine would probably result in ordinary gain to the extent of depreciation. See Hillsboro Nat’l Bank v. Commissioner, 460 U.S. 370 (1983). 163. I.R.C. § 1(h)(1)(D), (h)(6).
112
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
Another aspect of § 1231 is to provide that net unrecaptured involuntary-conversion gains on business and investment property can, when combined with other § 1231 gains and losses, end up as net capital gains despite the absence of a sale or exchange. 164 There is no reason that unrecaptured gains should be treated as capital gains just because the property is disposed of in an involuntary conversion, because the taxpayer in such cases can avoid the recognition of involuntary-conversion gain under § 1033 by reinvesting the proceeds of conversion in similar-use property. Unreinvested gains of an individual are available for consumption. Finally, if the purpose of capital gains benefits is to unlock investments, then involuntary conversions are not an inappropriate occasion to confer capital gains treatment, because the disposition was beyond the taxpayer’s control. 165 In general, the appropriate remedy for unexpected income or gains is a tax deferral rule, which already exists in the form of § 1033. Thus, this aspect of § 1231 also merits repeal. A provision parallel to § 1231 (as far as the “character” of gain or loss is concerned) exists under § 165(h)(2)(B) with regard to involuntary conversions of personal-use assets. The same arguments for repeal as noted above apply here as well. (Other aspects of personal casualty losses and gains will be discussed below.) What remains of § 1231 after repealing the foregoing is a tax expenditure provision that taxes income from certain extractive and agricultural enterprises at lower rates. 166 C. Losses on Sales and Exchanges Even if lower rates for net capital gains are eliminated, the problem of capital losses would remain. Under current law, a taxpayer’s aggregate capital losses for the year can only be deducted to the extent of the sum of (1) taxpayer aggregate capital gains for the year, or (2) $3000 (in the case of non-corporate taxpayers). 167 1. Restrictions on the Current Deductibility of Net Transactional Losses The restrictions on the current deductibility of net capital losses are designed to prevent the cherry picking of investment losses while allowing gains to go unrealized. The theoretically proper anti-cherrypicking rule would be to allow realized losses to be allowed to the ex164. Id. § 1231(a)(3)(A)(ii), (a)(4)(B), (a)(4)(C). 165. This point was the basis for the decision in Pounds v. United States, 372 F.2d 342, 348 (5th Cir. 1967). 166. I.R.C. § 1231(b)(2)-(4). 167. Id. § 1211. Capital losses that are disallowed are carried over to future years under § 1212.
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
113
tent of realized gains plus an amount equal to the excess (if any) of net realized losses over unrealized gains.168 However, accounting for unrealized gains would entail a valuation of appreciated assets at the end of the year, 169 and the income tax avoids valuations as a general rule. The “portfolio method” of accounting for securities transactions set forth in Part III.Q above is one way to deal with the problem. A less radical approach would be to allow taxpayers to elect to treat unrealized gains on publicly traded investments as having been realized (at the end of the taxable year) to the extent of such realized net losses, and such gains (although not actually resulting from a sale) would absorb the realized net losses. Realized losses on publicly traded investments in excess of realized and deemed-realized gains would be allowed to the extent that such excess exceeds gains that are neither realized nor deemed realized. Since the assets in the deemed-realized-gain category are still owned by the taxpayer, an amount equal to the deemed-realized gain would be added to basis, bringing the basis of such assets up to their fair market values at the end of the year, effectively reducing future gains (as would occur with carryovers). 170 2. Simplifying the Rules Defining Gains and Losses Subject to the Anti-Cherry-Picking Rule If lower rates for capital gains are eliminated, the existing terminology and definitions of capital gains and losses could be scrapped and a new system put in place that is designed solely to implement the anti-cherry-picking rules in an appropriate fashion. The anticherry-picking rule should be limited, roughly speaking, to “voluntary” realized losses from investments and from those business assets that are not routinely disposed of at the end of a normal business cycle (such as land and assets having an indefinite or very long useful 168. Thus, if realized losses are $10,000, realized gains are $2000, and unrealized gains are $5000, the amount currently deductible should be limited to $5000: $2000 + [($10,000 $2000) - $5000]. Stated differently, the deduction for net realized losses would be reduced by the amount of unrealized (“unpicked”) gains. 169. Since all figures in the formula are determined as of the end of the year, a loss that was not truly “cherry-picked” at the time realized could be disallowed and carried over because of appreciation that occurred later in the year. Of course, the reverse could happen as well. 170. Again, assume that a taxpayer has realized losses of $10,000 during the year, has realized gains of $2000 during the year, and has unrealized gains at the end of the year of $5000, all involving publicly traded investments. The taxpayer would report $2000 of realized gains and could elect to report an additional $5000 of deemed-realized gains (excess of end-of-year fair market value of appreciated assets over their then adjusted basis). In that case, all $10,000 of the realized losses would be allowable, because no cherry picking would exist in this scenario. Additionally, $5000 would be added to the basis of the unrealized gain assets, bringing the basis of each such asset up to the fair market value at the end of the year.
114
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
life). Thus, inventory and business equipment would normally be excluded from the loss-limitation system, as would be involuntaryevent losses, losses that were realized by reason of another party’s action, losses incurred by the lapse of a time period, and losses occasioned by worthlessness. Various “deemed sale or exchange” rules, such as §§ 165(g), 166(d)(1)(B), and 1271(a)(1), could be consolidated into one Code section treating certain losses as falling without the anti-cherry-picking rule. At the same time, all transactional gains (not from inventory, business equipment, receivables, etc.), whether voluntary or not, should be allowed to offset losses subject to the anticherry-picking rule. The existing distinction between short-term and long-term would be meaningless under the anti-cherry-picking rule. If no favorable treatment for net capital gains is available, the holding period concept could be dropped entirely. D. The Personal Deductions Proposals abound to eliminate, cut back, or restrict all or some of the personal deductions, sometimes in the name of raising revenue,171 and sometimes in the name of conforming to a normative tax base. 172 The deductions (in various degrees) have already been seriously eroded by floors, ceilings, phase-out rules, and indirect disallowance or deferral under the Alternative Minimum Tax. These backhanded approaches were critiqued in Part III as contributing to complexity and lack of transparency. Here, the focus is on the deductions themselves. 1. Residential Mortgage Interest Although defended by politicians as essential to preserving middle class homeownership, this deduction for qualified residence interest 173 is criticized by a broad spectrum of tax academics. 174 Plausible proposals include: (1) eliminating the deduction entirely, (2) eliminating the deduction for interest on home equity debt (as opposed to acquisition or improvement debt), 175 (3) restricting the deduction to in171. See, e.g., Edward D. Kleinbard, The Role of Tax Reform in Deficit Reduction, 133 TAX NOTES 1105, 1106-07 (2011). 172. Numerous articles discuss the issue of whether any of the personal deductions conform to the concept of Haig-Simons income. See, e.g., William D. Andrews, Personal Deductions in an Ideal Income Tax, 86 HARV. L. REV. 309 (1972); Mark G. Kelman, Personal Deductions Revisited: Why They Fit Poorly in an “Ideal” Income Tax and Why They Fit Worse in a Far from Ideal World, 31 STAN. L. REV. 831 (1979); William J. Turnier, Evaluating Personal Deductions in an Income Tax—The Ideal, 66 CORNELL L. REV. 262, 270-76 (1981). 173. I.R.C. § 163(h)(3). 174. See, e.g., Dennis J. Ventry, Jr., The Accidental Deduction: A History and Critique of the Tax Subsidy for Mortgage Interest, L. & CONTEMP. PROBS., Winter 2010, at 233. 175. Interest on home equity debt (as opposed to acquisition debt) is allowed on up to
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
115
terest on (acquisition) debt for the taxpayer’s principal residence only, 176 and (4) reducing the dollar figures for deduction-generating mortgage principal. The invocation of middle-class values is not a plausible defense of the deduction insofar as it relates to home equity debt and mortgages on second (vacation) homes. This deduction is neither particularly complex nor hard to administer. Nevertheless, if a deduction for home equity indebtedness is retained, the “net equity” limitation found in § 163(h)(c)(1) should be removed, because it entails annual valuations of the property and annual determinations of acquisition-debt principal. 177 Alternatively, this net equity rule could be retained but only applied as of the date of borrowing. A third possibility would be to require that the home equity loan come from an unrelated commercial lender. Since the personal exemptions already include an allowance for housing costs, consideration should be given to imposing a floor under the residential interest deduction (if it is retained) in order to prevent redundant deduction of the same costs. Since persons tend to spend at least 30% of their income on housing costs,178 and since mortgage interest would often be the largest such cost for homeowners, a plausible floor would be $6000 (one-third of the low-income allowance for a family of two as suggested earlier).179 However, such a floor—although perhaps a revenue raiser—would not eliminate much data from the system. 2. State and Local Taxes The deduction for nonfederal taxes (unrelated to business or investment) is also controversial. Plausible proposals include (1) abolishing the deduction entirely, (2) eliminating the deduction for property taxes (or possibly only foreign property taxes), and (3) eliminating the deduction for sales taxes. Accounting for state and local sales taxes is impractical. Additionally, sales taxes are naturally viewed (rightly or wrongly) as a cost of whatever is purchased. The case for eliminating the deduction for $100,000 of home equity debt principal. I.R.C. § 163(h)(3)(C)(ii). 176. The deduction is available for interest on the taxpayer’s personal residence and one other residence. Id. § 163(h)(4)(A)(i). 177. Id. § 163(h)(c)(1). 178. See Mary Schwartz & Ellen Wilson, Who Can Afford to Live in a Home?: A Look at Data from the 2006 American Community Survey, U.S. CENSUS BUREAU, http://www.census.gov/housing/census/publications/who-can-afford.pdf (last visited Jan. 25, 2014). 179. Off-the-bottom allowances are discussed in the text supra Part III.E–F. However, a fixed-dollar floor is probably a political non-starter, since it appears to favor high-income taxpayers whose mortgage interest expense would exceed the floor. The conventional approach in response to this problem is to express floors as a percentage of net income. However, that kind of floor appears to be out of synch with fixed-dollar subsistence deductions.
116
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
sales taxes on personal-consumption items is compelling from both a theoretical and practical perspective. In sum, sales taxes should be treated as part of the cost of whatever is purchased and not as a separate expense. Property taxes are viewed as a cost of maintaining property, and costs of maintaining personal-use property should not be deducted. Moreover, property taxes on personal-use property can be avoided by renting rather than owning. Hence, it cannot be persuasively argued that these expenses are involuntary or are forced. Thus, the deduction for taxes on personal-use property is also a good candidate for repeal. Certainly, real property taxes on second homes should be disallowed as being highly discretionary. Since it is sometimes hard to tell whether a tax on tangible personal-use personal property is really a tax, and since such taxes typically are small in amount, the deduction for such taxes should also be eliminated. State and local income taxes cannot be avoided except by the extreme measures of moving or cheating. Hence, a plausible case exists for deducting only these taxes. Moreover, since state and local income taxes are not universal in the United States, a deduction only for this category of nonfederal taxes is not a proper scenario for a floor under the deduction. Taxes on real property are universal, all but five states impose sales taxes,180 and all but seven (or nine) states impose income taxes.181 Aggregate state and local taxes as a percentage of income ranged (in 2010) from about 7.0% to 12.8%, 182 which is a fairly narrow spread. Since the tax base is supposed to be a “difference principle,” costs that all persons bear equally (or proportionately to income) can well be ignored. Although a floor under a deduction is usually appropriate to weed out commonly incurred expenses of a certain type, allowing a deduction in excess of a floor is indicated only where extraordinary expenses of the category in question is possible. In the case of state and local taxes, it is hard to see how such extraordinary payments can occur. Therefore, even if it is thought that one or more of the categories of state and local taxes should be deducted under a normative 180. Alaska, Delaware, Montana, New Hampshire, and Oregon do not have comprehensive state sales taxes, but most have taxes that are partial substitutes for sales taxes. State Sales Tax Rates, SALES TAX INST., http://www.salestaxinstitute.com/resources/rates (last updated Nov. 1, 2013). 181. States without income taxes are Alaska, Florida, Nevada, New Hampshire, South Dakota, Tennessee, Texas, Washington, and Wyoming. States Without a State Income Tax, IRS.GOV, http://www.irs.gov/uac/States-Without-a-State-Income-Tax (last updated Apr. 11, 2013). Nevertheless, New Hampshire and Tennessee tax dividends and interest. See Taxes by State, RET. LIVING INFO. CTR., https://www.retirementliving.com/taxes-by-state (last updated Jan. 2013). 182. State and Local Tax Burdens: All States, One Year, 1977 – 2010, TAX FOUND. (Oct. 23, 2012), http://taxfoundation.org/article/state-and-local-tax-burdens-all-states-one-year1977-2010.
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
117
theory of income, a case can be made that none of them should be deductible in practice. Under current law, refunds of deductible taxes must be run through the machinery of § 111 in order to determine the portion of them that is includible by reason of having actually reduced taxable income in a prior year. This calculation is required where: (a) the deduction is subject to a floor, (b) the deduction falls within a class of deductions that is subject to a floor, or (c) the taxpayer’s taxable income is reduced to a negative number by the deduction. Refunds occur mainly with respect to income taxes. If taxes (including income taxes) are not deductible at all, then refunds of such taxes would be wholly excludible and would not have to be included subject to the machinery of § 111. 3. Personal Casualty and Theft Losses The standard rationale for this deduction is that personal casualty and theft losses constitute a decrease in wealth that is not “consumption.” 183 However, in fact consumption under an income tax is viewed as occurring when a personal-use asset is purchased, not as and when it is used.184 Moreover, the tax system does not otherwise take into account deviations of consumption value from cost. As a matter of broader policy, the deduction operates as taxpayersubsidized insurance for uninsured losses. The deduction is more valuable to high-bracket taxpayers who can best afford to purchase property-loss insurance. It is tempting, therefore, to repeal this deduction entirely, and for most taxpayers the deduction has already been repealed by reason of the floor under the deduction equal to 10% of adjusted gross income. Nevertheless, in some cases casualty and theft losses reduce ability to pay, and the system should make appropriate allowance in that event. Any reduction in ability to pay occurs by reason of having to prematurely replace “essential” property. (Such a rationale is the same as the “duplicative cost” rationale for deducting business lodging costs.) Thus, the deduction should be triggered only by the unexpected destruction of certain property. The deduction would be the lesser of the cost of replacement or the cost of the items being replaced, reduced by the sum of net salvage proceeds, insurance proceeds, and government cash benefits, but not to exceed a specified
183. Turnier, supra note 172, at 272. 184. Consumption costs, whether expenses or capital expenditures, are taxed by being nondeductible. The nondeductible (and non-depreciable) cost of a personal-use asset represents the present value of its future estimated consumption value. Actual consumption with respect to such assets is not taxed as it occurs.
118
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
fixed-dollar figure. “Replacement cost” would include unreimbursed costs of lodging for a maximum period of, say, one year. If the deduction is not repealed or further cut back, the following simplification reforms are suggested. First, valuation “after” the casualty should not play any role in cases where the item is not disposed of and is repaired or rehabilitated. The valuation of, say, a wrecked automobile is pointless, because a wrecked automobile has no economic use, except as salvage. In such a case, the repair costs (not to exceed the cost of the property), reduced by recoveries, should be treated conclusively as the tentatively deductible amount. Of course, if the item is abandoned or sold for scrap, the loss amount is the adjusted basis reduced by any monetary recovery. Second, no deduction should be allowed for losses attributable to unrealized appreciation. Hence, the tentatively deductible amount should be reduced by the excess, if any, of the pre-loss value over the adjusted basis of the item. Third, it is not clear why casualty and theft losses are allowed to avoid the existing floor by first being netted against recognized casualty and theft gains. 185 Personal consumption losses should not offset recognized gains that are essentially investment gains (other avenues exist for nonrecognition of personal casualty and theft gains, namely, §§ 121 and 1033). This netting rule echoes that of § 1231, but § 1231 would be eliminated under a proposal made above. Also, no good reason exists why recognized personal casualty gains should obtain capital gains treatment, as occurs under § 165(h) when such gains exceed such losses. The issue of loss deductibility should have priority over that of character. The portion of § 165(h) relating to whether the casualty and theft deduction is an itemized deduction or an above-the-line deduction would be rendered moot by the abolition of that distinction. Accordingly, § 165(h) should be mostly repealed, leaving only the floor under the deduction (if retained) in place. 4. Charitable Contributions The charitable deduction has been critiqued (and defended) from many angles, but the only consensus reform proposal is to limit the deduction with respect to donations of appreciated property to the taxpayer’s basis across the board. (As to depreciated-value property, presumably the deduction should be limited to value.) Certainly it is 185. The 1982 Act revised § 165 so that the 10% floor applied to all casualty and theft losses. Tax Equity and Fiscal Responsibility Act of 1982, Pub. L. No. 97-248, 96 Stat. 324. The 1984 Act introduced the complex rules of § 165(h) as a technical correction, apparently designed to cull personal casualty theft and casualty gains and losses out of § 1231. Deficit Reduction Act of 1984, Pub. L. No. 98-369, 98 Stat. 494.
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
119
hard to justify the various distinctions found in § 170(e), which limits the deduction to basis in some cases but not others.186 This reform would advance the cause of simplification of the income tax. Apart from the issue of appreciated-property contributions, the charitable deduction should be subject to a floor, equal to, say, 2% of net income. 187 Viewed instrumentally, the charitable deduction is an incentive to give, but nontax incentives also exist, and it is likely that people would give modest amounts to charity without a tax incentive. A modest floor should actually increase incentives to give at the margin. Moreover, a floor would also eliminate a good deal of trivia (and potential valuation disputes) from the system. Valuation of utilitarian tangible personal property imposes a considerable administrative burden on the tax system. Such property is virtually certain to have depreciated greatly in value and is likely to be slated for abandonment in any event. The donor is hardly incurring any kind of sacrifice by giving these items to a charity, because such items have already been consumed by the donor. Thus, the rationale for any deduction at all in this scenario is very weak and can only survive by supposing both that it is socially better that these items end up in the hands of charity rather than a waste disposal site and that potential donors would prefer (in the absence of a tax incentive) to destroy rather than give. Consideration should be given to authorizing the IRS to issue a valuation table that confers a small (or zero) per item value on such property. 188 Alternatively, the deduction could simply be disallowed for donations of tangible personal property worth less than, say, $200 per item.189 For items of utilitarian tangible personal property that possess significant value and that could either be sold or used by the charity (such as cars, boats, furniture, and computers), a deemedconsignment approach is appropriate: the donor would simply obtain a deduction in the year of sale by the charity in an amount equal to 186. Roughly speaking, the deduction equals basis for (1) property held for less than one year, (2) property given to a private (non-operating) foundation, and (3) tangible personal property not to be used by the donee for its exempt function. The latter category was sufficiently abused that Congress was forced to enact § 170(e)(7) in 2006. 187. That is, only aggregate contributions in excess of 2% would be deductible. Higher (10% of AGI) floors already exist under the medical expense deduction, I.R.C. § 213(a), and the deduction for personal casualty losses, id. § 165(h)(2)(A). Additionally, a 2%-of-AGI floor exists under aggregate “miscellaneous itemized deductions.” Id. § 67(a). 188. Section 170(f)(16), added in 2006, disallows a deduction for clothing and certain household items that are in “good used condition or better.” Id. § 170(f)(16). However, this standard is imprecise and probably unenforceable. The same section allows the IRS to issue a regulation that treats contributed clothing or certain household items of “minimal monetary value” as being worth zero, but no such regulation has been issued, and, again, the standard is vague. Id. 189. Cf. id. § 165(h)(1) (throwing out the first $100 of losses per casualty or theft event).
120
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
the charity’s net sales proceeds.190 It might be objected that the donee might actually use the property, in which case the sales price might turn out to be much lower than the value at the time of contribution. However, since charities have a long history of accommodating donors at the expense of the IRS, a charity’s representations to a donor as to its intentions are unreliable (and unenforceable by the IRS). Hence, the donation rule should induce the charity to sell the donated item in the market and spend the cash on whatever it desires. Another possible reform proposal (possessing a simplification angle) would be to eliminate any income tax deduction for a contribution that will benefit the charity only at or after the donor’s death, generically referred to as a “charitable remainder transfer.” 191 The income tax is an annual tax, and there is no reason why a donor should obtain an income tax deduction in the current year for a transfer not reduced to possession or use by the charity during the year in question, especially if the donor (or the natural object of the donor’s bounty) is enjoying the property in the meantime. The charity really receives no useable value until the retained interest expires. The income tax is not bound to follow the law of future interests. Charitable remainder interests are hard to value, and techniques exist to overvalue the charitable remainder interest relative to the nondeductible retained interest. The ceilings on the charitable deduction are complex and overlapping. Additionally, concern exists that the charitable deduction can be combined with other personal deductions (as well as the personal and dependency exemptions) to virtually zero-out the donor’s tax liability. This problem can be eliminated by imposing a single ceiling as a percentage of taxable income (without regard to the charitable deduction itself). In other words, other deductions would operate to lower the ceiling on the charitable deduction. 5. Medical Care The deduction for medical care, subject to a 10% floor of adjusted gross income, is for uninsured medical costs paid by an individual for herself, her spouse, and her dependents. 192 The floor can effectively 190. A rule of this type already exists in § 170(f)(12), added in 2006, but only for vehicles, boats, and airplanes, and it does not apply to vehicles or airplanes if the donee undertakes “significant intervening use or material improvement.” Id. § 170(f)(12)(A)(ii). This provision is unnecessarily complex, requires paperwork to be provided to the donee and the IRS, and appears to contemplate the possible amendment of the donor’s tax returns. Moreover, it is not clear why it is limited to vehicles, boats, and airplanes. 191. A cognate device is the “direct charitable annuity,” in which a contribution is made in return for an annuity payable by the charity. A unique problem with this device is that the “donor” benefits from the charitable tax exemption in the form of increased annuity payments (relative to the commercial norm). 192. See Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act, Pub. L. No. 111-148, § 9013, 124
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
121
be avoided through medical savings accounts, employer health plans, self-employment health insurance, and (to some extent) selfpurchased insurance. 193 The floor renders the deduction useless for most of those taxpayers unable to avoid it. The Code section allowing the deduction, § 213, has become something of a Christmas tree by reason of being worded in such a way that allows the scope of the deduction to expand endlessly to include borderline items that have more to do with desires than objective health needs. 194 The problem is aggravated by the fact that no political constituency appears to favor the elimination or containment of this deduction. Nevertheless, the deduction (if retained) should be limited to costs for, say, the prevention or cure of disease, the alleviation (other than by over-the-counter drugs) of chronic or abnormal pain, or the correction of a non-self-inflicted work-disabling physical defect or condition. Current health policy favors near-universal coverage through private insurance. It is surprising that the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act of 2010 did not enact an above-the-line deduction for self-purchased health insurance, a move that would have further eroded the significance of § 213. Instead, what the Act gave us was a tax subsidy, effective starting in 2014, for persons (above the eligibility level for Medicaid but below an amount that is four times the applicable poverty level) who purchase health insurance through “exchanges” in the form of a refundable tax credit found in § 36B.195 The credit is extremely complex, and it will undoubtedly require a worksheet. 6. Costs of Tax Planning and Compliance A good case can be made for eliminating the deduction conferred by § 212(3) for costs relating to taxes. This deduction has already been partially repealed by virtue of having been categorized as a mis-
Stat. 119, 868 (2010) (amending I.R.C. § 213). 193. All except the last have the effect of allowing a deduction for the insurance premium, I.R.C. §§ 106, 162(l), 223, plus a tax-free reimbursement for health care costs. The last scenario entails a nondeductible premium combined with such tax-free reimbursement. Reimbursements are tax-free under § 104(a)(3) or § 223(f). Id. §§ 104(a)(3), 223(f). 194. The deduction is overbroad in defining medical care to entail costs relating not to only diseases, but also to costs “affecting any structure or function of the body.” Id. § 213(d)(1)(A). The over-broadness is compounded by the tendency of the medical and, especially, the mental health professions to expand the definition of “disease” to encompass virtually any biological or mental condition that inhibits the attainment of an individual’s personal goals. See O’Donnabhain v. Commissioner, 134 T.C. 34 (2010), acq., 2011-47 I.R.B. 789 (Nov. 21, 2011) (allowing deduction for sex change surgery because “gender identity disorder” is now a “disease” recognized by the mental health profession). 195. Premiums (up to the credit amount) will not also be deductible as medical expenses. I.R.C. § 280C(g).
122
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
cellaneous itemized deduction, 196 and it now chiefly operates to subsidize tax litigation (including criminal tax fraud defense) and tax planning for the wealthy. Despite the fact that tax planning costs are not within the language of the existing statute, the IRS has decided otherwise, without satisfactory explanation.197 Other costs of nonbusiness litigation are not deductible. As a matter of income tax theory, a cost incurred to reduce a nondeductible cost (such as a federal tax) should not be deducted. 198 E. Personal Injury Recoveries Under current law, recoveries for personal physical injuries are excluded under § 104(a)(2). 199 Other tort and tort-like recoveries (including punitive damages and compensatory damages for nonphysical injuries) are included. No persuasive rationale exists for the exclusion. 200 If the exclusion is based upon solicitude for plaintiffs, taxing damages can be overcome by grossing up tort recoveries. The exclusion for plaintiffs can be captured (in whole or in part) by defendants, resulting in failure to internalize fully the social costs of the tort. The distinction between included and excluded damages in turn determines the deductibility of attorney fees and other costs of obtaining recoveries, because only costs allocable to included recoveries are deductible. 201 Since most tort claims are settled, and since private settlement allocations cannot be trusted (no party desires an allocation to punitive damages), it devolves upon tax trial courts to undertake the onerous and costly task of adjudicating the tort claim in order to make an allocation. These issues can be solved in a fashion that simplifies the tax law by making all personal injury recoveries includible. In that case, all costs of obtaining such recoveries (which are really capital expenditures)202 would be deductible.
196. Also, if the deduction reduces taxable income, it is added back to AMT taxable income. 197. See Merians v. Commissioner, 60 T.C. 187 (1973) (noting IRS concession of this issue), acq., 1973-2 C.B. 1 (Dec. 31, 1973). 198. A refund of federal income taxes is excluded from income on account of the fact that the overpaid tax was not deductible. Costs of obtaining excluded income (or nonincome) are not deductible. See I.R.C. § 265(a)(1). Any deduction here can only offset unrelated income. Planning strategies resulting in a reduction of nondeductible federal taxes have the same effect as a refund of overpaid nondeductible federal taxes. 199. Id. § 104(a). 200. See generally Joseph M. Dodge, Taxes and Torts, 77 CORNELL L. REV. 143 (1992). 201. I.R.C. § 265(a)(1) (disallowing expenses of obtaining excluded income). 202. See Joseph M. Dodge, The Netting of Costs Against Income Receipts (Including Damage Recoveries) Produced by Such Costs, Without Barring Congress from Disallowing Such Costs, 27 VA. TAX REV. 297 (2007).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
123
F. Retirement Savings Explicit statutory tax favoritism for savings vehicles exists for certain funded qualified retirement vehicles, herein referred to as “qualified plans,” but the benefit of tax deferral is also obtainable under certain nonqualified (funded and non-funded) arrangements. 1. Qualified Tax-Deferral Retirement Plans Except for Roth IRAs, 203 the basic pattern for qualified retirement savings vehicles under current law is to allow tax-free contributions to an account to be excluded (or included and deducted) by the account owner, the earnings on the account to be tax free, and for the payouts to be fully taxed.204 (a) Complexity in the Service of an Ineffective Policy Design At the individual taxpayer level, the “complexity problem” with current law is the proliferation of tax-favored plan types with assorted requirements pertaining to qualification, taxpayer eligibility, maximum contributions, minimum and maximum distributions, and more.205 Simplification could begin by consolidation of the various existing plan types,206 especially those used by small business owners and self-employed individuals. But tinkering with the existing system is not ambitious enough and may result in further complications.207 203. Roth IRAs generate tax-exempt income from nondeductible contributions, I.R.C. § 408A, and therefore do not fall within the category of “tax-deferral plans.” 204. The tax favoritism consists of a deduction for worker contributions to the plan, contrary to the capitalization principle. Alternatively, an employer’s contribution to a funded plan benefitting the employee is excludible by the employee, but exclusion is the equivalent of inclusion (as compensation for services) and full offsetting deductibility. 205. A good introduction to the system, along with reform proposals, is found in Norman P. Stein, An Alphabet Soup Agenda for Reform of the Internal Revenue Code and ERISA Provisions Applicable to Qualified Deferred Compensation Plans, 56 SMU L. REV. 627 (2003). 206. Qualified plans can be classified according to method of contribution, calculation of benefits, or unique qualification rules, and various categories often overlap or hybridize. Besides Roth IRAs, the following types of plans can be qualified: regular IRAs, “SIMPLE” IRAs, cash or deferred § 401(k) plans, regular pension plans, cash-balance defined benefit plans, pension equity plans, simplified employee pension plans (SEPs), salary-reduction pension plans, profit-sharing defined contribution plans, target-benefit (defined contribution) plans, age-weighted profit-sharing (defined contribution) plans, money purchase (defined contribution) plans, employee stock ownership plans (ESOPs), non-ESOP stock bonus plans, top-heavy plans, annuity § 403(a) plans, exempt-organization annuity § 403(b) plans, and state and local government § 457 plans. See I.R.C. §§ 219, 401(k), 403(b), 408(k), 408(p), 457. The rules pertaining (mostly) to plan qualification occupy 338 pages in the Code alone (the 2012 CCH edition). 207. A retirement income simplification/reform proposal submitted by the American Bar Association Tax Section was released on October 3, 2012. Letter from Rudolph R. Ramelli, Chair of the A.B.A. Section of Taxation, & Charles H. Egerton, Former Chair of the A.B.A. Section of Taxation, to Chairmen and Ranking Members of the S. Comm. on Fin. & H. Comm. on Ways & Means (Oct. 3, 2012), available at http://www.americanbar.org/content/
124
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
The task of meaningful simplification can be approached by way of focusing on the underlying policy rationale for the existing system, which is explicitly that of retirement security. 208 The existing system, overall, is currently embodied in both the Social Security retirement system and the law that governs privately funded retirement plans (the Employee Retirement Income Security Act of 1974 as amended, known as ERISA). 209 Non-workers, ranging from the chronically unemployed to wealthy investors, lie beyond the scope of retirement income security policy.210 A possible approach is to eliminate tax-favored plans entirely and to expand the Social Security retirement system so that it provides an adequate level of wage replacement in retirement for all or most of the workforce.211 Nevertheless, the discussion herein will proceed on the twin assumptions that the Social Security program will continue and that retirement security in excess of Social Security will be privately funded.212 In the context of a privately funded system that supplements Social Security, the concept of retirement income security has two prongs. One is financial security through funding, vesting, nonalienability, plan insurance (for defined benefit plans), and portability, dam/aba/administrative/taxation/100312letter.authcheckdam.pdf. 208. An alternative means of simplification would be to allow universal tax-free savings accounts, but that move would not only entail a major shift towards a cash-flow consumption tax, but would also undermine the goal of income security, as described infra in the text accompanying notes 250-51. 209. The non-tax provisions of ERISA are located at 29 U.S.C. §§ 1001-1461 (2006). The historical evolution of the pension system in the U.S. is recounted in JOHN H. LANGBEIN ET AL., PENSION AND EMPLOYEE BENEFIT LAW 44-63 (5th ed. 2010). 210. It should be noted here that a federal needs-based program, Supplemental Security Income (SSI), provides benefits to low-income persons over age sixty-five, as well as to the disabled and blind. 42 U.S.C. § 1382(a)(1) (2006). In contrast, Social Security retirement benefits are not conditioned on need. Id. § 402(a). 211. It appears that many affluent countries provide a more extensive governmentfunded pension system than does the United States, where the wage replacement rate provided by Social Security appears to be fairly modest. Specifically, the wage replacement rate has been roughly 45% for lowest-quintile wage earners and about 33% for middlequintile workers, with further declines in the two highest quintiles. See Alan Fox, Earnings Replacement Rates and Total Income: Results from the Retirement History Study, 45 SOC. SEC. BULL., Oct. 1982, at 3, 13 (mid-1970s data), available at http://www.ssa.gov/policy/ docs/ssb/v45n10/v45n10p3.pdf; see also LANGBEIN ET AL., supra note 209, at 38-39. The Social Security retirement income program (which is not really contingent on retirement as such) is part of the Old Age, Survivors, and Disability Insurance (OASDI) federal program. To be eligible, a person must contribute to the program for a specified period. Contributions are withheld by employers for employees. See I.R.C. §§ 3101, 3111. Self-employed persons contribute by way of the self-employment tax. See id. §§ 1401-1403. Current contributions fund current benefits, so that the program operates on a pay-as-you go basis, as opposed to an investment basis. 212. Under current demographic assumptions, the Social Security program is, if unchanged, expected to run a large deficit in the future, and, in any event, benefits are estimated to represent a lower rate of return on contributions than would be the case with privately-funded plans. See LANGBEIN ET AL., supra note 209, at 41-43.
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
125
many of which can be (and are) achieved simply by federal government mandates under ERISA, as amended, but which are also incorporated into the tax qualification rules. 213 The second prong of the policy is that of covering virtually the entire workforce. This second aim is merely touched upon by legal mandate.214 Instead, it is almost exclusively the aim of the tax rules, 215 which is to incentivize employers to offer broad-coverage retirement plans (which, inside the firm, are often mandatory for covered employees), with a secondary purpose to incentivize non-covered workers to save for retirement. 216 Unfortunately, the present system of qualified plans has only brought retirement plan coverage up to about half of the workforce, and this coverage is heavily weighted towards high-income employees.217 The reasons for the ineffectiveness of the present system are legion, but the root of the problem is that employers are not required to adopt qualified plans, nor are non-covered workers required to create their own plan. Employers willing to adopt a plan can (and do) effectively avoid covering large portions of their workforce by hiring workers as independent contractors or less-than-half-time workers.218 Additionally, unionized workers can be excluded,219 and benefits and contributions for employees under qualified plans can be integrated with Social Security, thereby effectively reducing plan coverage for low-paid workers.220 Also, the qualification rules themselves contain loopholes 213. See I.R.C. § 401(a)(1), (2), (7). 214. Basically, the legal mandate is that an employer adopting a plan can exclude only part-time employees, employees under the age of twenty-one, or employees with less than one year of service. 29 U.S.C. § 1052 (2006). The same rule appears (in substance) as § 410(a) of the tax Code. See I.R.C. § 410(a). 215. A “minimum coverage” nondiscrimination rule is located at I.R.C. § 410(b). Additionally, contributions or benefits must not discriminate in favor of highly compensated employees. Id. § 401(a)(4). Finally, caps exist on contributions and benefits, id. § 415(b)-(c), which operate mainly to the detriment of high-salary employees. 216. See Bruce Wolk, Discrimination Rules for Qualified Retirement Plans: Good Intentions Confront Economic Reality, in PENSION AND EMPLOYEE BENEFIT LAW, supra note 209, at 402, 402-05. For an account of the enactment of ERISA that stresses the political motivations, see S. SPEC. COMM. ON AGING, 98TH CONG., THE EMPLOYEE RETIREMENT INCOME SECURITY ACT OF 1974: THE FIRST DECADE 1-25 (Comm. Print 1984) (Chapter 1, Overview: Why Was ERISA Enacted? written by Michael S. Gordon). For a more cynical view, see John H. Langbein, Social Security and the Private Pension System, in IN SEARCH OF RETIREMENT SECURITY 109 (Teresa Ghilarducci et al. eds., 2004) (describing the effect of the system as being a stealth program to allow high-income earners to accumulate wealth at low tax rates). 217. See LANGBEIN ET AL., supra note 209, at 25-30. 218. The term “employee” is not actually defined in ERISA, but in Nationwide Mutual Insurance Co. v. Darden, 503 U.S. 318 (1992), the Supreme Court held that independent contractors are excluded. See also Treas. Reg. § 31.3121(c)-(d); Rev. Rul. 87-41, 1987-1 C.B. 296. Employees who work less than twenty hours per week are effectively not considered to be employees. See I.R.C. § 410(a)(3). For a comprehensive discussion of excludible employees, see LANGBEIN ET AL., supra note 209, at 412-15. 219. I.R.C. § 410(b)(3)(A). 220. See generally Keith A. Bender, Characteristics of Individuals with Integrated Pensions, 62 SOC. SEC. BULL., no. 3, 1999, at 28 (noting that integration is allowed in part so
126
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
that allow non-coverage of (especially) low-compensation employees. 221 Finally, the most widely used plan type for self-employed persons is the § 401(k) type of defined contribution plan, which itself is elective on an annual basis. Technicalities aside, the tax incentives for employers and noncovered workers are too feeble. The only current tax inducement to the employer is a current deduction for cash transfers to qualified employee trusts, 222 but a current deduction for cash transfers already accords with income tax norms, and such treatment operates as an incentive only because Congress has imposed an artificial tax disincentive for nonqualified funded plans. 223 The more salient employer tax incentive consists of offering the tax benefits attendant upon qualified plans to highly compensated employees (who presumably control company policy) on condition, by way of nondiscrimination rules, that they offer qualified plans to rank-and-file employees. This indirect, trickle-down, approach is wasteful for several reasons. First, employer-maintained retirement plans for employees below the top tier would exist to a fair degree without tax benefits on account of the dynamics of employee recruitment and collective bargaining. 224 Second, the cost—lost tax revenue—attendant on bribing high-level employees is high, whereas the incentive is weak, because highly-paid employees—who already have the capacity to save—can achieve equivalent or better tax results through other forms of deferred compensation, such as nonqualified arrangements, incentive stock options, and carried interests. 225 Third, the net cost of covering lowerincome employees may outweigh the net tax benefits for high-salary employees. 226 Fourth, workers at the bottom may oppose coverage solely on the ground of a perception (perhaps accurate) that contributions reduce current cash wages dollar for dollar. Fifth, various actors (non-covered employees, self-employed workers, small business owners, and unprofitable businesses) may under-appreciate the benefits of wage-deferral. 227 that the sum of Social Security and qualified plan benefits do not exceed the worker’s wages). 221. Qualification for tax benefits is conditioned on compliance with nondiscrimination rules, I.R.C. §§ 401(a)(4), 410(b), the ineffectiveness of which is critiqued in Peter Orszag & Norman Stein, Cross-Tested Defined Contribution Plans: A Response to Professor Zelinsky, 49 BUFF. L. REV. 629 (2001). 222. I.R.C. § 404(a)(1)-(4) (providing limits on such current deductions). 223. See id. § 404(a)(5) (deferring the employer deduction for nonqualified plans until employee inclusion). 224. Unions that obtain pension plans can justify their existence, while the employer can pass all or a portion of the cost thereof on its workforce and other parties. 225. These devices achieve not only income deferral but also result in capital gains treatment for gain that is essentially compensation for services. 226. See Wolk, supra note 216, at 402-05. 227. A worker without other income at retirement will benefit from shifting income from higher current rate brackets into lower tax rate brackets after retirement. Additionally, under certain assumptions (including one of constant tax rates over time), deducting the
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
127
The foregoing calls into question whether employers should be the focal point of retirement income policy. It is certainly the case that employers are not needed as administrators of funded plans; financial institutions are better positioned to perform this function, as well as that of investment guidance. (b) Plan A: Mandatory Retirement Contributions One simple alternative to the present system is that of mandatory contributions 228 by employers and self-employed persons to privately run individual-account annuity plans that satisfy the essential conditions of retirement income security. 229 Some sweeteners might be required to induce Congress to adopt such an approach, such as waivers for employees covered by existing plans, tax credits to employers to cover a portion of incremental administrative costs, government subsidies for low-wage contributors, and opt-out provisions for highincome workers. 230 The simplification advantage of this approach is obvious: taxdeferral incentives would be unnecessary,231 although tax deferral could still be conferred as a way of increasing the amount of future retirement distributions. (c) Plan B: Tax Subsidies at the Margin The other option is to design more effective tax (or other) mechanisms to achieve the goal of near-universal retirement income securiinvestment and including distributions in full—the paradigm for qualified plans—produces the same after-tax amount as not deducting the investment but fully exempting the net economic return. 228. The contribution would be a specified percentage of a worker’s wages. The percentage could vary with the hourly wage rate, but design issues such as this are beyond the scope of a piece on income tax simplification. 229. See generally PRESIDENT’S COMM’N ON PENSION POLICY, COMING OF AGE: TOWARD A NATIONAL RETIREMENT INCOME POLICY (1981); Tax Analysts, Clinton Details Universal Savings Accounts, Including 401(k) Matches, 1999 TAX NOTES TODAY 72-1; Daniel Halperin, Retirement Income Security After the Fall, in 2009 N.Y.U. REVIEW OF EMPLOYEE BENEFITS AND EXECUTIVE COMPENSATION ch. 11, § 11.09 (2009) (calling for direct government contributions to accounts for low-income workers, to make up for the fact that mandatory contributions would be likely to result in a reduction in wages). 230. A proposal loosely based on these premises, known as the “Universal, Secure, and Adaptable (“USA”) Retirement Funds,” is set out in TOM HARKIN, U.S. S. COMM. ON HEALTH, EDUC., LABOR & PENSIONS, THE RETIREMENT CRISIS AND A PLAN TO SOLVE IT (2012), available at http://www.harkin.senate.gov/documents/pdf/5011b69191eb4.pdf. A similar proposal was made in the 2013 Obama Administration Budget Proposal, see OFFICE OF MGMT. & BUDGET, FISCAL YEAR 2013 BUDGET OF THE U.S. GOVERNMENT 147 (2012), available at http://www.gpa.gov/fdsyspkg/BUDGET-2013-BUD/pdf/BUDGET-2013-BUD.pdf. A feature of these proposals is to transfer investment decisions from individual account holders to professional fiduciaries. 231. Social Security contributions (taxes) paid by an employee are not deductible, I.R.C. § 275(a)(1), and distributions are mostly includible under a complex formula, see id. § 85, that is critiqued supra notes 58-62 and accompanying text.
128
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
ty. Simplification could be obtained by positing a single vehicle for providing such security, which would be the worker-owned Qualified Retirement Account (QRA). Any person having compensation income during the year would be eligible to contribute to such an account, managed by an independent administrator. The QRA would automatically possess the attributes of funding, vesting, and portability. The tax treatment of such accounts would generally follow the present model of tax deferral. Aggregate additions to a worker’s QRA (by the worker’s employers and/or the worker herself) for a given year would be a specified percentage of salary, say, 6%, subject to a fixed-dollar cap.232 Excess additions would not be deductible or excludible (as the case may be), but would create a tax basis in the account. However, if the QRA approach were solely dependent on voluntary worker contributions, the broad-coverage aspect of retirementincome-security policy would essentially be blown off. Tax provisions designed to incentivize broad coverage would reintroduce complexities into the system, but it is hoped that these complexities can be minimized. Perhaps the most effective means of broadening coverage within a QRA system would be to induce employers to provide mandatory QRAs for all of its employees, under which employers would directly transfer cash to the worker QRAs. 233 The optimal tax mechanisms for accomplishing this goal are not self-evident, but some suggestions follow. Some tax benefits should be aimed at employers directly. Among possibilities to be considered are: (1) a modest tax credit to “compensate” the employer for its trouble, 234 (2) a current employer deduction, as under current law, along with a deductionequivalent credit for non-profitable employers. Additionally, a possible “stick” would be to wholly disallow deferred compensation tax deductions for employers failing to adopt a mandatory QRA plan. A possible tax incentive for highly-compensated management to support an employer-sponsored QRA plan would be to provide that adoption of such a plan would result in replacement of the normal fixeddollar cap on annual QRA contributions by a gradual decrease (above the cap amount) in the specified contribution percentage as compensation increases. Thus, if the basic annual contribution limit is 8% of compensation (up to $400,000) not to exceed $32,000 (8% of $400,000), then top management of a company adopting a mandatory plan would be allowed to make additional contributions to their indi232. Under current law, the maximum contribution to an employer-sponsored defined contribution plan is the lesser of 100% of “compensation” or $40,000 (as indexed for inflation). See I.R.C. § 415(c) (the limit was $51,000 in 2013). 233. Amounts within the limitation would be excluded by the worker if provided by the employer and deductible if provided by the employee. Presumably employer contributions, if any, would count first in applying the limitation. 234. Cf. I.R.C. § 45E (credit for small employer pension start-up costs).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
129
vidual QRAs at a rate of, say, 6% on the next $200,000 of compensation, 4% on the next $200,000, and so on. The foregoing may be insufficient to bring employees of small businesses, moderate-to-low income business owners, and other selfemployed persons into the fold. For non-covered low-income workers, an additional refundable credit might be offered for voluntary worker contributions to a QRA, somewhat along the lines of that provided by § 25B.235 The credit can be expressed as a percentage of contributions to a QRA, not to exceed a fixed dollar amount. 236 (d) Defined Benefit Plans Not to be overlooked are employer-funded defined benefit pension plans, 237 as opposed to the individual account plans discussed above. Defined benefit plans are particularly attractive in terms of retirement-income-security policy insofar as benefits are typically expressed as a percentage of wages, and investment risk is borne by the employer instead of the worker. 238 Such plans essentially constitute in-house non-profit annuity companies that require a large actuarial pool. Qualified defined benefit (pension) plans should continue to exist, 239 but tax simplification does not appear to be a significant concern here for individual taxpayers. (e) Mandatory Annuity Pay-Outs Under All Tax-Favored Plans By definition, retirement security entails a funded individual annuity that serves to continue wages (or a portion thereof) after retirement or a specified age until a worker’s death, to protect against the risk of longevity. It follows that annuity pay-outs should be mandatory for all subsidized retirement vehicles.
235. The § 25B credit, however, is nonrefundable, meaning that it has no effect on lowincome workers. Id. § 25B. 236. A tax credit proposal was provided by a group known as Retirement USA. See Proposals for a New Retirement System, RETIREMENT USA (Oct. 21, 2009), http://www.retirement-usa.org/proposals-new-retirement-system. A prominent academic commentator favoring this approach is Halperin, supra note 229, § 11.06. 237. Such plans, which require a large pool of participants, provide salary-replacement payments based on a formula relating to salary history and years of participation. 238. However, portability (avoiding the loss of benefits by reason of changing employers), which is also an aspect of retirement security, is hard to achieve in the case of defined benefit plans except by converting an accrued benefit right into a lump-sum amount that can be rolled over into a defined-contribution plan. 239. As under present law, I.R.C. § 415(b)(1), annual annuity distributions should be capped at a specified amount.
130
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
Additionally, and contrary to present law, 240 a beneficiary of any qualified plan should not be able to withdraw amounts from a QRA before retirement age, except perhaps for permanent disability. 241 (f) Other Issues Numerous other issues would need to be dealt with, including the definition of “employee” for purposes of the ERISA tax rules, 242 possible provision for non-working spouses of working spouses,243 surviving spouses and dependents of workers both before and after the commencement of annuity pay-outs, 244 and divorced spouses. (g) Roth IRAs The Roth IRA, instead of deferral, gives a tax-free return on an after-tax investment.245 Roth IRAs do not conform to the retirementincome-security paradigm because tax-exemption after retirement (as opposed to claiming deductions while working) is preferable to tax deferral only if the owner already has post-retirement taxable income in significant amounts. Additionally, Roth IRAs do not require annuities or even minimal distribution rules, and they allow contributions even after retirement age. 246 In short, Roth IRAs do not advance the policy of retirement income security and function mainly to allow the 240. An annuity is not required for defined contribution plans (including IRAs, § 401(k) plans, and § 403(b) plans), which currently outweigh defined benefit plans in terms of coverage. 241. The current system imposes a 10% penalty on pre-retirement distributions but allows for numerous exceptions. I.R.C. § 72(t). The only exception should lie for permanent disability (premature forced retirement), which can be monitored by the Social Security Administration and can trigger conversion into an individual annuity. Insurance problems (such as a medical emergency) should be dealt with, if at all, by other mechanisms. 242. Currently, “employee” is defined in Treas. Reg. § 31.3121(c)-1(d), which also serves as the definition for income tax withholding and payroll tax purposes. The definition adopts a modified common-law fact-based “control” test. Perhaps the test could itself be simplified. See Calvin H. Johnson, Settle Withholding by the Dollars, Not Control, 136 TAX NOTES 949 (2012). 243. A large percentage of spouses will be employed on their own and will thereby be eligible to contribute to their own qualified plans. It is appropriate that a non-working spouse of a working spouse should be able to contribute to her own QRA on the ground that she is being implicitly paid for domestic labor. 244. The qualified annuity of a person who is married on the annuity starting date could be required to be a self-and-survivor annuity for the annuitant and the annuitant’s spouse, unless the spouse waives the survivorship right. Such a rule exists for certain qualified plans under current law. See I.R.C. §§ 401(a)(11), 417. Of course, a longer expected annuity period results in lower periodic payments. Moreover, a surviving spouse should not receive a greater aggregate annuity than the largest of her own annuity or the deceased spouse’s annuity. Since the purpose of an annuity is the exact reverse of that of life insurance, a QRA should not provide survivorship benefits (or a refund to the deceased worker’s estate) in cases where the QRA owner dies before the annuity starting date. A refund feature would reduce annuity payments. 245. Id. § 408A(c)(1), (d)(1). 246. Id. § 408A(c)(4), (5).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
131
well-off to augment the amount of their bequests. Accordingly, the Roth IRA should be repealed. 247 2. Nonqualified Tax-Deferral Arrangements For non-qualified employer-provided deferred compensation arrangements, tax deferral can be obtained either if the arrangement is unfunded or if the employee’s interest in the plan is funded but subject to a substantial risk of forfeiture.248 On the other hand, if an employer confers upon an employee the right and power to obtain current cash income, the employee would be in constructive receipt of the income (even if the cash is not actually taken) unless a meaningful restriction or penalty would attach to the taking. 249 In other words, the employee is not currently taxed unless she (a) is in constructive receipt of income or (b) receives property (or is a beneficiary of an employer-funded trust that receives cash) that is not subject to a substantial risk of forfeiture. In general, the readily available opportunities for deferral through nonqualified arrangements undermine incentives to create qualified plans 250 and fail to satisfy the policy of retirement income security. 251 (a) Restricted Property Transfers and Funded Nonqualified Plans The general rule is that receipts of cash income are currently included, notwithstanding a risk of forfeiture, and any actual forfeiture gives rise to a deduction in the year of loss. 252 Current § 83(a), which provides otherwise for compensation-related receipts of property interests (including funded deferred compensation), 253 came into existence to accommodate court decisions that failed to treat receipts of property
247. If they are retained, Roth IRAs should be subjected to similar requireddistribution rules as are applicable to tax-deferral plans. 248. Section 83(a) states that the transfer of property to a service provider is current income unless the property is “subject to a substantial risk of forfeiture.” I.R.C. § 83(a). Section 402(b) states that the transfer of cash by an employer to a nonqualified deferred compensation trust is deemed to be a transfer of property to the employee subject to § 83(a). Id. § 402(b). This provision codifies the tax common law rule known as the economic benefit doctrine. John F. Cooper, The Economic Benefit Doctrine: How an Unconditional Right to a Future Benefit can Cause a Current Tax Detriment, 71 MARQ. L. REV. 270, 273 (1988). 249. Treas. Reg. § 1.451-2(a). 250. Nonqualified deferral plans are, by reason of not being subject to a nondiscrimination requirement, usually limited to highly compensated service providers. Thus, availability of such plans undermines the goal of retirement security for most of the workforce. 251. An arrangement that is unfunded and/or subject to a substantial risk of forfeiture—and is not annuitized—hardly provides for retirement income security. 252. See James v. United States, 366 U.S. 213 (1961); N. Am. Oil Consol. v. Burnet, 286 U.S. 417, 424 (1932). 253. Section 402(b) provides that transfers of cash to a deferred compensation plan shall be treated as transfers of property subject to § 83. I.R.C. § 402(b).
132
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
subject to a significant risk of forfeiture the same as receipts of cash.254 This differing tax treatment of forfeitable cash and forfeitable property is hard to justify as a matter of policy, 255 especially where the “property” is nothing more than a right to future cash. 256 Moreover, restrictions on property given as compensation can be viewed as selfimposed (or at least willingly accepted) by virtue of the benefit of tax deferral, and tax deferral for nonqualified arrangements conflicts with the overriding policy of retirement income security through qualified plans. 257 The cleanest solution would be to alter § 83 so as to be in accord with the treatment of “restricted” cash. Accordingly, the property should be included at the time of receipt and valued without regard to the restrictions.258 Such a revised § 83 should provide that the service provider obtains an ordinary loss deduction upon any actual forfeiture. Property that has no ascertainable fair market value on receipt, such as nontransferable (and not-in-the-money) stock options and pure profits interests, are subject to a different default rule, namely: no inclusion until cash receipt (or until the property can be reasonably valued, such as upon the exercise of the option or the obtaining of liquidation rights).259 Current rules generally accord with this principle,260 but the principle should be made into a universal rule, which means eliminating the special tax breaks given to incentive stock options (ISOs) 254. The doctrinal problem was the notion that the receipt of property as compensation, although normally an income realization event, avoided current inclusion because the forfeiture condition rendered the property incapable of valuation when received (assuming that any transferee would also be subject to the forfeiture condition). See Kuchman v. Commissioner, 18 T.C. 154 (1952) (holding forfeitable property not currently included). Not so justifiable in terms of doctrine was Lehman v. Commissioner, 17 T.C. 652 (1951), where it was held that no income arose upon the lapse of such a restriction, resulting in deferral (and capital gains treatment) until the property was sold. The IRS acquiesced in these cases in Rev. Rul. 68-86, 1968-1 C.B. 184. Section 83(a), enacted in 1969, deferring compensation until the lapse of the forfeiture restriction, can be described as a compromise between this case law and the tax rules for cash. See I.R.C. § 83(a). 255. The difference in tax results channels transactions of this sort into the property mode. 256. The rationale of Kuchman, 18 T.C. at 163, was that forfeitable property was not capable of valuation and therefore not currently realized income. See supra the doctrine and text accompanying note 254. However, the courts could have treated the restriction as being personal and not an aspect of the property itself. However, the restriction can be made to be on the property by a provision that all transferees are subject to the restriction. In any event, Congress can do what the courts fail to do. 257. The argument in favor of § 83 is that forfeiture conditions (usually, leaving the firm) align the interests of employee and employer, but this is not a concern of tax policy. Moreover, the proposed change in tax treatment does not prohibit such forfeiture conditions. 258. Current § 83(a) states that non-forfeiture restrictions are to be ignored in valuing in-kind compensation. I.R.C. § 83(a). 259. See Commissioner v. LoBue, 351 U.S. 243, 248 (1956); Treas. Reg. § 1.83-7. 260. See I.R.C. § 83(e)(3)-(4).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
133
and employee stock purchase plans.261 Additionally, any income realized under this type of arrangement should be ordinary income.262 (b) Non-Funded Plans The core principle for non-funded, purely contractual deferred compensation arrangements is that deferral is obtainable in the absence of the constructive receipt of cash income, but, as already noted, constructive receipt is easily avoided by imposing a more-than-deminimis penalty on demanding current cash. Section 409A, which was enacted in 2004 to deal with certain problems relating to nonqualified deferred compensation, is framed in these terms: “The [House] Committee believes that certain arrangements that allow participants inappropriate levels of control or access to amounts deferred should not result in deferral of income inclusion.” 263 Section 409A requires current inclusion in gross income, with interest and penalties, of nonqualified rights to future compensation (funded or non-funded), unless various anti-abuse rules are complied with. 264 With regard to non-funded arrangements, § 409A has effectively expanded the constructive receipt doctrine by requiring immediate inclusion of rights to future cash unless the arrangement (1) prohibits last-minute deferral decisions and elective accelerations of deferred benefits and (2) requires deferred amounts to be distributed only upon objectively determinable occurrences. 265 Section 409A is considered to be an excessively complex and openended response to the stated abuses.266 The governing concept here should be that tax deferral of salary is essentially not justified at all for tax reasons unless pursuant to a government mandate or under a funded qualified plan, while acknowledging that certain rights to future cash cannot be currently taxed due to future contingencies. Accordingly, deferral should be “allowed” for non-funded arrangements only if (a) no short-term cash-or-deferral elections are available and (b) the plan prohibits—and does not in fact make—distributions on 261. See id. §§ 83(e)(1), 421-424 (providing for no taxation until the sale of the stock, with any gain being capital gain). 262. Deferred compensation that is tied to changes in stock prices is apparently within the scope of § 409A. Id. § 409A. Under Treas. Reg. § 1.409A-1(b)(5)(i)(A), (C), a nonqualified stock option may be exempt if it (a) is not in the money when granted or (b) is “service recipient stock” (common stock of the employer). Section 409A, if it is retained in any form, should not apply to nonqualified stock options, since the exercise of an option is not a distribution, nor does it represent an ability to obtain the employer’s cash. 263. See H.R. REP. NO. 108-548, pt. 1, at 343 (2d Sess. 2004). 264. See I.R.C. § 409A(a)(1)(A)(i). 265. See id. § 409A(a)(2)-(4). These rules also apply to funded arrangements, but in that context they would be irrelevant if forfeiture conditions could no longer achieve deferral. 266. The proposed regulations under § 409A take up 103 pages in the 2013 CCH Federal Tax Reporter. Section 409A apparently applies to nonqualified stock options and splitdollar life insurance arrangements.
134
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
any occasion other than reaching a certain age or long-term disability. In cases where current inclusion would occur except for future contingencies that render the right to future cash incapable of valuation, a penalty tax, say, 10%, would be imposed on actual pay-outs. 3. Rabbi Trusts The IRS has held that a Rabbi trust (a funded deferred compensation trust that is reachable by the employer’s creditors) is not truly “funded” for tax purposes, 267 and therefore falls into the category of contractual deferred compensation. Section 409A(b) taxes to the employee employer contributions to a Rabbi trust that is offshore and any nonqualified deferred compensation amount subject to an employer’s financial-health contingency. 268 These rules partially overlap, and it should suffice to provide that financial contingencies of an employer should not be taken into account in determining that a contribution has been made by an employer to a deferred compensation arrangement (i.e., that the trust is funded). 269 At this point, deferral would be impossible if Congress repeals the rule pertaining to forfeiture conditions.270 If the risk-of-forfeiture rule is retained, it should be provided that financial and investment risks should themselves not be viewed as substantial risks of forfeiture. G. Foreign Income of U.S. Nationals The United States generally taxes U.S. citizens and residents (“U.S. nationals”) on worldwide income. If another country happens to tax foreign-source income of a U.S. national, the United States generally allows a tax credit against the U.S. tax on the same income (but not to exceed the average U.S. tax on the same income). 271 1. Repeal the Exclusion for Foreign-Source Earned Income Current § 911 allows an exclusion from U.S. tax for foreign-source personal services (i.e., “earned”) income up to $80,000, as adjusted for inflation ($97,600 in 2013), of a U.S. national if the U.S. national has 267. See Rev. Proc. 92-64, 1992-2 C.B. 422; I.R.S. Priv. Ltr. Rul. 81-13-107 (Dec. 31, 1980). 268. I.R.C. § 409A(b). 269. Since the underlying rule—that funded rights to future cash are current property rights—is indifferent to the relationship between the parties (or the nature of the income), the rule proposed here should be made applicable to trusts benefitting independent contractors as well as employees. 270. However, a funded (defined contribution) nonqualified plan must (generally) fully vest within five years. See Employee Retirement Income Security Act, 29 U.S.C. § 1053(a)(2)(A)(ii) (2006). Full vesting removes conditions of forfeiture and would require income inclusion under § 83(a). I.R.C. § 83(a). 271. I.R.C. §§ 901, 904(a).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
135
a “tax” home outside of the U.S. and meets a foreign residency test. 272 The calculation of the exclusion is complicated by a deduction for the “foreign housing cost amount,” determined under a formula. 273 The exclusion is hotly contested in tax policy circles and is the only significant exception to U.S. taxation of its own nationals. Earned income is foreign-source if the taxpayer performs the services abroad.274 The exclusion allows creative talents, consultants, and any person who can perform technical services from a non-U.S. location to avoid U.S. tax, even if there is no business reason to perform these services abroad (or in the country of residence). The income can be earned in a tax haven country that imposes little or no tax on the income, or perhaps in a non-tax-haven country that exempts certain types of services income by statute or under an income tax treaty with the United States. The argument for the foreign-income exclusion is no stronger than that for excluding all foreign-source income (or perhaps foreignsource business income) of a U.S. individual taxpayer from U.S. tax. 275 But, if the United States were to move wholesale to a territorial system that applied to individual taxpayers, source rules would come under scrutiny. The source rule for services is mechanical and bears little relationship to U.S. policy interests.276 In the context of the prevailing U.S. norm of taxing U.S. nationals on world-wide income, it is hard to see what purpose the § 911 exclusion serves. In the current world economic climate, it has little to do with exploiting foreign markets or tapping into foreign labor supplies.277 Removing the exemption would do no real harm, because the foreign tax credit would be available to avoid double taxation of foreign-source earned income. Also, income tax treaty provisions can be negotiated with a view of curbing host country taxation of temporary visitors. 278 2. Expand the Simple Version of the Foreign Tax Credit The operation of the foreign tax credit is normally quite complex, as it involves the application of “basket limitations” for foreign pas272. Id. § 911 (citizens or residents of the United States living abroad). 273. See id. § 911(a)(2), (c). 274. Id. § 861(a)(3). 275. The tax systems of some prominent trading partners of the United States have a territorial slant, especially where corporations are involved. See HUGH J. AULT & BRIAN J. ARNOLD, COMPARATIVE INCOME TAXATION 446-52, 467-71 (3d ed. 2010). 276. The income is sourced where the services are performed, not, say, where the benefit of the services are obtained. See I.R.C. § 861(a)(3). 277. The exclusion is critiqued in CHARLES H. GUSTAFSON ET AL., TAXATION OF INTERNATIONAL TRANSACTIONS 454-57 (4th ed. 2011). 278. See INTERNAL REVENUE SERVICE, UNITED STATES MODEL INCOME TAX CONVENTION OF NOVEMBER 15, 2006, arts. 14, 16 (2006), available at http://www.irs.gov/pub/irstrty/model006.pdf.
136
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
sive income and for other foreign income. 279 Individual taxpayers paying modest amounts of foreign tax should not be involved with these complications. Under § 904(k), the foreign tax credit limitations do not apply if the taxpayer’s foreign income is entirely passive and the creditable foreign taxes do not exceed $300. This provision should be liberalized by eliminating the passive income requirement and increasing the maximum foreign tax amount to, say, $1000. H. Entity Taxation The taxation of family business enterprise impacts the taxation of individual taxpayers. The discussion below assumes the implementation of a corporate tax “reform” that includes a reduction in tax rates for C corporations relative to individual tax rates. 280 Interestingly, such a “reform” would create several opportunities for simplification. 1. Mandatory Pass-Through Regime for All Non-Publicly Traded Business Entities If C corporation tax rates are less than individual tax rates, and if the present system is otherwise unchanged, the accumulation/bailout game would be revived for closely held entities that elect to do business as a C corporation.281 This opportunity can be foreclosed by requiring all non-public business entities and their equity holders to be subject to pass-through taxation. 282 The liquidity premium incident to public trading is what perhaps justifies a separate business entity tax to begin with. Accordingly, only publicly traded entities would be subject to the (reduced) C corporation tax. No reason exists to condition pass-through treatment of corporations on having no more than a specified number of shareholders, as currently exists with S corporations.283
279. See I.R.C. § 904(d). 280. The American Taxpayer Relief Act of 2012, Pub. L. No. 112-240, 126 Stat 2313 (2013), raised the highest individual rate to 39.6%, leaving the highest corporate rate at 35%. 281. The game consists of accumulating corporate earnings at a relatively low tax rate, deferring or abstaining from dividend payments, and realizing on the value of the appreciated stock at low individual capital gains rates (with basis offset). Anti-bailout provisions were salient features of corporate taxation during periods when the game was being played. See, e.g., I.R.C. §§ 531-537 (accumulated earnings tax); id. §§ 541-547 (personal holding company tax); id. § 341 (repealed) (collapsible corporation provision); id. §§ 302, 304, 306, 355, 1248 (current Code). 282. “Pass-through taxation” means that profits and losses are attributed (passed through) to the equity holders, with no tax at the entity level. 283. See I.R.C. § 1361(b)(1)(A), (c) (S corporation cannot have more than 100 shareholders). A study by the American Law Institute proposes removal of this feature. See GEORGE K. YIN & DAVID J. SHAKOW, AM. LAW INST., TAXATION OF PRIVATE BUSINESS ENTERPRISES 170-72 (1999).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
137
It might be argued that pass-through treatment is not appropriate for non-public corporations with complex capital structures, because here the burden of losses is not settled by contract or organizational structure, as it is with a partnership or LLC. The difficulty of profit and loss allocation is perhaps overrated. For example, holders of preferred interests can be taxed like debt-holders, 284 and the profit shares of other equity interests would be spelled out. The issue of loss shares in multi-tier pass-through corporations has been addressed by me elsewhere. 285 Pass-through treatment of non-public corporations would render pointless the personal holding company tax and the accumulated earnings tax, which could be repealed. The proposed change would also simplify the task of entity classification for tax purposes and reduce the factors entering into choice of tax entity decisions into one, namely, whether equity interests in the entity are to be publicly traded, which is a decision that would normally be made on nontax grounds. 2. A Simplified Pass-Through Regime Under a mandatory pass-through system for non-public entities, it might be desirable to offer separate pass-through regimes, as exists under current law: (a) the relatively simple S corporation regime, elective for a corporation meeting certain eligibility requirements (such as the one-class-of-stock rule), and (b) the complex passthrough regime for tax partnerships. 286 However, an S corporation cannot currently elect into Subchapter K, and a partnership (or other entity, such as an LLC, that is eligible to be taxed as a partnership) cannot elect subchapter S status. It is proposed that non-public business entities be allowed to choose between a simple and a complex pass-through regime, or, more modestly, that a tax partnership be allowed to elect into Subchapter S (as modified to accommodate partnerships). 287
284. That is, holders of preferred interests would be taxed on dividends paid (and possibly dividends accrued), which would be deducted by the entity, thereby reducing passthrough income. 285. See Joseph M. Dodge, A Combined Mark-To-Market and Pass-Through CorporateShareholder Integration Proposal, 50 TAX L. REV. 265, 319-23 (1995). 286. See I.R.C. §§ 1366-1377 (operative rules for S corporations); id. §§ 702-761 (operative rules for entities taxed as partnerships). The differences are explained in Walter D. Schwidetzky, Integrating Subchapters K and S—Just Do It, 62 TAX LAW. 749 (2009). 287. Compare YIN & SHAKOW, supra note 283, at 131-272 (proposing a simplified version of conduit taxation for eligible private business organizations that so elect), with Schwidetzky, supra note 286 (essentially proposing elimination of Subchapter S).
138
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
3. Nondeductibility of C Corporation Interest Under present law, the distinction between corporate debt and equity is salient, because interest and dividends carry different tax treatment to both the corporate entity 288 and the equity holders,289 resulting in a distortive incentive to use debt. 290 Additionally, the distinction is often difficult to apply in practice, and, being highly factintensive, is costly to administer and uncertain in result. 291 From the policy angle, the interest deduction can combine with business tax preferences to generate a very low, zero, or even negative income tax on business earnings derived from capital, resulting in the misallocation of capital to marginal or bad investments. 292 These problems can be solved by disallowing interest deductions for C corporations—at least those in which capital is a material income-producing factor. This disallowance would be a fair trade-off for reducing the corporate tax rate. Indeed, it should generate sufficient revenue to enable Congress to enact a truly significant reduction in the corporate tax rate. 293 4. Eliminate Capital Gains Treatment of Dividends Under current law, most dividends received from corporations are treated as long-term capital gains.294 This special treatment (along with the capital gains preference) operates, as far as corporate equity is concerned, as a form of “partial” corporate/shareholder integration by significantly reducing the shareholder-level tax. However, it is better (in theory) to tax corporate profits at the level of individuals receiving distributions, not the entity, because, although it is easy to collect tax at the corporate level, the incidence of the corporate tax is unknown and could vary among industries and firms. 295 Moreover, a 288. Interest is generally deductible, I.R.C. § 163(a), whereas dividends are not. 289. Interest is ordinary income, whereas “qualified dividend income” is currently treated as “net capital gain.” Id. § 1(h)(11)(A). 290. The tax incentive to use debt financing often overwhelms nontax factors in choosing finance mechanisms. Additionally, interest can be used to shift income away from U.S. debtors to related foreign parties. See I.R.C. § 163(j). 291. Section 385 was enacted in 1969 to deal with this issue, but that section is contingent on the issue of regulations, and final regulations have never been issued. 292. Expensing of capital expenditures results in “single” taxation of investment returns, whereas the exclusion of borrowing and deduction of interest yield “double” deduction of interest, viewing both phenomena in present value terms. 293. Limiting the current interest deduction to business or investment income, see id. §§ 163(d), 469, would fail to solve the arbitrage problem of combining the current treatment of debt with consumption-tax treatment of investments. It might be contended that certain interest (e.g., on purchase-money loans used to purchase real estate) should be exempt from any disallowance rule, but if borrowed money is truly fungible, then such a contention loses force. 294. See id. § 1(h)(11). 295. See Forum: Incidence of the Corporate Income Tax, 66 NAT’L TAX J. 149-262 (2013) (introduction and four articles).
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
139
significant reduction in the C corporation rate itself operates as a form of partial integration. Many of the leading trading partners of the U.S. have moved to partial integration systems of various types. Accordingly, a significant reduction in the corporate tax rate should be accompanied by restoration of the status of dividends as ordinary income. Also, insofar as a capital gains preference for stock gains and dividends is justified as a partial integration measure, such preference would become redundant to the low corporate tax rate.296 5. Repeal the Earnings and Profits Apparatus Under current law, a non-liquidation distribution from a C corporation is gross income only to the extent it is deemed to come out of the corporation’s post-1913 earnings and profits (E & P). 297 E & P is a financial accounting construct, and one has to make numerous adjustments to taxable income to calculate it. Additionally, rules are required to determine what distributions reduce E & P. 298 These rules, which are wholly arbitrary, operate so that a few corporations still are deemed to possess pre-1913 E & P.299 The entire E & P system is much ado about practically nothing, as the E & P system rarely prevents non-liquidation distributions from being taxable dividends. From another angle, the taxation of equity investments should be separated from any taxation of the underlying entity. The E & P mechanism operates inappropriately as a capital recovery for corporate equity. Shares of stock are correctly not subject to depreciation, because corporate equity has an indefinite useful life. Additionally, partial loss deductions are not generally allowed under the income tax. 300 Thus, recovery of capital under a realization income tax should not be allowed unless there is a true disposition of all or a physical portion of an asset. Stated in abstract terms, taxation of an investment should depend only on the investment and its economic return,
296. A 1982 study estimated that corporate stocks and bonds accounted for almost 37% of total assets for all top wealthholders, closely followed by real estate (gains on which are already largely exempt under § 121), with other categories being relatively insignificant. See Marvin Schwartz, Estimates of Personal Wealth, 1982: A Second Look, SOI BULL., Spring 1988, at 31, 32. Thus, the capital gains (and dividends) tax preference could be wholly eliminated, or at least targeted to individuals investing in family-owned businesses. 297. Corporate distributions in excess of E & P are tax free due to the shareholder’s stock basis offsetting the cash received, and distributions in excess of basis are treated as gains from the sale of the stock. See I.R.C. §§ 301(c)(1), 316(a). 298. See id. § 312. 299. The general rule is that distributions are deemed to come out of the most-recentlyacquired E & P. See id. § 316(a)(2). This last-in, first-out (LIFO) convention is the opposite of the most commonly used convention for inventory, which is first-in, first-out (FIFO). 300. See Citizens Bank of Weston v. Commissioner, 252 F.2d 425 (4th Cir. 1958); Lakewood Assocs. v. Commissioner, 109 T.C. 450 (1997); Pulvers v. Commissioner, 48 T.C. 245 (1967), aff’d, 407 F.2d 838 (9th Cir. 1969).
140
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
not on the remote source of the return. 301 The fact that dividends are not deductible represents the decision that corporate taxable income is a tax base independent from the tax base of the shareholders. (In contrast, the net income of a trust or estate is viewed as a pool of income that can only be taxed once.) A (pro rata) non-liquidation distribution is not a disposition of an investment or a portion thereof, but only a cash return thereon: the shareholder retains the same right to future distributions and same degree of control as existed before. The fact that the corporate assets have shrunk in size is immaterial. Such shrinking would cause the value of the stock to decrease, but that decrease is simply unrealized depreciation, and unrealized depreciation is not deductible under a realization income tax. The E & P mechanism, in short, is contrary to both the realization principle and the separation of the corporate and individual income taxes. Accordingly, the E & P apparatus should be jettisoned, and all prorata non-liquidation distributions should be treated as gross income.302 The notion of a “partial liquidation” distribution, resulting in a basis offset without an actual surrender of stock, could be retained.303 However, since the same basis offset as is desired in a partial liquidation can be obtained by (1) dropping assets into a newly-created controlled corporation, (2) distributing the stock of that corporation to the shareholders of the distributing corporation, and (3) liquidating the corporation whose stock was distributed, 304 the qualification requirements for obtaining a basis offset in a partial liquidation should be essentially the same as would qualify a distribution of stock in a controlled corporation for tax-free treatment under § 355. 305 301. Basis recovery in the case of an annuity or a level-payment debt obligation is based on the notion that each cash receipt marks the disposition of a component of the asset. 302. For other critiques of the current system, see William D. Andrews, “Out of Its Earnings and Profits”: Some Reflections on the Taxation of Dividends, 69 HARV. L. REV. 1403 (1956), and Walter J. Blum, The Earnings and Profits Limitation on Dividend Income: A Reappraisal, 53 TAXES 68 (1975). 303. See I.R.C. § 302(e) (qualified partial liquidation treated as sale of portion of shareholder’s stock). 304. The assets of the terminal business can be placed in a separate corporation tax free, id. § 368(a)(1)(D), the stock of which is distributed to the existing shareholders tax free, id. § 355, and that corporation can be liquidated in a transaction treated as a sale with basis offset, id. § 331(a). 305. The three-step transaction described at the beginning of this text sentence achieves the same result as a partial liquidation under § 302(e) only if step (2) thereof—the distribution of controlled corporation stock—qualifies as a tax-free distribution under § 355. Current § 355, in turn, has various qualification requirements, including (1) the distributed corporation must contain assets of an active business that has been carried on for at least five years, (2) that business must be carried on immediately after the distribution, and (3) the transaction must not be a disguised dividend (which would be indicated by a prior agreement to sell or liquidate the distributed corporation). See id. § 355(a)(1)(B), (b). The requirements of current § 302(e) are more lax, requiring either that a business (carried on for five years) be terminated or that the transaction not be essentially the equivalent of
2013]
SIMPLIFICATION PROPOSALS
141
An issue is whether, as a transitional rule, existing corporations would be allowed to declare pre-1913 E & P and apply it against the first post-enactment dividends until pre-1913 E & P is exhausted. However, all current distributions with respect to stock are income to the shareholder when received and cannot be pre-1913 income of the shareholder. There is no constitutional requirement that dividends out of pre-1913 E & P must be exempt, especially since the accounting convention that has the effect of preserving pre-1913 E & P is arbitrary. 306 In fact, Lynch v. Hornby 307 held precisely that a post1913 dividend paid out of profits accumulated before 1913 could be constitutionally taxed. 308 Therefore, any such transition rule would be unnecessary and, in my view, unwarranted. V. CONCLUSION The emphasis here has been on proposals that fit into a realization income tax, which would simplify compliance and administration for the bulk of individual taxpayers. The proposals made herein (some original, some not) advance only some simplification moves among the many that are possible. Other kinds of proposals can be imagined, such as simplifying depreciation accounting (or eliminating depreciation altogether). International taxation is another area that is only lightly considered herein. Tax academics are often skeptical of a simplification agenda. Tax law, as well as life itself, is complex, and tax professionals thrive on complexity. Thus, we tax professionals have a vested interest in the fact that we have mastered the intricacies of the tax law, which is a major component of our human capital. But we tend to overlook the fact that tax law is not self-executing. Accordingly, we tend to overestimate the ability of the IRS and the general population to follow what we have wrought. In any event, the simplification agenda is not necessarily bad news for tax professionals. The reader will have undoubtedly noted that many of the proposals made herein are not fully developed and would require further working out. Some may even turn out to be non-viable from the simplification angle itself. Tax professionals should be as good at creating simple, workable solutions to a dividend at the corporate level (meaning, in effect, that a meaningful contraction of the corporation’s business occurred). 306. Doyle v. Mitchell Bros. Co., 247 U.S. 179 (1918), construed the 1909 corporate income tax to exclude pre-enactment appreciation. However, since a tax on gross receipts (without basis offset) is constitutional as an indirect tax, basis recovery cannot be constitutionally required. See Joseph M. Dodge, Murphy and the Sixteenth Amendment in Relation to the Taxation of Non-Excludable Personal Injury Awards, 8 FLA. TAX REV. 369, 401-07 (2007). 307. Lynch v. Hornby, 247 U.S. 339 (1918). 308. I.R.C. § 316(a)(1), excluding distributions from pre-1913 E & P, is, therefore, not constitutionally required.
142
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:71
existing complexities as they are at mastering existing ones. It is certainly a lot more enjoyable.
A PROPOSED REPLACEMENT OF THE TAX EXPENDITURE CONCEPT AND A DIFFERENT PERSPECTIVE ON ACCELERATED DEPRECIATION DOUGLAS A. KAHN* I. II. III.
IV.
INTRODUCTION ...................................................................................................... REPLACEMENT OF THE TAX EXPENDITURE CONCEPT ......................................... DEPRECIATION DEDUCTIONS ................................................................................ A. Economic Depreciation .................................................................................... B. Proper Method of Depreciation ........................................................................ C. Illustration of a Flaw in the Tax Expenditure Concept ................................. CONCLUSION..........................................................................................................
143 145 153 154 155 157 158
I. INTRODUCTION The concept of tax expenditures has been widely accepted1 and has even been adopted into federal law, which requires the annual promulgation of tax expenditure budgets.2 Pursuant to that mandate, several federal governmental offices publish lists of what they deem to be tax expenditures. One such budget is published by the Department of Treasury,3 and a different budget is published by the Staff of the Joint Committee on Taxation.4 While there is considerable overlap in those two budgets, they are not identical, and they utilize different norms and baselines for determining what constitutes a tax expenditure.5 In addition, forty-five states publish their own versions of a tax expenditure budget.6 The theme of the tax expenditure concept is that some tax provisions are not elements of a normal or ideal system of income taxation and that such provisions are designed indirectly to finance a program that Congress has chosen to support.7 The listed tax provisions are designated as * Paul G. Kauper Professor, University of Michigan Law School. The author thanks Justin Hoag for his assistance in the preparation of this Essay. 1. Professor Zelinsky observed in a recent article that the advocates of the tax expenditure concept have prevailed and that the federal government and the governments of forty-five states publish tax expenditure budgets. See Edward A. Zelinsky, The Counterproductive Nature of Tax Expenditure Budgets, 137 TAX NOTES 1317 (2012). 2. 2 U.S.C. § 622(3) (2012) defines the terms “tax expenditures” and “tax expenditures budget.” Section 632(e)(1) requires the Committee on the Budget of both houses of Congress to publish a report each fiscal year, and the report must contain a tax expenditure budget. Id. § 632(e)(2)(E). 31 U.S.C. § 1105(a)(16) (2006) requires the president to submit a budget each year, which must include a tax expenditure budget. 3. OFFICE OF MGMT. & BUDGET, EXEC. OFFICE OF THE PRESIDENT, ANALYTICAL PERSPECTIVES: BUDGET OF THE U.S. GOVERNMENT, FISCAL YEAR 2014, at 241-77 (2013). 4. STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, 113TH CONG., ESTIMATES OF FEDERAL TAX EXPENDITURES FOR FISCAL YEARS 2012–2017 (Joint Comm. Print 2013). 5. Id. at 1, 20-22. 6. Frank Shafroth, Tax Expenditures: A Most Taxing Challenge, 64 ST. TAX NOTES 327 (2012). 7. STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, supra note 4, at 2 (“Special income tax provisions
144
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:143
disguised expenditures of the government that should be subjected to the same scrutiny as are direct expenditures.8 While there is considerable overlap in the items listed in the two federal tax expenditure budgets, there are differences because they do not utilize the same baseline. The budgets also provide an estimate of the amount of revenue that the government loses because of the inclusion in tax law of each such designated provision.9 There are several questions concerning the premise on which the various tax expenditure budgets rest. First, is there a “pure” or “ideal” income tax system? Second, even if there is one, was there any intention by the legislators to adopt a system that would accord with a pure income tax system? Third, as a matter of policy, would it be desirable to adopt a tax system that comports with a pure income tax system? I will explore these questions in this Essay. In prior articles, I have expressed my view that the tax expenditure concept is flawed and misleading.10 In this Essay, I will set forth a view of the structure of the federal income tax system that is different from, and in contravention of, the view underlying the tax expenditure concept. I propose an entirely different standard for measuring the appropriateness of a tax provision. The tax expenditure concept is based on a binary approach in categorizing tax provisions. Under that system, an item either is consistent with normal tax provisions or is inconsistent with them. There are no shades of consistency. Instead, I propose a multivariate standard for evaluating tax provisions. Over 32 years ago, I published an article on accelerated depreciation in which I concluded that some amount of acceleration was consistent with normal tax principles and should not be classified as a tax expenditure.11 Over the intervening years, from time to time, I have exchanged comments with authors who have questioned that conclusion.12 It is time
are referred to as tax expenditures because they may be analogous to direct outlay programs and may be considered alternative means of accomplishing similar budget policy objectives.”). 8. There are reasons to question just how much scrutiny is given to direct expenditures. Many governmental programs, such as Social Security, Medicare, and Medicaid dispense large amounts of money without any congressional oversight of the programs. See AARON WILDAVSKY, THE POLITICS OF THE BUDGETARY PROCESS 213-16 (2d ed. 1974) (explaining that members of Congress have increasingly become “negligent guardians” of the purse). 9. The two budgets utilize different methodologies in determining the amount of revenue that is lost. STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, supra note 4, at 20-22. 10. See, e.g., Douglas A. Kahn & Jeffrey S. Lehman, Tax Expenditure Budgets: A Critical View, 54 TAX NOTES 1661 (1992) (criticizing the tax expenditure concept’s assumption of “[a]n ideal Internal Revenue Code”). 11. Douglas A. Kahn, Accelerated Depreciation—Tax Expenditure or Proper Allowance for Measuring Net Income?, 78 MICH. L. REV. 1 (1979). 12. See, e.g., Walter J. Blum, Accelerated Depreciation: A Proper Allowance for Measuring Net Income?!!, Comment, 78 MICH. L. REV. 1172 (1980); Douglas A. Kahn, Accelerated Depreciation Revisited—A Reply to Professor Blum, 78 MICH. L. REV. 1185 (1980).
2013]
A PROPOSED REPLACEMENT
145
to revisit that topic and renew the consideration of how tax depreciation may properly operate. This Essay’s analysis of depreciation provides one example of how the tax expenditure budgets are flawed. The treatment of some accelerated depreciation as a tax expenditure is based on a view that any acceleration conflicts with normal tax principles.13 I will show in this Essay that when the structure of depreciation is examined, it becomes clear that there is more than one way to determine what allowance for depreciation should be made. Furthermore, allowing acceleration does not contravene any established tax principles. It is not the thesis of this Essay that acceleration is the only proper method of tax depreciation. To the contrary, it is my view that many forms of depreciation are proper and comply with normal tax principles, and that accelerated depreciation is merely one of the appropriate methods that can be authorized. II. REPLACEMENT OF THE TAX EXPENDITURE CONCEPT Even those that admire the tax expenditure concept acknowledge that there is a problem in identifying many of the items that constitute expenditures because there is not universal agreement as to what constitutes a pure income tax system. Such a system is the base against which tax provisions are measured to determine whether they are “pure” tax provisions or tax expenditures.14 Nevertheless, these commentators note that there are many clear examples of what are and are not tax expenditures, so they approve of the concept and regard any questionable inclusions in the budgets as minor discrepencies.15 It is noteworthy that some of the items that are regarded by the concept’s proponents as clearly constituting expenditures are not so regarded by some other commentators. For example, Professors Chirelstein and Zelenak state that all personal deductions, such as charitable contributions and medical expenses, are clearly tax expenditures.16 On the other hand, a number of commentators have concluded that some personal deductions are consistent with a normal tax system.17 That conflict of 13. The commentary in the budget promulgated by the Staff of the Joint Committee states that any depreciation provision that allows for a deduction in excess of what would be permitted under straight-line recovery using the recovery periods set forth in the alternative depreciation system established in I.R.C. § 168(g) will be treated as a tax expenditure. STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, supra note 4, at 6. The commentary indicates that economic depreciation is deemed to be the model. Economic depreciation is explained infra Part III.A. 14. See, e.g., MARVIN A. CHIRELSTEIN & LAWRENCE A. ZELENAK, FEDERAL INCOME TAXATION 206 (12th ed. 2012). 15. Id. 16. Id.; see also Gregg D. Polsky, Rationally Cutting Tax Expenditures, 50 U. LOUISVILLE L. REV. 643 (2012) (arguing that charitable deductions, certain retirement accounts, child tax credits, and the home mortgage interest deduction are all types of tax expenditures). 17. See, e.g., William D. Andrews, Personal Deductions in an Ideal Income Tax, 86 HARV.
146
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:143
views illustrates that even if the premise of the expenditure concept were correct, the classification of many such tax items as expenditures is controversial. To quarrel with the inclusion of some of the items in the budgets may not be sufficient to justify abandoning the expenditure concept. While such commentary casts doubt on the reliability of parts of the budgets, it leaves open the question of whether the concept itself is viable. The more items that are questioned, the greater the skepticism over the reliability of the budgets; but the flaw in the concept is more fundamental than the difficulty encountered in identifying those items that are expenditures. It is the thesis of this Essay that the controversial aspect of some of the items listed in the budgets is a symptom of the fact that the underlying premise of the expenditure concept is unsound. The failure of the expenditure concept is not merely that many of the inclusions in the budget are questionable. Rather, its failure lies in the fact that the entire concept is based on an erroneous view of the income tax system. It is not sufficient to correct individual items of the budget; the entire tax expenditure concept should be discarded. I discuss below the view of the tax system on which the expenditure concept is based and describe a different view of the tax system that more accurately comports with how tax law actually operates and should operate. The tax expenditure concept rests on the view that an ideal or normal tax system exists. Tax provisions are then compared to that ideal or normal system to see if they conform or not. The ideal system is usually described as one that assesses taxes on some modified version of the Haig-Simons definition of income—i.e., that income is equal to the sum of a person’s accumulation of wealth and the market value of that person’s personal consumption during a specified period.18 Whatever may be said about that definition as an ideal, it does not take into account the administrative practicalities of overseeing an income tax system for millions of people engaged in a great variety of economic activities. The various tax expenditure budgets, however, do exclude provisions that serve administrative functions.19
L. REV. 309 (1972); Jeffrey H. Kahn, Personal Deductions – A Tax “Ideal” or Just Another “Deal”?, 2002 L. REV. M.S.U.-D.C.L. 1; Joel S. Newman, Commentary, Of Taxes and Other Casualties, 34 HASTINGS L.J. 941 (1983); William J. Turnier, Personal Deductions and Tax Reform: The High Road and the Low Road, 31 VILL. L. REV. 1703 (1986). 18. HENRY C. SIMONS, PERSONAL INCOME TAXATION: THE DEFINITION OF INCOME AS A PROBLEM OF FISCAL POLICY 50 (1938). Treasury’s tax budget expressly adopts the Haig-Simons definition as its model. OFFICE OF MGMT. & BUDGET, supra note 3, at 242. 19. The Staff of the Joint Committee’s budget expressely states that it excludes provisions that serve administrative feasability. STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, supra note 4, at 5. Treasury’s budget excludes some items because of their administrative function. For example, it excludes unrealized income from its budget. OFFICE OF MGMT. & BUDGET, supra note 3, at 242.
2013]
A PROPOSED REPLACEMENT
147
The two governmental budgets apply different standards for determining the baseline against which tax items are measured.20 The drafters of one budget create what they consider to be an ideal system for their baseline, and the drafters of the other budget determine what principles they consider to be normal in the current tax system and then characterize some of the current tax provisions as out of place with those principles and, therefore, as tax expenditures.21 However, both budgets recognize that some basic tax principles are appropriate and do not create an expenditure. For example, the doctrine of realization is treated as a normal and appropriate part of a tax system, and so adherence to that doctrine does not create a tax expenditure for either budget.22 For accounting purposes, the Joint Committee’s budget treats the accrual method as normal except where it is not feasible to use it.23 The budgets acknowledge that administrative convenience is a proper goal of a tax system, and that is why they generally accept the realization doctrine.24 In recognition of the importance of administrative convenience to the operation of a tax system, the budgets accept a number of other tax principles, including the measuring of gain without regard to the effect of inflation.25 The Joint Committee’s budget does not treat the failure to tax the imputed income from one’s own services or from home ownership as a tax expenditure because the Committee considers them to be excluded from income out of administrative necessity.26 The tax expenditure system is based on a binary view of tax provisions. They either conform to normal principles or they do not. There are no degrees of compliance; every tax provision is either black or white. That is an inaccurate picture of how a tax system is actually structured and how it should be structured. The proponents of the tax expenditure concept are correct in asserting that there is a core of provisions that clearly are part of the structure of an income tax system. The deduction of the expenses of producing income is a necessary part of a tax system if one seeks to tax net in-
20. STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, supra note 4, at 1, 20-22. 21. Id. 22. Id. at 5; OFFICE OF MGMT. & BUDGET, supra note 3, at 241-42. In a recent article, Professor Calvin Johnson proposes a different baseline for tax expenditures that would include the failure to tax unrealized appreciation as a tax expenditure. See Calvin H. Johnson, Measure Tax Expenditures by Internal Rate of Return, 137 TAX NOTES 273 (2013). If the tax expenditure concept were to adopt all of Professor Johnson’s recommendations, the budget would have very little significance because relatively few tax provisions would be omitted. 23. STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, supra note 4, at 7. 24. See supra note 19 and accompanying text. 25. STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, supra note 4, at 7; OFFICE OF MGMT. & BUDGET, supra note 3, at 257. 26. Id. at 5. However, Treasury’s budget does classify some imputed income as a tax expenditure. Id. at 5 n.11.
148
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:143
come as contrasted to gross receipts.27 The number of provisions that fit within that core may be fewer than some imagine, but there is no doubt that there is a core of such provisions. However, it is an error to treat tax provisions as either within that core or outside of it. In reality, most provisions lie on a continuum of varying distances from that core. For example, the expenses of daycare for an infant may be necessary for the parent to work and earn income, but the personal elements of having a child cause that expense to lie further from the core than the expenses of paying an employee to sell the taxpayer’s products. Medical expenses may be an appropriate deduction,28 but they are further from the core than are ordinary business expenses. One of the flaws of the tax expenditure concept is that it ignores the proximity of a provision to the core. Tax law does not operate in a vacuum. Tax laws affect behavior and can have societal and economic consequences that may be desirable or may be undesirable. For example, the failure to tax imputed income may influence one spouse to stay home to care for a child rather than to earn taxable wages and pay someone else to care for the child. The tax law will have an influence on the parent’s decision. The likelihood of the tax system skewing that decision is enhanced by the fact that the secondary spouse’s wages may be taxed at a higher rate because of the income earned by the other spouse. If no deduction is allowed for child care, the tax law will create an incentive for one spouse to not be employed. The decision for one spouse to stay home and care for the child may be regarded as desirable or undesirable depending upon one’s views on both societal and economic issues. If it were concluded that that decision should be made by the parents, insulated from any outside influence by the government, the tax law’s influence could be neutralized by providing a tax deduction for the expense of child care. The parent’s decision could then be made independently of tax considerations. Instead of providing a deduction, current tax law gives a tax credit for such expenses.29 That works less efficiently than would a deduction, but it serves the same function. The child care example is one where a tax provision could be adopted to prevent another tax position (the failure to tax imputed income) from influencing behavior when it is determined that such influence is undesirable. It seems to me that a provision designed to negate a negative influence of the tax law should not be regarded as a tax expenditure
27. There are good reasons not to base a tax system on gross receipts. Such a tax would impose greater taxes on businesses with high costs than on those with low costs. That would violate the doctrine of horizontal and vertical equity. 28. To the contrary, as previously noted, there are those who conclude that medical expenses should not be deductible. The issue is controversial. See supra note 16 and accompanying text. 29. I.R.C. § 21(a)(1), (b)(2)(a).
2013]
A PROPOSED REPLACEMENT
149
even if the provision is deemed to differ from an ideal tax. Provisions of that nature should be classified differently. In contrast to neutralizing tax influences, a tax provision could be adopted in order to induce or deter certain behavior. Some provisions clearly were designed to further a non-tax objective. For example, providing tax benefits for the purchase of anti-pollution devices has programmatic goals. The tax expenditure proponents would claim that a tax provision that is designed to induce behavior is a subsidy and should be characterized as an expenditure.30 That view is too simplistic. As noted above, relatively few tax provisions fit within the core of measuring and taxing net income. Instead, most lie on a continuum in which some are close to that core and some are far from it. Legislators take into account the effect that a proposed tax provision will have on behavior and consider whether that behavior will have societal or economic consequences that are desirable or undesirable. It would be foolish to ignore the influence of taxation on the economy and on societal decisions and simply to allow good and bad consequences to occur in any way they happen to arise. That is not what occurs. The considerations that go into the adoption of tax provisions are multifaceted. The proximity of the provision to the core of a tax system is one factor, but only one factor. The further a provision is from the core, the greater the policy considerations must be to justify its retention. The closer the provision is to the core, the less relative weight that is accorded to policy considerations. However, policy considerations are never entirely absent from the equation. Even a core provision may be removed from the tax law because of the prominence of adverse policy considerations. For example, a deduction for an expense that directly produces income is a core provision. But, there are circumstances where no deduction is allowed for such expenses because they contravene nontax policies. One such exception is for illegal expenses, which are denied deductibility by I.R.C. § 162(c). While, for several reasons, I think that § 162(c) is a bad provision, its legislative purpose obviously rests on nontax considerations. A fine that arises out of an activity conducted in operating a business is nondeductible because of I.R.C. § 162(f). Another example is unreimbursed employee business expenses, which are treated as miscellaneous itemized deductions and so are subjected to limitations on their deductibility31 or even disallowed entirely if the AMT applies.32 There is no aspect of accurate income measurement that would 30. The thesis of the tax expenditure concept is that tax provisions that are designed to implement a program, as contrasted to a measurement of net income, are equivalent to a direct expenditure of governent funds and should be accorded the same treatment. See STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, supra note 4, at 2; STANLEY S. SURREY & PAUL R. MCDANIEL, TAX EXPENDITURES 1 (1985). 31. Id. §§ 67-68. 32. Id. § 56(b)(1)(A)(i) (disallowing a deduction for miscellaneous itemized deductions in
150
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:143
justify that treatment of business expenses, the full deductibility of which is clearly within the core of proper tax provisions. This picture of taxation explains one of the reasons why tax provisions need to be altered from time to time. The consequences of a provision can change as societal and economic conditions change. The values that society holds can change so that consequences that once were thought desirable are now viewed as undesirable, or vice versa. There is another fundamental flaw in the tax expenditure concept. Not only does it posit that there is a pure income tax system, it is based on the assumption that the current tax law is designed generally to conform to that system so that variances from it can be seen as departures that often represent disguised expenditures.33 To the contrary, the current system is not designed to be purely a taxation of net income nor did its drafters aspire to that exclusive goal. The current system is far more pragmatic. It is designed to be a combination of taxation of income and consumption.34 In their excellent casebook, Professors Bankman, Shaviro, and Stark state, “it is often said that our system is as much a consumption tax as an income tax, or more precisely some sort of impure hybrid of the two.”35 More broadly, the tax system can be seen as a hybrid of income tax and consumption tax systems infused with a pragmatism that takes into account various policies and values. The pragmatic approach that Congress has adopted in enacting the tax law is illustrated in Subchapter K, which contains the principal provisions dealing with the taxation of partnerships and partners.36 There are two very different views of the nature of a partnership. It can be viewed as a separate entity distinct from its partners. Alternatively, it can be regarded as a mere convenient representative of the aggregate of interests of the partners. The exclusive adoption of either view would result in a quite different tax system from the one that would be applied if the other view were taken. Congress chose not to adopt either view determining the alternative minimum taxable income of an individual); see also id. § 67(b) (outlining what constitutes a “miscellaneous itemized deduction”). 33. The only plausible justification for characterizing some tax provisions as falling outside of pure income measurement is that the legislative purpose for having an income tax system is to measure and tax income, such that any actual tax provisions that fail to measure income accurately and that further a non-tax policy objective constitute a utilization of the tax system to finance a program that the legislature desires. 34. For example, the tax law does not apply to some significant accessions to wealth such as imputed income and unrealized appreciation of the value of assets, and the tax law’s view of consumption appears to be different from the one contemplated in the Haig-Simons definition. For example, commentators have questioned whether the deduction for medical expenses and charitable contributions conflict with Haig-Simons because they should be treated as consumption expenses. See supra note 16 and accompanying text. 35. JOSEPH BANKMAN, DANIEL N. SHAVIRO & KIRK J. STARK, FEDERAL INCOME TAXATION 14 (16th ed. 2012). 36. LAURA E. CUNNINGHAM & NOEL B. CUNNINGHAM, THE LOGIC OF SUBCHAPTER K 1 (4th ed. 2010).
2013]
A PROPOSED REPLACEMENT
151
exclusively. Instead, Congress adopted a hybrid view that treats a partnership as a separate entity for some purposes and as an aggregate of interests for others.37 Rather than adhering to a fixed model, Congress chose a more flexible and nuanced approach. When the tax law operated better by treating the partnership as an entity, Congress did so; and when the tax law operated better by treating the partnership as an aggregate of the partners’ interests, it did so. The pragmatism of the tax system is reflected throughout the Code. Another example is the treatment of spouses. For some purposes, they are treated as two separate individuals.38 For other purposes, they are treated as a single unit.39 Repeatedly, Congress shows that it is not seeking to adopt some idealized system, but rather seeks to have a system that carries out its policies and goals. The discussion in Part III.B of this Essay notes that Congress has shown that same pragmatism in its treatment of depreciation. In some circumstances, Congress has chosen to ignore unrealized appreciation in measuring the amount of an asset’s depreciation.40 In other circumstances, it has disallowed any depreciation deductions because it has taken unrealized appreciation into account.41 In other words, in some circumstances, Congress has adhered to the realization doctrine in determining depreciation, and in other circumstances it has rejected the realization doctrine. Given the hybrid and pragmatic nature of the country’s income tax system, it is folly to speak of provisions departing from some fixed, ideal view of income. Such so-called departures can be as much a proper part of the system as those that are seen as core provisions. There are numerous factors to be considered in determining whether any tax provision should be retained, but its relationship to some ideal tax system is not one of them. Once it is accepted that the tax law does not seek to adhere to a single view of taxation, it seems clear that any purported departures from an ideal system cannot be characterized as impure. A provision that does not conform to an imagined ideal tax system could be a provision that complements other provisions that do not conform. Once a variance
37. See, e.g., KAREN C. BURKE, FEDERAL INCOME TAXATION OF PARTNERS AND PARTNERSHIPS 1-2 (4th ed. 2013). 38. For example, spouses are not required to file a joint income tax return under I.R.C. § 6013, but they can each file separately, reporting his or her own income and deductions. 39. See, e.g., I.R.C. § 318(a)(1)(A)(i) (treating a taxpayer as owning stock owned by the taxpayer’s spouse); id. § 469(h)(5) (treating the participation of a taxpayer’s spouse as participation of the taxpayer). 40. As noted in Part III.B infra, the allowance of accelerated depreciation effectively ignores the unrealized appreciation in the remaining life of the asset. 41. No depreciation is allowable for a non-wasting asset (such as land) because the appreciation of the value of the remaining life of the asset offsets the value that was exhausted in the year in which the asset was used.
152
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:143
from a system has been adopted, there can be good reasons not to follow that system when adopting other provisions. The proponents of the tax expenditure concept do not contend that the items listed in the budgets necessarily should be repealed or changed. They contend that since the items do not conform to established tax principles, each should be repealed unless a convincing case can be made for its retention on the basis of serving some valuable societal or economic purpose whose benefit justifies the amount of revenue that is lost because of that provision.42 In other words, because of their equivalence to a direct expenditure, they should meet the same process of review that is applied to determine whether to continue making a direct expenditure.43 By singling out some tax provisions because they serve non-tax policy functions, the concept obscures the fact that non-tax policy considerations have a role in the question of the adoption or retention of virtually all tax provisions.44 The inclusion of some items on the list suggests that the items that are not on the list are free of policy considerations. Also, by placing all so-called tax expenditures in a single category of nonneutral, the concept ignores the different status of provisions that lie on different points of the continuum. Since the adoption or retention of virtually all tax provisions is influenced by non-tax considerations, the selection of some such provisions to be designated as having a programmatic function is misleading because it suggests those provisions are significantly different from the many other provisions that also serve a programmatic function. The expenditure concept serves more of a political purpose than it does provide any useful information. By classifying some provisions as tax expenditures, it suggests that they do not belong in the tax system and makes them prominent targets for repeal whenever Congress needs to increase revenue.45 This labeling could alter the debate on listed items by marking them with a scarlet letter. Moreover, the question of where the items belong on the continuum, which should be a factor, might be 42. SURREY & MCDANIEL, supra note 30, at 26-27. 43. As previously noted, some authors have questioned the extent to which direct expenditures are scrutinized. See, e.g., Zelinsky, supra note 1, at 1320. 44. As previously noted, even core provisions, such as business expenses, are subject to non-tax considerations. See supra notes 27-32 and accompanying text. In that case, as contrasted to inducing the adoption of a provision, the presence of undesirable non-tax consequences can lead to eliminating or limiting the item. 45. Despite the promulgation of tax expenditure budgets, the number of items that are classified as expenditures has continued to grow. Some have concluded, therefore, that the tax expenditure budgets have been ineffective. Indeed, Professor Zelinsky contends that the budgets have been counterproductive and have actually stimulated the increase in tax expenditures. Zelinsky, supra note 1, at 1317. While that seems an unlikely consequence and other explanations are available, I make a different point in this Essay. My thesis is that the expenditure concept is based on a false premise and should be discarded regardless of its efficacy.
2013]
A PROPOSED REPLACEMENT
153
overlooked. The following discussion of accelerated depreciation provides an example of a designated expenditure provision that can be seen to be within the core itself. The characterization of accelerated depreciation as an expenditure reflects the rigidity of the expenditure concept and its failure to reflect the flexibility of the tax system, which accommodates a variety of approaches for the determination of income. III. DEPRECIATION DEDUCTIONS The cost of acquiring an asset that will be used in a trade or business or for the production of income is deductible.46 However, if the asset is to be used by the taxpayer for more than one year, the entire cost generally cannot be deducted currently, but instead it must be capitalized.47 The capitalized cost can be allocated among the years of the asset’s useful life, and a portion of the cost can be deducted in each year.48 Certain types of amortization of cost are referred to as depreciation.49 If an aliquot amount is allocated equally to each year of the recovery period, the depreciation is referred to as “straight-line” depreciation.50 Some methods of depreciation allocate a greater amount of cost to the earlier years of the recovery period than to the later years. Those types are called “accelerated depreciation.” The most commonly used accelerated depreciation method authorized by the Code is the “declining balance method.”51 While there is little dispute as to the appropriateness of allowing depreciation deductions, there are issues as to the methods of depreciation that should be available and as to the choice of a recovery period. In general, the tax expenditure budgets treat accelerated methods as expenditures to the extent that the amount of deduction in a year exceeds what would be allowed under either straight-line or economic depreciation.52 The source of the view that accelerated depreciation is excessive is an approach to depreciation called “economic depreciation” or “sinking-fund depreciation.”
46. I.R.C. §§ 162(a), 212(1). 47. Id. § 263; see Indopco v. Commissioner, 503 U.S. 79 (1992). The one-year standard is a rule of thumb that has been adopted by the Service. See Rev. Rul. 73-357, 1973-2 C.B. 40; Rev. Rul. 69-560, 1969-2 C.B. 25. 48. I.R.C. §§ 167-168. 49. Id. 50. Treas. Reg. § 1.167(b)-1(a). 51. I.R.C. § 168(b). 52. STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, supra note 4, at 6; OFFICE OF MGMT. & BUDGET, supra note 3, at 258 (utilizing economic depreciation, a decelerated method, as the normal tax baseline).
154
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:143
A. Economic Depreciation Economic depreciation is based on the premise that the correct amount of depreciation allowable for a year is the amount by which the asset declined in value by the end of the year.53 It is not based on the actual decline in the asset’s value, which would require appraisals to be made. Rather, it is based on the decline that occurs because of the passage of time without regard to changes that may have taken place in market conditions. Apart from the administrative difficulty in measuring market changes, tax law has firmly established that changes in market value do not affect the amount of depreciation that is allowable.54 Economic depreciation concludes (quite reasonably) that the value of an asset is the sum of the present values of the income stream that it is assumed the asset will produce. The calculation of economic depreciation is illustrated in an example in the treatise on federal income taxation that is co-authored by Professors Chirelstein and Zelenak.55 I will use their example since it provides such a clear explanation of that approach to depreciation. In that illustration, a machine is purchased for $4000 to be used in a business. The machine is expected to last for 5 years and to produce (after maintenance expenses) income of $1200 each year. While it is unrealistic to assume an equal amount of income production each year, that assumption makes the calculations easier. I will also assume, unrealistically, that the entire $1200 is received at the end of each year, rather than being earned throughout the year. To calculate the value of each year’s income stream to a purchaser, the market will discount the $1200 for that year by a figure that represents the rate of income that the market deems appropriate for the risk involved in purchasing the machine. The discount rate that is used to establish the price of an asset is set by the market. Since the purchaser paid $4000 for a machine that will produce $6000 over a 5-year period, the discount rate was about 15%. The value of the machine will decrease by the end of each year since the remaining life of the machine will be one year less. But, simultaneously, the value of the remaining years of use will increase because they are one year nearer to occurring. The latter increase in value will offset some of the reduction in value caused by the expiration of one year’s life. Chirelstein and Zelenak illustrate this effect by setting forth the following schedule:56
53. 54. 55. 56.
CHIRELSTEIN & ZELENAK, supra note 14, at 187. Fribourg Navigation Co. v. Commissioner, 383 U.S. 272, 277 (1966). CHIRELSTEIN & ZELENAK, supra note 14, at 187-88. Id. at 188.
2013]
Present Value of Investment Start Year 1 End Year 1 End Year 2 End Year 3 End Year 4 End Year 5
155
A PROPOSED REPLACEMENT
$4000 $3427 $2740 $1950 $1045 $0
Present Value of Remaining Payments 1 $1045
2 $905 $1045
3 $790 $905 $1045
4 $687 $790 $905 $1045
5 $573 $687 $790 $905 $1045 Total
Annual Loss in Present Value $573 $687 $790 $905 $1045 $4000
As you can see from that schedule, the decline in value of the machine at the end of Year 1 was $573. In the next year, the machine declined in value by $687. The decline in value was larger in each subsequent year until the fifth year when the decline was $1045. If depreciation deductions were to follow that schedule, there would be only $573 of depreciation in the first year and increasing amounts each year until the last year would have $1045 of depreciation. Instead of straight line or accelerated depreciation, there would be decelerated depreciation. In a nutshell, that is economic or sinking-fund depreciation. Because economic or sinking-fund depreciation is based on several unrealistic assumptions, no one advocates the adoption of that system. Indeed, Chirelstein and Zelenak themselves acknowledge that the assumptions are unrealistic for the depreciation of tangible assets, and they note that if more realistic assumptions were made, “the proper depreciation method would be less decelerated than sinking fund, or possibly even straight-line or accelerated.”57 While the tax expenditure budget proposed by the Joint Committee on Taxation considers economic depreciation to be the model, they treat straight-line depreciation as the normal baseline for their budget.58 B. Proper Method of Depreciation Let us ignore the unrealistic assumptions that go into economic depreciation and focus on whether it is the only proper view of depreciation when accepting those assumptions. Referring to the schedule above for the machine that was purchased for $4000, we can see that of the $4000 that the purchaser paid for the machine, $1045 of it was attributable to the income he expected to earn in the first year of using the machine. If he paid $1045 for the first 57. Id. at 189. 58. See STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, supra note 4, at 6.
156
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:143
year’s use of the machine, why doesn’t economic depreciation allow him to deduct that amount for the use of the machine in that year? Why does economic depreciation allow him to deduct only $573? The answer is that while he used up the first year of the machine’s life for which he paid $1045, the value of the remaining four years of the machine’s life increased due to the fact that they are all one year closer in time to being earned. So, we can see that economic depreciation is based on offsetting the exhaustion of the $1045 paid for the first year’s use of the machine by the increase in value of the remaining life of the machine due to the passage of time. The increase in the value of the remaining life of the machine is unrealized appreciation. The doctrine of realization is a basic element of the federal income tax system, and the tax expenditure budgets do not treat the application of that doctrine as creating an expenditure.59 If the increase in value of the remaining life were not taken into account in determining depreciation because of the realization doctrine, the machine would be depreciated on an accelerated method. The first year’s depreciation would be $1040, the second year’s would be $905, and so on, until the fifth year’s depreciation would be $573. Does that accelerated method violate normal principles of federal income taxation? It is the thesis of this Essay that it does not. It rests on an application of the realization doctrine that is widely used in the federal income tax system and clearly is part of the normal tax system. As previously noted, it is not my position that accelerated depreciation is the only permissible method under normal taxation rules. While the realization doctrine is generally applied in the tax system, there are a few circumstances when Congress has chosen not to apply it.60 If Congress chose not to take the unrealized appreciation of the remaining life of an asset into account when determining depreciation deductions, that would not violate any neutral principles of taxation. Similarly, if Congress chose to calculate depreciation by offsetting the appreciation of the remaining life of an asset against the amount paid for one year’s use, even though that would not comport with the realization doctrine, that treatment also would be consistent with normal tax principles. While the realization doctrine is a normal part of tax law, there is no requirement that it be used. Ignoring the realization doctrine is just as “normal” as following it. There is no “correct” method; either one is permissible. Indeed, Congress has rejected the realization doctrine for purposes of determining depreciation in certain circumstances. Generally, no depreciation deduction is allowable for assets that are not subject to wear and
59. See supra note 22 and accompanying text. 60. See, e.g., I.R.C. §§ 336, 1272 (treating “debt instruments having original issue discount[s]” and property acquired during corporate liquidation as a gain/loss of income).
2013]
A PROPOSED REPLACEMENT
157
tear.61 Consequently, no depreciation deduction is allowable for land and for stocks. While such assets do not deteriorate due to wear and tear, the present value of each year’s income declines the further the years are from the present. At some point in time, the present value of the remaining years of income will be de minimis. Why then is no depreciation allowable for such assets? The apparent answer is that in those cases, Congress has chosen to reject the realization doctrine and to take into account the appreciation in value of the remaining life of those assets. Once again, Congress has displayed its pragmatism by refusing to be restricted to a single approach.62 C. Illustration of a Flaw in the Tax Expenditure Concept The tax expenditure budgets’ treatment of accelerated depreciation illustrates the basic flaw in that concept. The budgets rest on the notion that there is a single correct or perfect system of federal income taxation that has no relationship to policy considerations. The error in that view is much more than the great difficulty that exists in determining just what constitutes a perfect system. The error is to assume that such a system exists and that it would be desirable to adopt it. The budget’s rigid approach to depreciation illustrates how wrong it is to hold that there is a single correct approach to measuring income. The tax law is and should be far more flexible and pragmatic than that. It should accommodate the needs of the time. Policy considerations are a normal part of the tax system and should not be classified as aberrations. If accelerated depreciation is more desirable at one point in time, it should be employed. If it is not desirable at another point in time, it should be abandoned. There is no reason to skew that decision by categorizing one of the choices as being inconsistent with normal tax principles. Accelerated depreciation is consistent with normal tax principles, and the decision whether to retain or repeal it should not be influenced by a false characterization that it is not. 61. Treas. Reg. § 1.167(a)-2. 62. In a recent article, Professor Calvin Johnson contends that accelerated depreciation does not comport with a new baseline that he urges should be adopted in determining tax expenditures in lieu of the baselines that are used currently. See Johnson, supra note 22, at 273-74. In essence, his contention is that a policy analysis of depreciation would reject accelerated depreciation. As noted above, I do not contend that accelerated depreciation should be adopted; I merely contend that its adoption does not contravene normal current tax principles. Professor Johnson’s position that economic policy supports eliminating accelerated depreciation rests on a single consideration (on the merits of which I express no opinion in this Essay) and ignores some of the other factors that might properly be taken into account. For example, the likely effect of inflation on measuring depreciation might be considered. The fact that the value of many personal property items does decline more in the earlier years of the asset’s use might be weighed. In any event, it is not my intention to take a side on the question of whether accelerated depreciation is desirable as a matter of policy. I leave that question for others to resolve, but I suspect that answers will differ at different points in time depending upon the needs of that period.
158
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:143
IV. CONCLUSION I maintain that the tax expenditure concept is grounded on a basic error in its view of the income tax system. There is no “perfect” or “ideal” tax system. The tax system is not divorced from every political, societal, and economic condition that exists, nor is it independent of the values that society holds at given points in time. The tax expenditure concept views the ideal tax system as one that is insulated from non-tax factors rather than being a part of and responsive to them. It is wrong to treat tax as isolated from everything else. The adoption of that view can distort the proper consideration of the passage or repeal of tax provisions. The advocates of the tax expenditure concept recognize that non-tax policies can properly induce Congress to adopt specific tax provisions. Their contention is that such provisions should be scrutinized as they would if they were direct expenditures. However, by characterizing some provisions as inconsistent with neutral tax principles, they attempt to make it more difficult to defend the listed items. More importantly, by adopting a binary approach in characterizing provisions as either within normal tax principles or outside of them, the concept fails to take into account the greater variety that exists in a properly structured tax system. Provisions that are outside of the core of proper tax provisions are not all distanced from that core to the same extent. Some provisions lie closer to the core than others, and some are far removed from it. The expenditure concept obscures that fact and describes the tax world as containing only two categories—those within the system and those outside of it. It has been pointed out that while the tax expenditure concept has been widely accepted, it has been notoriously ineffective in changing the tax law.63 While there has been some speculation as to why that is so, the most obvious reason seems to have been ignored. The likely reason that the concept has not had a greater impact on tax legislation is that even though people purport to approve of the concept, they intuitively realize that it is flawed and should not have any influence. Some have suggested that even if the tax expenditure concept is flawed, it would be useful to have a list of tax items that might be scrutinized by Congress when it seems appropriate to do so. I have no quarrel with the promulgation of such a list. My quarrel is with the characterization of certain tax items as “impure” because they do not comport with a supposed ideal tax system. It is the stigmatization of certain tax items that is the source of the mischief with which I find fault.
63. See, e.g., Zelinsky, supra note 1, at 1317 (explaining how “tax expenditure budgets . . . have not curbed tax expenditures, as the proponents of those budgets promised”).
THE END OF CASH, THE INCOME TAX, AND THE NEXT 100 YEARS JEFFREY H. KAHN * & GREGG D. POLSKY **
I. INTRODUCTION.................................................................................................. II. CASH AND THE INCOME TAX GAP ...................................................................... III. WILL PAYMENT SYSTEMS TECHNOLOGY EASE TRANSITION TO A CONSUMPTION TAX? .......................................................................................... IV. CONCLUSION .....................................................................................................
159 161 166 171
I. INTRODUCTION One theme of this symposium, which celebrates the 100th anniversary of the federal income tax, is “The Next 100 Years.” What will the next hundred years have in store for the federal income tax? We suspect that technological innovations will play a very significant role. Technology has dramatically affected life in the United States over the past century in many areas, perhaps most notably in communications. 1 On the other hand, the income tax is technologically very similar to the way it was in its early years, and technological developments have been at the margins of the income tax and have not affected its core elements. This is not to imply that technology has had no effect on the income tax. Technological improvements have made third-party reporting and withholding more efficient, which has allowed these mechanisms to become more pervasively used.2 Tax compliance software has made it easier for professional tax preparers and taxpayers alike to prepare and file tax returns and information statements. 3 Technology has also made it easier for taxpayers to substantiate their activities; the proverbial shoebox full of receipts is disappearing. All of these changes have undoubtedly facilitated the evolution of the in* Charles W. Ehrhardt Professor & Associate Dean for Academic Affairs, Florida State University College of Law. ** Willie Person Mangum Professor of Law, University of North Carolina School of Law. The authors thank Joshua Eagle, Brant Hellwig, Douglas Kahn, Kathleen Delaney Thomas, Lawrence Zelenak, and the participants at Duke Law School’s tax colloquium and at the Florida State College of Law’s tax symposium for comments, suggestions, and discussions on this topic. They would also like to thank Mary McCormick for her research assistance. 1. Wesley MacNeil Oliver, Western Union, the American Federation of Labor, Google, and the Changing Face of Privacy Advocates, 81 MISS. L.J. 971, 972 (2012). 2. Ruth Mason, Delegating Up: State Conformity with the Federal Tax Base, 62 DUKE L.J. 1267, 1280-81 (2013). 3. See id.; see also Jay A. Soled, Homage to Information Returns, 27 VA. TAX REV. 371, 372-73 (2007).
160
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:159
come tax from its original class tax to the mass tax it is today. These changes have also facilitated the exponential growth of the tax expenditure budget, which is now the primary way in which the federal government engages in non-military discretionary spending.4 And both of these developments—the transition to a mass tax and the growth of tax expenditures—have resulted in the federal income tax becoming the most salient and controversial tax in the United States. 5 But while technology has certainly affected the income tax, it has not affected its core elements. The income tax remains a selfreported, annually calculated tax. And the tax problems resulting from the cash economy—namely, that cash income is rarely reported accurately—continue to plague the income tax. 6 The income tax is thus analogous to the transportation industry; while technology has made car and plane travel more efficient and accessible to the masses, the traveling experience has not changed fundamentally over the past century. However, recent news reports suggest that driverless cars may be available on a widespread basis within the next ten years.7 Driverless cars would fundamentally alter traffic control systems, parking, and even the way that cities are structured.8 Perhaps the same fundamental technology-driven changes are in store for the income tax. While technology might improve the federal income tax, it could have the opposite effect by paving the way towards the elimination of the income tax. One particular type of technology—payment systems—has the potential either to fortify the income tax or to destroy it. Payment systems technology (e.g., electronic payment systems) could eventually shrink the cash economy down to an immaterial size and perhaps even make cash as obsolete as payphones. These developments would fortify the income tax by reducing the large part of the “tax gap” 9 attributable to unreported cash income, which would result in increased fairness and efficiency, greater confidence in the tax system, and improved taxpayer morale. But payment systems technology, instead, could destroy the income tax by easing the transition from the income tax to a consumption tax. 4. See LAWRENCE ZELENAK, LEARNING TO LOVE FORM 1040: TWO CHEERS FOR THE RETURN-BASED MASS INCOME TAX 56-60 (2013) (describing the tax expenditure explosion and its relationship to the income tax becoming a mass tax). 5. See id. 6. Susan Cleary Morse, Stewart Karlinsky & Joseph Bankman, Cash Businesses and Tax Evasion, 20 STAN. L. & POL’Y REV. 37, 39-40 (2009). 7. Nick Bilton, How Driverless Cars Could Reshape Cities, N.Y. TIMES, July 8, 2013, at B5. 8. See id. 9. See infra Part II (defining “cash tax gap”).
2013]
THE NEXT 100 YEARS
161
In Part II, we explain how the end of the use of cash would strengthen the income tax system by eliminating the very large portion of the tax gap that results from the inability of the Internal Revenue Service to ensure that cash transactions are properly reported. In Part III, we describe some of the advantages of a consumption tax over the income tax that have been asserted by many economists and policymakers. 10 We then explain how the end of cash makes the transition to that type of system more realistic. We also briefly address some of the possible transitional and permanent concerns that such a move would entail. In Part IV, we conclude. II. CASH AND THE INCOME TAX GAP A large portion of the income tax gap—the difference between the amount of income tax revenue that is by law supposed to be paid and the amount of income tax revenue actually collected—is attributable to cash income that is not reported. This “cash tax gap,” which has recently been estimated at over $100 billion per year, 11 has many troubling policy implications. First, the lost tax revenue means that tax rates are higher than they otherwise would need to be to raise the same amount of revenue. The higher tax rates result in greater tax-induced distortions, including the adoption of tax planning strategies to reduce the tax burden.12 Second, the unintentional tax preference for cash transactions results in the cash economy being larger than it otherwise would be. Businesses that routinely accept cash (such as those that provide household and other personal services 13) are tax-preferred relative to other businesses, which results in overinvestment in those types of businesses. In other words, the after-tax return from cash businesses is greater because of underreporting.14 10. DANIEL S. GOLDBERG, THE DEATH OF THE INCOME TAX: A PROGRESSIVE CONSUMPTAX AND THE PATH TO FISCAL REFORM 5 (2013) (“[A] consumption tax, that is, a tax based on what individuals consume rather than on what they earn as under an income tax, is viewed by most economists as superior to an income tax.”). 11. See Kathleen DeLaney Thomas, Presumptive Collection: A Prospect Theory Approach to Increasing Small Business Tax Compliance, 67 TAX L. REV. (forthcoming 2013) (manuscript at 5) (on file with authors). 12. JOEL SLEMROD & JON BAKIJA, TAXING OURSELVES 144 (4th ed. 2008) (“On all the margins of choice, taxpayers will undertake behavior that reduces tax liability up to the point that the marginal cost equals the marginal tax saving.”). 13. For tax avoidance reasons (both income and employment taxes), homeowners often pay domestic help in cash. Catherine B. Haskins, Household Employer Payroll Tax Evasion: An Exploration Based on IRS Data and on Interviews with Employers and Domestic Workers 5 (Feb. 1, 2010) (unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, Univ. of Massachusetts – Amherst), available at http://scholarworks.umass.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1171& context=open_access_dissertations. 14. See Thomas, supra note 11, at 5 n.21; see also U.S. GOV’T ACCOUNTABILITY OFFICE, GAO-07-1014, TAX GAP: A STRATEGY FOR REDUCING THE TAX GAP SHOULD INCLUDE OPTIONS FOR ADDRESSING SOLE PROPRIETOR NONCOMPLIANCE (2007), available at http://www.gao.gov/new.items/d071014.pdf. TION
162
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:159
Third, to avoid detection by the IRS, taxpayers who do not report cash income typically do not deposit the cash they receive in bank accounts or make other investments (e.g., in stocks, bonds, or CDs) with that cash. As a result, the cash is suboptimally invested, and cash recipients are unable to borrow funds to grow their businesses.15 Fourth, the cash tax gap hurts taxpayer morale and encourages other types of tax cheating. Open and obvious cheating by failing to declare cash income and offering “cash discounts” can make even taxpayers who are inclined towards honest reporting doubt the integrity of the system. 16 Fifth, the tax preference for cash encourages the use of cash over other mediums of money payment. In fact, the tax preference for cash probably plays a key role in the persistence of cash in the economy. Considering the readily available alternatives to cash (debit card, credit card, or e-payment transactions) and the problems inherent in dealing with cash, it is a wonder that cash transactions remain as common as they are. The problems with cash are legion. 17 Cash is subject to counterfeit, and counterfeiters are becoming increasingly sophisticated. Cash is more easily stolen than electronic money.18 Cash must be secured during transit and where stored. Cash must be physically delivered to where it will be stored, resulting in transportation costs.19 Once a transaction in cash is consummated, it may be impossible to find and collect against the seller if the product or service is not delivered or is defective. 20 Cash transactions do not spontaneously and immediately leave a record of what has transpired, which allows for disputes as to whether payments have been made and makes it more difficult for parties to keep track of what they have purchased or sold.21 Cash is easier for sellers’ or buyers’ agents to misappropriate. Cash transactions require change to be physically provided if exact cash is not paid, which requires sellers to keep change on hand and slows down transactions. Cash generally must be accounted for manually. Electronic cashiers cannot process cash 15. Morse et al., supra note 6, at 49-54; see also Ilan Benshalom, Taxing Cash, 4 COL65, 74 (2012). 16. See Leandra Lederman, Reducing Information Gaps to Reduce the Tax Gap: When Is Information Reporting Warranted?, 78 FORDHAM L. REV. 1733, 1755 (2010). 17. See generally DAVID WOLMAN, THE END OF MONEY (2012) (describing the problems of cash and predicting an eventual cashless society). 18. Id. at 45. 19. JACK WEATHERFORD, THE HISTORY OF MONEY 238 (1997). 20. Other payment systems make recourse against the seller much easier. Credit and debit card companies allow buyers to challenge charges, and e-payment sellers generally leave a footprint that would allow a claim to be made against them. Arnold S. Rosenberg, Better than Cash? Global Proliferation of Payment Cards and Consumer Protection Policy, 44 COLUM. J. TRANSNAT’L L. 520, 524 (2006). 21. Id. at 534. UM. J. TAX L.
2013]
THE NEXT 100 YEARS
163
transactions efficiently, which means that sellers that accept cash usually will hire human cashiers. The list goes on and on. This is not to say that cash does not sometimes have its virtues. Cash is currently very useful for small, ad hoc transactions, such as tipping service providers. 22 But this advantage too will soon wither away, as e-payment technologies through, for example, mobile phone applications, become commonplace.23 Nevertheless, there are certain advantages of cash that will likely persist. Most significantly, cash easily allows for anonymous purchases. 24 In addition, cognitive biases may have a salutary effect on spending behavior when cash is used as the medium of payment. 25 People tend to be more frugal paying in cash rather than in other media; casinos seem to bank (no pun intended) on this principle by requiring gamblers to bet with tokens. Personal finance experts likewise encourage the use of cash to tamp down excessive spending. 26 But even this advantage may be ephemeral as electronic commitment devices (perhaps electric shocks from your cell phone if you spend too much 27) eventually develop. Overall, the benefits of non-cash payment media substantially outweigh the benefit of cash, leaving aside tax consequences. This explains the exponential growth of non-cash payment media and its emerging dominance in the economy. 28 Eventually, it is likely that nearly all remaining cash-transaction outliers will involve tax evaders and crime participants. Given the critical role of cash in tax evasion and criminal activity more generally, it is not surprising that governments have begun to discourage the use of cash, sometimes subtly and other times in heavy-handed ways. Italy and Greece recently banned the use of cash
22. See Benshalom, supra note 15, at 71 (explaining that cash is “especially efficient for small retail purchases”). 23. Cf. DAVID W. SCHROPFER, THE SMARTPHONE WALLET: UNDERSTANDING THE DISRUPTION AHEAD (2010) (predicting the eventual dominance of the smartphone wallet). 24. See Benshalom, supra note 15, at 92 (describing the privacy benefits of using cash). Even the end of cash may not completely eliminate anonymous purchases. See Omri Marian, Are Cryptocurrencies Super Tax Havens?, 112 MICH. L. REV. FIRST IMPRESSION 38, 39 (2013). 25. See Benshalom, supra note 15, at 71 (noting that cash “allows some people to better manage their personal budgets”). 26. See WOLMAN, supra note 17, at 88. 27. In all seriousness, electronic devices allow users to check their balances anywhere at any time and should also make it easier to create (and perhaps stick to) a budget. 28. Some might point to the earning of points and miles through credit/debit card use as a reason for the emerging dominance of non-cash media. Certainly this may have been a factor in discouraging the use of cash (because points and miles operate as an effective tax on cash users), but the convenience and other benefits of non-cash media would outweigh the benefits of cash, leaving aside points and miles, except in a very small subset of purchasing activity.
164
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:159
in transactions exceeding a threshold amount. 29 Other countries have taken large currencies out of production, making large cash transfers more onerous. 30 Still others have subsidized the cost of electronic payment terminals for small retailers or provided tax rebates when a taxpayer’s electronic payments reach threshold amounts. 31 In addition to these legal changes, some governments have engaged in campaigns criticizing the use of cash in an attempt to change social norms. For example, Britain’s Treasury Minister recently remarked that paying tradesmen such as plumbers in cash is “morally wrong” because it facilitates tax evasion.32 Other governments have run advertising campaigns that, while not specifically targeting cash transactions, emphasize the social cost of tax evasion. 33 Academic commentators have argued that governments should discourage cash transactions. 34 For example, Ilan Benshalom would impose a Pigovian tax on cash withdrawals from financial institutions to cause cash users to internalize the societal costs of tax evasion and criminal activity facilitated by cash transactions. 35 As these legal and social attacks on cash proceed, technology continues to make e-payments easier, more secure, and more ubiquitous. For example, Starbucks recently started selling the Square card reader, which easily converts any cell phone into a credit or debit card reader. 36 Square and other companies have also created technology allowing for “mobile payment” through cell phones without the
29. Joe Weisenthal, Italy is Taking a Draconian New Measure to Avoid Tax Evasion, BUSINESS INSIDER (Dec. 4, 2011, 4:48 PM), http://www.businessinsider.com/italy-banningcash-transactions-above-1000-euros-2011-12; Greek FinMin Unveils Tax Reform, Wage Policy, REUTERS (Feb. 9, 2010, 11:37 AM), http://www.reuters.com/article/2010/02/09/ greece-finmin-highlights-idUSLDE61824V20100209. 30. REBECCA HELLERSTEIN & WILLIAM RYAN, FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF NEW YORK, STAFF REPORT NO. 400, CASH DOLLARS ABROAD 2 (rev. ed. 2011), available at http://www.newyorkfed.org/research/staff_reports/sr400.pdf. 31. See FRIEDRICH SCHNEIDER, A.T. KEARNEY, THE SHADOW ECONOMY IN EUROPE, 2011: USING ELECTRONIC PAYMENT SYSTEMS TO COMBAT THE SHADOW ECONOMY 7-8 (describing subsidies paid by Mexico, Columbia, Argentina, and South Korea for retailers who accept electronic payments). 32. Nicholas Watt, Paying a Plumber Cash in Hand is Morally Wrong, Says Tory Minister, THE GUARDIAN (July 23, 2012), http://www.theguardian.com/politics/2012/jul/23/ taxandspending-hmrc. 33. Elisabetta Povoledo, Italy Tries to Get Tax Cheats to Pay Up, N.Y. TIMES (Aug. 8, 2011), http://www.nytimes.com/2011/08/09/business/global/italy-tries-to-get-tax-cheats-topay-up.html. 34. See, e.g., Jay A. Soled, To Close the Tax Gap, Eliminate Cash, 115 TAX NOTES 379 (2007). 35. See generally Benshalom, supra note 15. 36. Brian X. Chen, Now on Sale at Starbucks: Square’s Credit Card Reader, N.Y. TIMES BITS BLOG (Jan. 3, 2013, 2:20 PM), http://bits.blogs.nytimes.com/2013/01/ 03/starbucks-square-mobile-credit-card-reader/.
2013]
THE NEXT 100 YEARS
165
use of a credit or debit card.37 Biometric payment, through, for example, a touch of the finger, is also reportedly on the horizon.38 The demise of cash should have positive ramifications for the income tax. E-payments automatically leave an electronic trail for every transaction, which decreases the risk of non-reporting of income. More importantly, e-payments must be made through a third-party intermediary who could become subject to third-party reporting obligations. The recently enacted section 6050W of the Internal Revenue Code expanded third-party reporting obligations to credit/debit card issuers and to “third party settlement organizations,” such as PayPal, who must now generally issue Forms 1099-K to their payees who both receive more than $20,000 in payments in a calendar year and engage in more than 200 transactions during the year. 39 Section 6050W could easily be expanded to cover the information-reporting regime; the $20,000/200 transaction floor could be lowered to cover nearly all e-payment transactions. Closing the cash tax gap would raise revenues, which could allow for reduced rates, which would in turn reduce tax-induced behavioral distortions. Closing the gap would also improve taxpayer morale and confidence in the tax system by buttressing the view that everyone is paying their fair share. Traditional cash businesses, which tend to be smaller, more informal, and have a business-to-consumer orientation, would no longer be tax-advantaged relative to other businesses, resulting in more efficient investment decisions overall.40 Second-order problems associated with the storing of cash proceeds, such as the suboptimal investment and borrowing activities by tax evaders, would be alleviated. 41 A major drawback of this electronic utopia is that financial companies will have information concerning our private as well as our commercial activities, but society may have no choice other than to accept that consequence. However, especially in light of recent NSA scandals, the public may object to the government obtaining that information. 42 Of course, the government already obtains a great deal of information (through third-party reporting), but individuals might
37. Jenna Wortham, I’m Still Waiting for My Phone to Become My Wallet, N.Y. TIMES (July 27, 2013), www.nytimes.com/2013/07/28/technology/im-still-waiting-for-my-phone-tobecome-my-wallet.html. 38. Ellen McCarthy, Cash, Charge or Fingerprint?, WASH. POST (June 9, 2005), http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2005/06/08/AR2005060802335.html. 39. See I.R.C. § 6050W. 40. Joel Slemrod, Small Business and the Tax System, in THE CRISIS IN TAX ADMINISTRATION 69, 96 (Henry J. Aaron & Joel Slemrod, eds., 2004). 41. See Benshalom, supra note 15, at 73-74. 42. See Goldberg, supra note 10, at 118.
166
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:159
be unwilling to have the government know every single transaction in which they engage. III. WILL PAYMENT SYSTEMS TECHNOLOGY EASE TRANSITION TO A CONSUMPTION TAX? The previous part explained that technological innovations in payment systems should fortify the income tax by dramatically reducing the income tax gap as well as cash-induced distortions. This part considers whether those same technological innovations might eventually doom the income tax as we know it by paving the way towards a retail-sales-based consumption tax. It should be noted that it is possible to adopt a consumption tax system and still retain an income tax for high income taxpayers. A number of countries have done that. 43 However, retention of an income tax system forgoes some of the benefits that are obtained from adopting a consumption tax as a complete substitution for the income tax. For a variety of reasons, many tax experts and policymakers advocate for the federal tax system to transition from a (mostly) income base to a pure consumption base. 44 In addition, moving from the current return-based system (in which taxpayers must file annual income tax returns) to a retail-transaction-based system (in which retailers charge and collect taxes on transactions) would probably have political traction because of the public distaste for filing tax returns.45 One argument in favor of a consumption tax is the philosophical one that the private withdrawal of goods and services from the economy ought to be taxed, rather than the production of goods and services.46 Another is that an income tax discourages saving (i.e., future consumption) in favor of immediate consumption, while a consumption tax is neutral as to the timing of consumption. 47 Yet another ar43. For example, the United Kingdom, France, and Germany each have both an income tax and a value added tax (VAT). 44. See, e.g., EDWARD J. MCCAFFERY, FAIR NOT FLAT: HOW TO MAKE THE TAX SYSTEM BETTER AND SIMPLER (2002); LAURENCE S. SEIDMAN, THE USA TAX: A PROGRESSIVE CONSUMPTION TAX (1997) (each proposing transition to a consumption tax). 45. See NEAL BOORTZ & JOHN LINDER, THE FAIRTAX BOOK: SAYING GOODBYE TO THE INCOME TAX AND THE IRS 40-41 (2005) (describing public dissatisfaction with the filing of income tax returns). 46. See, e.g., N. Gregory Mankiw, A Better Tax System (Assembly Instructions Included), N.Y. TIMES (Jan. 21, 2012), http://www.nytimes.com/2012/01/22/business/four-keys-toa-better-tax-system-economic-view.html?_r=0. 47. To illustrate this point, Chirelstein and Zelenak use the following example. Consumer (C) and Saver (S) each earn $1,000 in wages in Year 1. In a tax-free, 10% interest world, C will consume $1,000 in Year 1, while S could consume $1,100 ($1,000 x 1.1) in Year 2. Under a 40% consumption tax, C would consume $600 ($1,000 – 40%) in Year 1, while S consumes $660 ($1,000 x 1.1 – 40%) in Year 2. Under a 40% income tax, C would again consume $600 in Year 1, while S could only consume $636 ([$1,000 – 40%] + [10% x ($1,000 – 40%)]). The 1:1.1 ratio between immediate and delayed consumption holds for
2013]
THE NEXT 100 YEARS
167
gument is that taxing income is much more difficult and complicated than taxing consumption. The realization rule—that gains and losses from property are generally taken into account only upon a sale or exchange of the property—is a necessary fixture of the income tax; yet it can be circumvented through hedging.48 More importantly, the realization rule creates incentives to hold onto appreciated property (to avoid income recognition) and to dispose of depreciated property (to trigger losses); the capital gains preference and limitations on capital losses are responses to these incentives. 49 In addition, capitalization and cost recovery issues (e.g., repairs versus improvements, capitalization and amortization of intangibles) can be immensely difficult to administer. The taxation of undistributed income of flowthrough business entities is also difficult. All of these problems would disappear under a consumption tax. 50 Under a consumption tax, realization of gains or losses would be a non-event because mere realizations do not represent consumption. Likewise, the amount that a taxpayer consumes is unaffected by whether a business expenditure results in long-term or short-term benefit, which means that the capitalization doctrine would be rendered irrelevant. 51 And reinvested profits of a business likewise do not result in consumption, which means that business entity taxation would no longer be necessary. 52 Despite the purported benefits of moving to a consumption tax imposed on transactions, two principal obstacles are thought to be the most significant deterrents. First, and most important, it is impossible, with current technology and prevailing political attitudes, to impart much progressivity into a retail sales tax (or into its close cousin, the VAT). Everyone must pay the same tax rate because the the tax-free world and the consumption tax but it is reduced to 1:1.06 for the income tax. See MARVIN A. CHIRELSTEIN & LAWRENCE ZELENAK, FEDERAL INCOME TAXATION 486 (12th ed. 2012). Note that in this example it is assumed that the tax base for both the income tax and the consumption tax is tax-inclusive. 48. David M. Schizer, Frictions as a Constraint on Tax Planning, 101 COLUM. L. REV. 1312, 1340-44 (2001). 49. David A. Weisbach, The (Non)Taxation of Risk, 58 TAX L. REV. 1 (2004). 50. This is not to say that tax complexity would altogether disappear. There still would remain disputes about whether something represents consumption (e.g., gifts or fringe benefits versus non-taxable perks) and valuation of in-kind consumption. See John K. McNulty, Flat Tax, Consumption Tax, Consumption-Type Income Tax Proposals in the United States: A Tax Policy Discussion of Fundamental Tax Reform, 88 CALIF. L. REV. 2095, 2178 (2000). But disputes falling under the “increase in net worth” side of the HaigSimons equation would disappear since the focus is on consumption, not on the value of one’s net worth. 51. Under a pure consumption tax, all expenditures would be immediately deductible, thereby eliminating the need for capitalization. See SLEMROD & BAKIJA, supra note 12, at 238. 52. However, it is politically unlikely in the extreme that there would be no taxes imposed on corporate entities. It is a virtual certainty that the corporate income tax would be retained or would be replaced by some other tax.
168
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:159
cash register cannot distinguish between Bill Gates and Joe the Plumber. 53 To alleviate those concerns, retail sales tax advocates often propose that the government pay a “prebate,” which is a fixed cash transfer to every taxpayer to offset the sales tax paid on a specified amount of consumption.54 A prebate would effectively create a single zero-bracket but would not result in different marginal tax rates above the zero-bracket amount. Thus, once a taxpayer consumes above the zero-bracket amount, the taxpayer would be taxed at the same marginal rate regardless of whether he was Joe the Plumber or Bill Gates. 55 Widespread government cash disbursements also seem to be, at this point, a political non-starter. Prebates involve the transfer of cash to every citizen, which (it is claimed) makes voters uncomfortable 56 and has the potential for fraud. 57 “Tax coupons,” which would exempt from tax a specified amount of spending each year, would avoid the politically unattractive cash transfers, but would also impart only very limited progressivity.58 Tax coupons would also likely face similar fraud issues. Another version of a consumption tax—the so-called cash-flow tax—could easily impart a good deal of progressivity in a politically acceptable way. The income tax could be turned into a cash-flow tax quite easily. By allowing for unlimited individual retirement account (IRA) contributions and also getting rid of any penalty taxes on premature IRA distributions, only income that is consumed during the year is taxed.59 The “consumed income” could then be subject to a 53. Another way to attempt to add progressivity is to have different rates for different types of items (food could be taxed at a low rate while yachts could be taxed at a high rate). This, however, is an imperfect tool and leads to administrative difficulties of how to label certain items for tax purposes. See Catherine Rampell, Value-Added Taxes: A Primer, N.Y. TIMES ECONOMIX BLOG (Apr. 19, 2010, 1:38 PM), http://economix.blogs.nytimes.com/2010/ 04/19/value-added-taxes-a-primer/. 54. See, e.g., BOORTZ & LINDER, supra note 45, at 84-85. 55. Note, however, that the use of a zero-bracket amount does provide some progressivity to the effective tax rate applied to consumers. For example, take a consumption tax system with a prebate amount of $1000, and a consumption tax rate of 20%. X spends $10,000 in year one, X pays a tax of $2000 (20% times $10,000). Taking into account the $1000 prebate, X’s effective tax rate is 10%: $2000 minus the $1000 prebate, or $1000, divided by $10,000. Y spends $20,000, and pays a tax of $4000 (20% times $20,000). Y’s effective tax rate is 15%: $4000 minus the $1000 prebate, or $3000, divided by $20,000. So, the effective rate paid by Y is greater than the effective rate paid by X, even though the marginal tax rates are the same. 56. Daniel N. Shaviro, Welfare, Cash Grants, and Marginal Rates, 59 SMU L. REV. 835, 839 (2006). 57. See, e.g., HANK ADLER & HUGH HEWITT, THE FAIRTAX FANTASY 46 (2009). 58. Cf. ZELENAK, supra note 4, at 76-77 (describing a 1943 proposal by Treasury Secretary Henry Morgenthau, Jr. for a national sales tax combined with tax coupons to impart progressivity). 59. See MCCAFFREY, supra note 44, at 57-58; SEIDMAN, supra note 44, at 6-7.
2013]
THE NEXT 100 YEARS
169
progressive tax rate schedule, so that as the taxpayer’s consumption increases during the year, the consumption is taxed at higher rates.60 This method of taxing consumption would probably be palatable to the public, as it would superficially look very much like the current income tax. On the other hand, a cash-flow tax would still require taxpayers to file annual returns, 61 which would take away the attractiveness of the proposal for those who wish to do away with individual returns. Futuristic “smart” e-payment systems could be able to track how much every taxpayer spends each year and to adjust the rate of tax (as calculated and collected by the retailer or by an e-payment middleman) as the taxpayer’s spending increases. Thus, for example, the first $10,000 of consumption spending could be tax free, with the next $10,000 taxable at a 5% rate, the next $10,000 at a 10% rate, and so on. To avoid liquidity issues for both taxpayers and the government, the amount of tax paid on a particular transaction would be a blended rate based on estimated annual consumption, and true-up adjustments would be made towards the end of the year if actual consumption during the year differed from projected consumption. 62 However, one problem with that approach is that it is vulnerable to tax evasion by the simple scheme of having purchases made for someone by a person with low consumption. 63 A second obstacle to moving to a consumption tax is the transition problem. Money already taxed under the outgoing income tax, as represented by the taxpayer’s aggregate basis in her assets or cash on hand, should not be taxed again under the new consumption tax.64 Absent any transition relief, under any of the consumption tax systems—retail sales tax, VAT, and cash-flow tax—double taxation of pre-enactment basis would result. 65 While there are ways to mitigate 60. See MCCAFFREY, supra note 44, at 57-58; SEIDMAN, supra note 44, at 6-7. 61. See MCCAFFREY, supra note 44, at 57. 62. For example, assume that a taxpayer, based on her prior year’s consumption (or income, if this is the first year of the consumption tax), is expected to spend $100,000 on consumption, which would (after taking account of any exemption amount) be taxed at an effective rate of 20%. At the beginning of the year, the tax would be imposed at that 20%. If the taxpayer’s spending during the year is less than expected, such that the expected effective tax rate is now 15%, the tax rate on future purchases would be adjusted. After the end of the year, when the proper tax rate is known with precision, a refund would be issued to the taxpayer for any excess tax paid. This system is much like the wage withholding system we have today. 63. Of course, if cash is completely eliminated, then the government should be able to track transactions between the evaders. 64. See MCCAFFERY, supra note 44, at 108-10 (discussing transition problem of preenactment basis). 65. While it is easy to see how double taxation would result under retail sales tax and VAT, double taxation may be harder to see under the cash-flow model, but it nevertheless exists there too. Under the cash-flow model, taxpayers would be required to put all of their investment assets into their IRA, and distributions therefrom would subsequently be taxed
170
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:159
the transition burden on existing wealth even under current technology, smart e-payment systems would make it easier to provide transition relief. Smart e-payment systems could take account of the taxpayer’s basis and cash at the time of transition and allow for that amount to purchase tax-free consumption to the extent legislators determine transition relief is warranted. The amount of such exclusion from the consumption tax could be amortized over the anticipated consumption of the taxpayer during the taxpayer’s life expectancy. Payment systems technology could make a progressive retail sales tax that includes such transition relief for pre-enactment basis a realistic possibility. E-payment technology would allow third-party intermediaries (or, more rarely, retailers) to adjust the tax rate imposed on purchases to take account of both the taxpayer’s consumption level and the taxpayer’s previously taxed assets. The technology could also allow a taxpayer’s pre-enactment basis to be amortized against future consumption, preventing or at least ameliorating the double taxation problem. As a political matter, a progressive retail sales tax would have a number of benefits to make it attractive. It would remove the inconvenience of taxpayers having to file annual tax returns, which is something that voters claim to hate.66 Because the tax would be paid in small increments, like traditional retail sales taxes imposed by states, it would be less salient than the current income tax. 67 And the tax would be progressive without requiring the government to make direct wealth transfers to its citizens. Once the requisite technology is eventually developed, the major impediment to implementing a progressive retail sales tax would probably be privacy concerns. To impose the correct tax rate at the point of retail sale, the third-party intermediary (or, perhaps, the retail seller) would need to know the amount of the buyer’s previous consumption. This could be troubling to some people, though they might be comforted by the fact that machines, not people, will be aggregating and processing the consumption data. Unfortunately, we have seen that people can farm information out of the machines that collect it. 68 We also must keep in mind that attitudes towards privacy regardless of whether the distributions represent amounts previously taxed under the former income tax, thereby resulting in double taxation. 66. A Third of Americans Say They Like Doing Their Income Taxes, PEW RESEARCH CTR. (Apr. 11, 2013), http://www.people-press.org/2013/04/11/a-third-of-americans-saythey-like-doing-their-income-taxes/. 67. The salience of the income tax is reduced by the withholding mechanism. However, since taxpayers must file an income tax return each year, they will see their ultimate tax bill even if they do not have to pay it all at once. 68. Amir M. Hormozi & Stacy Giles, Data Mining: A Competitive Weapon for Banking and Retail Industries, INFO. SYS. MGMT., Spring 2004, at 62, 69.
2013]
THE NEXT 100 YEARS
171
and technology will certainly evolve as we inevitably move towards a paperless society. For example, the idea of electronic stock registration (in lieu of physical shares) would surely have been a non-starter over much of the stock market’s history, yet physical shares are now nearly obsolete. And the information now voluntarily shared by Facebook users would have been considered extremely private in years past. 69 So while current prevailing attitudes towards privacy might preclude the enactment of a progressive retail sales tax now, it is quite possible that privacy concerns will eventually diminish to the point where such a tax is politically feasible. Privacy concerns might also ensure that at least some cash transactions will continue to occur. People who place a high value on anonymous purchasing may continue to use cash.70 Other people might choose to use cash only when they are making purchases that they consider particularly private or sensitive. The persistence of cash transactions would pose a problem for a progressive retail sales tax. Ideally, the same amount of tax ought to be imposed whether payments are made in cash or electronically. But only electronic payments can be tracked, and such tracking is necessary in order to determine the correct tax rate. It seems to us that the best solution would be to impose the highest statutory tax rate on cash purchases and require the retail seller to collect the tax. This would treat all cash purchases as if persons with large amounts of consumption made them. In many cases, this would overtax cash purchases and, in effect, act as a penalty on anonymous purchasing. This would be an unintended by-product of a progressive retail sales tax, but given the expected evolution in attitudes regarding privacy, it is possible that this penalty might not impede the eventual enactment of such a tax. IV. CONCLUSION In this Symposium Essay, we have argued that technological innovation will be critical during the next 100 years of the income tax. On the one hand, the increasing prevalence of electronic payment systems should bolster the income tax by substantially reducing the tax gap and mitigating the distortions caused by the cash economy. On the other hand, technological innovation and the corresponding evolution of attitudes towards privacy could make a progressive retail sales tax quite feasible, which might spell the end of the income tax. 69. Natasha Singer, Your Online Attention, Bought in an Instant, N.Y. TIMES (Nov. 17, 2012), http://www.nytimes.com/2012/11/18/technology/your-online-attention-bought-inan-instant-by-advertisers.html?pagewanted=1&_r=0. 70. Even without cash, anonymous electronic currencies, such as bit coins, may be available. See Marian, supra note 24, at 39.
172
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:159
ON THE FUTURE OF TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP: OPERATIVE MECHANISMS AND LIMITING FACTORS DAVID GAMAGE ∗ I. INTRODUCTION.................................................................................................. II. BACKGROUND.................................................................................................... A. Market Salience ......................................................................................... 1. Spotlighting ......................................................................................... 2. Ironing ................................................................................................. B. Political Salience ....................................................................................... 1. Indirect taxes ........................................................................................ 2. Tax-system complexity ......................................................................... 3. Withholding ......................................................................................... 4. Deficit financing................................................................................... 5. Sticky baselines .................................................................................... 6. Tax-label aversion ................................................................................ III. OPERATIVE MECHANISMS ................................................................................. A. Bounded Rationality .................................................................................. B. Time Inconsistency..................................................................................... C. Framing Effects ......................................................................................... IV. LIMITING FACTORS............................................................................................ A. Size of the Tax Liability ............................................................................. B. Learning from Experience.......................................................................... C. Aversion to Being Manipulated ................................................................. V. CONCLUSION .....................................................................................................
173 176 177 177 177 177 178 178 178 179 179 179 179 181 185 188 193 193 195 199 202
I. INTRODUCTION As we celebrate the centennial anniversary of the U.S. federal income tax and look forward to the next hundred years, it is worth reflecting on the nature of tax scholarship. The U.S. tax system is incomprehensibly complex. Any attempt to assess the U.S. tax system must therefore rely on applying some theoretical frame. Which frames are chosen, and how they are applied, potentially has firstorder consequences for how we understand the role of the income tax as a central component of the U.S. system of governance. The two most important frames that have been used to assess the income tax over the past hundred years are comprehensive tax base theory1 and optimal tax theory.2 Both of these approaches have ∗ Assistant Professor of Law, University of California, Berkeley (Boalt Hall). Many thanks to Joe Dodge, Brian Galle, Jacob Goldin, Andrew Hayashi, James Hines, Doug Kahn, Jeff Kahn, Stacie Kinser, Shruti Rana, Chris Sanchirico, Darien Shanske, Larry Zelenak, and other participants of the “One-Hundred Years of the Federal Income Tax” Symposium at Florida State University. 1. See, e.g., Boris I. Bittker, A “Comprehensive Tax Base” as a Goal of Income Tax Reform, 80 HARV. L. REV. 925 (1967) (discussing comprehensive tax base theory); Joseph A. Pechman, Comprehensive Income Taxation: A Comment, 81 HARV. L. REV. 63 (1967) (same). 2. See, e.g., LOUIS KAPLOW, THE THEORY OF TAXATION AND PUBLIC ECONOMICS (2008) (providing an overview of optimal tax theory); BERNARD SALANIÉ, THE ECONOMICS OF TAX-
174
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
generated powerful insights. Yet both of these approaches also have serious limitations. 3 Over the past few decades, optimal tax theory has come to dominate tax scholarship in both economics departments and elite law schools. A number of strands of recent scholarship have thus attempted to address some of the limitations of optimal tax theory as it has traditionally been employed. One of the most prominent of these recent scholarly trends is the study of questions related to tax salience. 4 In a recent Article, Darien Shanske and I reviewed the developing literature on tax salience. 5 When we began the project that led to that article, we were hopeful that the literature on tax salience could be applied to illuminate a number of conundrums plaguing both federal and state and local tax policy. However, we ultimately concluded that the literature on tax salience is not yet sufficiently developed to be applied in making concrete recommendations for practical tax policy problems. Building on that article, this Essay—written for Florida State University’s symposium on the 100th anniversary of the federal income tax—evaluates how the literature on tax salience should be advanced in order for it to guide more effectively tax policy over the coming decades. In particular, this Essay analyzes potential limiting factors to the operation of observed tax salience effects. To date, most of the empirical literature on tax salience has focused on demonstrating the existence of specific tax salience effects within particular contexts. Building on these empirical studies, most of the normative scholarship engaging with tax salience has been based on extrapolating from the discrete instances of tax salience ef(2d ed. 2011) (same). 3. For discussions of the limitations of optimal tax theory (as it has traditionally been employed), see, for example, James Alm, What is an “Optimal” Tax System?, in TAX POLICY IN THE REAL WORLD 363 (Joel Slemrod ed., 1999); Christopher Heady, Optimal Taxation as a Guide to Tax Policy: A Survey, 14 FISCAL STUD. 15 (1993); Alex Raskolnikov, Accepting the Limits of Tax Law and Economics, 98 CORNELL L. REV. 523 (2013). 4. For a definition of tax salience, see David Gamage & Darien Shanske, Three Essays on Tax Salience: Market Salience and Political Salience, 65 TAX L. REV. 19, 23 (2011) (“As we use the term, ‘tax salience’ refers to the extent to which taxpayers account for the costs imposed by taxation when the taxpayers make decisions or judgments. The concept of tax salience is thus meant to abstract from taxpayers’ values or preferences with respect to taxation—from how the taxpayers might wish to account for tax costs were they not subject to cognitive limitations. Our concept of tax salience would be meaningless in a world of complete information in which taxpayers had unlimited time and resources and were not subject to any cognitive biases. Thus, our concept of tax salience is meant to capture any systematic differences between how taxpayers would perceive the costs of taxation in this hypothetical world of perfect economic rationality and how taxpayers actually perceive the costs of taxation in the real world.” (footnote omitted)). 5. Id. ATION
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
175
fects observed in these empirical studies. Only a handful of scholars have attempted to develop more systematic theories for how tax salience might operate. 6 Yet in the absence of more systematic theories, we cannot predict with any confidence how tax salience effects might operate outside of the specific empirical contexts in which they have been observed. Only after analyzing potential operative mechanisms and limiting factors should we apply the developing literature on tax salience to broad questions of tax policy. I should note at the outset that the purpose of this Essay is not to critique the existing scholarship on tax salience. Conducting empirical studies to demonstrate the existence of tax salience effects within specific contexts is a necessary first step for developing more general theories.7 Rather, the intent of this Essay is to point out that more is needed before the tax salience literature can offer a useful guide with respect to the complexities of real-world policy. Most importantly, normative scholars should not assume that a tax salience effect that is demonstrated to occur within one set of particular circumstances will necessarily manifest when circumstances differ. This Essay evaluates potential limiting factors to the operation of tax salience effects, such as the size of the tax liability, taxpayers learning from experience, and taxpayers’ aversion to being manipulated. These limiting factors have the potential to prevent tax salience effects that are shown to occur in one set of circumstances from manifesting in scenarios where these limiting factors are strongly present. Ultimately, in order to develop a broader theory capable of predicting the conditions under which tax salience effects are likely to prove important, we must develop a better understanding of the operative mechanisms underlying tax salience. To this end, the literature on tax salience must move beyond offering a list of biases and must seek instead to provide a theory of cognition (or of social reasoning or of whatever else might underlie observed tax salience effects). This Essay proceeds as follows. Part II provides background by briefly summarizing the portions of my previous article with Darien Shanske upon which this Essay builds. Following that background, Part III evaluates three potential operative mechanisms that might underlie observed tax salience effects. Part IV then analyzes three potential limiting factors that might prevent tax salience effects from 6. And these attempts have been limited to applications of the bounded rationality paradigm. See infra Part III.A. 7. Indeed, I have conducted research of this sort myself; see Andrew T. Hayashi, Brent K. Nakamura & David Gamage, Experimental Evidence of Tax Salience and the Labor-Leisure Decision: Anchoring, Tax Aversion, or Complexity?, 41 PUB. FIN. REV. 203 (2013).
176
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
occurring in circumstances under which these limiting factors are strongly present. Part V concludes. II. BACKGROUND One of the central contributions of my prior article with Darien Shanske was to argue that market salience and political salience should be considered distinct concepts.8 In our terminology, “market salience” refers to when tax salience effects occur with respect to market decisionmaking (for example, consumer purchasing), and “political salience” refers to when tax salience effects occur with respect to political judgment formation (for example, individual voting). 9 We argued that market salience and political salience often work in opposite directions.10 Factors capable of “reduc[ing] market salience may increase political salience, and vice versa.” 11 Much of our article was devoted to evaluating normative arguments that have been made about the policy implications of tax salience.12 This Essay does not primarily build on that discussion of normative arguments, but rather seeks to further develop our conclusion that “the existing empirical findings on both forms of tax salience are tentative. . . . [W]e cannot currently predict with any confidence how tax-design techniques affect tax salience within realworld environments.” 13 Yet before proceeding to develop this conclusion by evaluating possible operative mechanisms and limiting factors, it is necessary to first briefly summarize the overview we provided in that article of hypotheses about tax salience in the existing literature. 14 Readers 8. Gamage & Shanske, supra note 4, at 54-59. 9. For further discussion, see id. at 24-25. 10. Id. at 54-58. 11. Id. at 54. 12. Id. at 60-98. 13. Id. at 22-23. 14. The remainder of this Part summarizes portions of my prior article with Darien Shanske. Elaboration on and support for all of the statements made in the remainder of this Part can be found in that prior article, id. at 22-54. Since its publication, there have been a number of important developments in the literature on tax salience. Due to space and scope constraints, I will not review those developments in this Essay. Particularly noteworthy recent additions to the literature include: STEVEN M. SHEFFRIN, TAX FAIRNESS AND FOLK JUSTICE (2013); Lilian V. Faulhaber, The Hidden Limits of the Charitable Deduction: An Introduction to Hypersalience, 92 B.U. L. REV. 1307 (2012); Brian Galle, Carrots, Sticks, and Salience, 66 TAX L. REV. (forthcoming 2013), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2224160; Jacob Goldin & Tatiana Homonoff, Smoke Gets in Your Eyes: Cigarette Tax Salience and Regressivity, 5 AM. ECON. J.: ECON. POL’Y 302 (2013); Jacob Goldin, Note, Sales Tax Not Included: Designing Commodity Taxes for Inattentive Consumers, 122 YALE L.J. 258 (2012); Andrew T. Hayashi, The Legal Salience of Taxation (Sept. 14, 2012) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2151867; Daniel Reck, Taxes and Mistakes: What's in a Sufficient Statistic? (July 29, 2013) (unpublished manuscript), available
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
177
who are already familiar with the empirical literature on tax salience may wish to skip the remainder of this Part, so as to begin reading with this Essay’s contributions to the literature in Parts III and IV. A. Market Salience Taxpayers do not always fully factor the price effects of taxation into their market decisions.15 Two categories of market salience— spotlighting and ironing—examine two different hypotheses for how taxpayers may respond to complicated or obscured tax prices. 1. Spotlighting Spotlighting involves taxpayers focusing only on certain components of an aggregate price and thereby underestimating the aggregate price. 16 Most observed spotlighting behavior results from a separation of the tax assessment from the market decision. 17 In particular, a number of empirical studies suggest that taxpayers often discount taxes that are not assessed until after a market decision has been made. 18 In other words, taxpayers appear often to spotlight on the prices displayed at the time of market decisionmaking. 2. Ironing Ironing occurs when taxpayers incorrectly use their average tax rates when making market decisions rather than their marginal tax rates. 19 In essence, ironing is a form of spotlighting behavior wherein taxpayers spotlight on their average tax rates when it would be more economically rational for the taxpayers to make decisions based on their marginal tax rates. B. Political Salience Political salience refers to how the presentation of taxes affects political decisionmaking. For instance, certain tax instruments may have low political salience if voters discount tax costs imposed through these instruments when making voting decisions. A number of factors have been hypothesized to influence the political salience of taxation, including: indirect taxes, tax-system complexity, withholding, deficit financing, sticky baselines, and tax-label aversion. 20 at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2268617. 15. Gamage & Shanske, supra note 4, at 26. 16. Id. at 27. 17. Id. 18. Id. at 27-31. 19. Id. at 31. 20. Id. at 34-54.
178
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
1. Indirect taxes Indirect taxes refer to tax instruments for which the statutory incidence falls on businesses or other intermediaries rather than on individual taxpayers. 21 Even though at least a portion of the economic burden of indirect taxes falls on consumers in the form of higher prices, because voters do not personally remit these taxes they are alleged to have low political salience. 22 In other words, according to the indirect-taxes hypothesis, the public may often ascribe the burden of indirect taxes to the nominal payors, thus failing to account fully for taxes that the voting public does not explicitly pay. 2. Tax-system complexity The tax-system complexity hypothesis holds that the voting public may discount tax prices for which determining the overall tax price requires more complex calculations.23 For instance, many have alleged that breaking a tax price into a series of smaller payments assessed over a period of time may reduce political salience as compared to assessing a single aggregate tax price.24 It is also sometimes alleged that reducing the compliance costs of tax instruments may lower the political salience of those tax instruments. 25 3. Withholding It is frequently alleged that the use of withholding mechanisms may lower the political salience of the withheld taxes.26 However, the existing literature is not entirely clear as to what it is about withholding that is thought to reduce political salience. 27 It has been posited that breaking tax remittances into smaller regular payments may reduce the political salience of the tax liabilities. 28 To the extent this is so, the withholding hypothesis can be thought of as a subfactor of the tax-system-complexity hypothesis. Alternatively, if tax liabilities subject to withholding are viewed more like money that is never received rather than a coercive extraction from the taxpayer’s income, then the withholding hypothesis may operate similar to the indirect-taxes hypothesis. 29 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29.
Id. at 35. Id. at 35-38. Id. at 39-41. Id. Id. Id. at 41-43. Id. Id. Id.
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
179
4. Deficit financing The costs of deficit financing may be less politically salient than the costs of financing through current taxes. 30 In a sense, the deficitfinancing hypothesis may operate like the market-salience hypothesis for spotlighting, to the extent that the deficit-financing hypothesis operates through the separation in time between voting decisions and when the future tax liabilities are imposed.31 5. Sticky baselines The sticky-baselines hypothesis groups several sub-hypotheses that all stand for the principle that foregone tax cuts are less politically salient than are actual tax hikes.32 These sub-hypotheses include the flypaper effect, bracket creep, income elasticity, and the fiscal-volatility effect. 33 6. Tax-label aversion The final political salience hypothesis is based on the notion that the mere labeling of a policy as a “tax” can reduce voter support for the policy. This general notion can be grouped into a number of related sub-hypotheses, including: taxes versus other extractions, taxfinanced spending versus tax expenditures, and tax-financed spending versus regulation.34 III. OPERATIVE MECHANISMS There is considerable evidence that tax salience effects are real and that they are potentially important. However, the existing literature cannot yet offer clear predictions about how tax salience operates with respect to real-world tax instruments. In particular, the existing literature does not sufficiently analyze potential limiting factors to the hypotheses advanced about tax salience, and the literature thus cannot determine whether increased use of techniques for reducing tax salience would have the intended effect. 35 Ultimately, our current understanding of both market salience and political salience remains largely speculative.
30. See id. at 43-45. 31. Id. 32. See id. at 45-49. 33. Id. 34. See id. at 49-54. 35. A key paper—Raj Chetty, Adam Looney & Kory Kroft, Salience and Taxation: Theory and Evidence, 99 AM. ECON. REV. 1145 (2009)—does analyze limiting factors, but only within a bounded rationality model. See infra Part III.A.
180
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
One method for improving our understanding of tax salience is through empirical testing of discrete tax salience hypotheses—such as the research reviewed in my prior article with Darien Shanske and summarized in Part II of this Essay. I am hopeful that this approach will yield further insights, and I applaud scholars engaged in this form of research. 36 However, testing of discrete hypotheses must be complemented with bigger-picture theorizing. An empirical study can only evaluate the predictions of a hypothesis as it relates to the particular circumstances giving rise to the experimental data. Without proper theoretical contextualizing, policy-minded scholars may inappropriately extrapolate the results of an empirical study to circumstances in which the results are unlikely to hold.37 I continue to believe that tax salience has multiple dimensions and that market salience and political salience should be considered distinct concepts. Nevertheless, both market salience and political salience are likely to result from similar operative mechanisms. Both refer to how taxpayers perceive their tax burdens with respect to either their market or political decisionmaking. Over the last couple decades, behavioral economists and decision-theory psychologists have developed a rich literature analyzing how consumers respond to price-shrouding techniques as employed by private-sector firms. This Part attempts to apply that consumer behavior literature to analyze potential operative mechanisms underlying both the market salience and political salience of taxation. 38 A strong finding of the consumer behavior literature is that misperceiving prices does not necessarily imply underestimating prices.39 When consumers are faced with convoluted price calculations in the private sector, they do not always underestimate the final price. Indeed, depending on the details of how a price is made convoluted, consumers may overestimate the final price rather than underestimating it.40 Consequently, it is naive to assume that taxpayers will 36. As noted earlier, supra note 7, I have engaged in this form of research myself. 37. Arguably, a primary goal of empirical research is to test hypotheses, so that the supported hypotheses can yield predictions outside of the contexts directly studied. Theorizing about operative mechanisms and limiting factors can help refine hypotheses and generate new predictions to be tested through future empirical work. 38. My discussion here builds on similar work by others, including: Aradhna Krishna & Joel Slemrod, Behavioral Public Finance: Tax Design as Price Presentation, 10 INT’L TAX & PUB. FIN. 189 (2003); Edward J. McCaffery & Jonathan Baron, Thinking About Tax, 12 PSYCHOL. PUB. POL’Y & L. 106 (2006). 39. Hyeong Min Kim & Luke Kachersky, Dimensions of Price Salience: A Conceptual Framework for Perceptions of Multi-Dimensional Prices, 15 J. PRODUCT & BRAND MGMT. 139, 139-40 (2006). 40. Vicki G. Morwitz, Eric A. Greenleaf, Edith Shalev & Eric J. Johnson, The Price Does Not Include Additional Taxes, Fees, and Surcharges: A Review of Research on Partitioned Pricing 36 (July 26, 2011) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1350004 (“[F]irms need to understand that partitioned pricing
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
181
necessarily underestimate their tax liabilities when faced with difficult tax calculations. If a taxpayer is aware of the existence of a tax instrument but has trouble calculating her tax liabilities, should she not just estimate her tax liability and use this estimate when making market and political decisions? This Part posits three potential explanations for what might cause taxpayers to (at least sometimes) underestimate their tax burdens. I label these mechanisms as: bounded rationality, time inconsistency, and framing effects. These mechanisms are not mutually exclusive. Methods for attempting to reduce tax salience may function through multiple or even all of these mechanisms. Nevertheless, determining which operative mechanisms potentially underlie empirical findings of tax salience is important both for generating hypotheses to be tested through future empirical research and for predicting the robustness of the empirical findings to limiting factors. Moreover, determining which operative mechanisms underlie observed tax salience effects may also be important for assessing their normative implications. A. Bounded Rationality Bounded rationality refers to explanations wherein taxpayers rationally allocate scarce cognitive resources. 41 Once we recognize that taxpayers have limited time, energy, willpower, or other cognitive resources, it becomes manifestly obvious that taxpayers will not always perform all of the calculations needed to accurately assess the tax implications of their decisions. In their seminal paper on the market salience of taxation, Chetty, Looney, and Kroft presented an influential model of bounded rationality. 42 Their model predicts that taxpayers will be more likely to spotlight on immediately available price components (e.g., ignoring taxes that are not assessed until after the time of market decisionmaking) when making small, repeated purchases, and when tax rates are low. 43 Conversely, their model predicts that consumers will be more likely to calculate aggregate (post-tax) prices when making large, one-time purchases, or when tax rates are high. 44 The underlying notion is that consumers are more likely to expend the time and effort to calculate post-tax prices when more is at stake in their doing so. Effectively, Chetty, Looney, and benefits firms in many situations, but certainly not in all situations. . . . If some or all of these factors are absent, however, partitioned pricing can have no positive impact, or even a negative one.”). 41. See generally Matthew D. Adler, Bounded Rationality and Legal Scholarship (Univ. of Pa. Law Sch. Inst. for Law & Econ., Research Paper No. 08-03, 2008), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1095874. 42. Chetty et al., supra note 35. 43. See id. at 1149-64. 44. See id. at 1175-76.
182
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
Kroft’s bounded-rationality approach models consumers as trading off between making tax-efficient purchasing decisions and expending the cognitive effort required to calculate post-tax prices. Within a bounded-rationality framework, the more complicated a tax calculation becomes, the less likely it becomes that taxpayers will accurately assess their tax liabilities. This dynamic can affect political salience as well as market salience. The more difficult it becomes to accurately assess tax burdens, as compared to how much the taxpayer cares about making accurate political judgments, the less likely that the taxpayer will expend effort to incorporate accurately tax information into her voting decisions.45 However, as I noted earlier, taxpayers do not necessarily respond to complicated tax calculations by underestimating their tax liabilities.46 If a taxpayer makes a rough estimate of the post-tax price of a market decision, or of the tax liability associated with a political decision, the taxpayer may well overestimate (rather than underestimate) the tax consequences. 47 Hence, to reduce tax salience under a bounded-rationality framework requires doing more than just increasing complexity; a common strategy involves offering taxpayers a reference price that is lower than the total price. 48 If the reference price is close enough to the total price and is significantly more available, taxpayers may be induced to focus solely on the reference price rather than expending the effort to calculate the total price. 49 Reference-price strategies can be 45. If voters care little about accurately incorporating tax information into their voting decisions, voting behavior may be especially prone to manipulation. 46. See supra text accompanying notes 39-40. 47. See Kim et al., supra note 39, at 139-40. 48. Id. at 140. 49. See id. at 139-40 (“This stream of research contends that consumers trade-off the benefits of accuracy with the costs of time and effort to process MDPs, and therefore they often underestimate total prices.”). In the consumer behavior literature, price-presentation strategies that involve making price calculations more complicated and then offering a reference price that is lower than the final price are called “price-partitioning strategies,” “reference-price strategies,” or “multi-dimensional-pricing strategies.” See, e.g., ChienHuang Lin, Shih-Chieh Chuang & Chaang-Yung Kung, The Presence of Reference Price: How Value Can Appear Convergent to Buyers and Sellers, 33 ADVANCES IN CONSUMER RES. 237 (2006); Kim et al., supra note 39; Richard L. Ott & David M. Andrus, The Effect of Personal Property Taxes on Consumer Vehicle Purchasing Decisions: A PartitionedPrice/Mental Accounting Theory Analysis, 28 PUB. FIN. REV. 134 (2000). There are many variations to this basic strategic approach. For instance, one variation involves offering a discount and then trying to make the discount appear as salient and large as possible, rather than trying to make surcharges to the reference price less salient. For a couple other variations: “bundling” consists of charging a single combined price for multiple distinct goods, while “options pricing” involves creating additional features that can be added to a base product for additional charge. Marco Bertini & Luc Wathieu, Research Note, Attention Arousal Through Price Partitioning, 27 MARKETING SCI. 236, 237 (2008). These variations may also have tax-salience analogs, particularly in the state and local government context where it is common to assess fees and user charges for various publically provided services as an alternative to taxation.
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
183
especially effective when there is a temporal gap between when the reference price is assessed and when the final price is charged. 50 As DellaVigna notes, “[h]olding constant the informativeness, information that is further into the future (or past) is less likely to be salient.” 51 With regard to market salience, studies of the spotlighting hypothesis found that taxpayers often discount taxes that are not assessed until after market decisions are made. 52 In other words, the price components available at the time of market decisionmaking may function as a reference price.53 The reference-price dynamic also provides a potential explanation for the ironing hypothesis. Nonlinear price schedules can be difficult to understand, and boundedly rational taxpayers may prefer to use a reference price rather than calculating their actual marginal tax rates when faced with a nonlinear price schedule. If taxpayers sometimes use their average tax burdens from prior time periods as a reference price for predicting their future tax liabilities, then this would result in ironing behavior.54 With respect to political salience, the basic reference-pricing dynamic supports the indirect-taxes and deficit-financing hypotheses.55 For indirect taxes, voters may use their direct tax burdens as a reference price, discounting the burdens of indirect taxes when reaching political judgments. 56 Similarly, for deficit financing, voters may use their current tax burdens as a reference price, discounting the increased future tax burdens needed to repay accrued debt. 57 50. Stefano DellaVigna, Psychology and Economics: Evidence from the Field, 47 J. ECON. LITERATURE 315, 352 (2009). 51. Id. 52. See supra Part II.A. 53. For example, pre-sales-tax prices are close enough to aggregate post-sales-tax prices (as most states’ sales taxes have rates below ten percent) and are significantly more available due to their being posted on the store aisles such that boundedly rational consumers may well decide it is not worth their time and effort to incorporate sales taxes into their purchasing decisions. See Chetty et al., supra note 35, at 1165-75. As another potential example, the time gap between when many income-tax-related decisions need to be made (December 31st) and when income taxes are calculated (April 15th) may reduce the market salience of decisions related to claiming income tax deductions and credits. 54. This explanation for ironing behavior is empirically supported by Feldman and Katuščák’s finding that taxpayers make market decisions partially based on their average income-tax rates from prior years, even controlling for the relationship between prior and current year tax status. See Naomi E. Feldman & Peter Katuščák, Should the Average Tax Rate Be Marginalized? (Charles Univ. Ctr. For Econ. Research & Graduate Educ., Acad. of Scis. of the Czech, Econ. Inst., Working Paper No. 304, 2006), available at http://www.cerge-ei.cz/pdf/wp/Wp304.pdf. 55. For political salience, scholars have typically used the terms “isolation effect” or “focusing effect” in place of “spotlighting” or “reference pricing,” but the underlying idea is the same. See, e.g., Edward J. McCaffery & Jonathan Baron, Isolation Effects and the Neglect of Indirect Effects of Fiscal Policies, 19 J. BEHAV. DECISION MAKING 289, 290 (2006). 56. See id. 57. See id. at 297-300.
184
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
Within the consumer behavior literature, a potentially important variation on the basic reference-pricing strategy is sometimes called “pennies-a-day.” 58 The idea is that if a total price can be divided into a series of smaller sub-prices assessed over a prolonged period of time, then it can become more difficult to calculate the aggregate final price, and consumers may be induced to focus on the smaller periodic payments as a reference price. The pennies-a-day concept thus supports the tax-system-complexity hypothesis that tax instruments which levy many smaller payments over a period of time (e.g., sales taxes) may have lower political salience than tax instruments which levy fewer larger tax payments (e.g., property taxes). Krishna and Slemrod have speculated that this mechanism also supports the view that withholding reduces the political salience of the income tax.59 Another potentially important variation on the reference-pricing strategy has been called the “metric effect.” 60 Research has demonstrated that individuals may react differently to prices depending on whether the prices are presented in dollar values or as percentages.61 This metric effect manifests for both market salience and political salience. For market salience, displaying prices as percentages— instead of in dollar values—appears to make prices seem lower when the percentages are small and to make prices seem higher when the percentages are large. 62 When base prices are displayed in one format (either in dollar values or as percentages) and tax surcharges in another format, this can increase the cognitive effort needed to calculate aggregate prices and thereby make taxpayers more likely to spotlight on the reference price. For political salience, voters’ attitudes toward progressivity and other tax-policy topics appear to differ dramatically depending on whether tax liabilities are displayed in dollar amounts or as percentages.63 Many voters appear to support progressivity “without having a strong sense about what progressivity means or about how much
58. Krishna & Slemrod, supra note 38, at 193. The pennies-a-day strategy may also function via the mechanisms of time-inconsistency and/or framing effects, as I will discuss further infra Part III.B–C. 59. Id. at 193-94. 60. McCaffery & Baron, supra note 38, at 113. 61. Id. at 114. 62. See, e.g., Timothy B. Heath, Subimal Chatterjee & Karen Russo France, Mental Accounting and Changes in Price: The Frame Dependence of Reference Dependence, 22 J. CONSUMER RES. 90, 96 (1995) (“A $50 savings probably sounds smaller when framed as a 1 percent discount, and a $100 savings probably sounds larger when framed as a 50 percent discount.”); Morwitz et al., supra note 40, at 37. 63. See, e.g., McCaffery & Baron, supra note 38, at 113-14 (“Most strikingly, subjects gave systematically different answers on the basis of whether the question was asked using dollars or percentages . . . .”).
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
185
progressivity they favor.” 64 For instance, “[u]nder the standard definitions, a ‘flat tax’ is defined as when all taxpayers pay the same percentage of their incomes in taxation, and a ‘progressive tax’ as when higher-income taxpayers pay a greater percentage of their incomes in taxation than do lower-income taxpayers.”65 But when tax liabilities are displayed in dollar values rather than as percentages, higherincome taxpayers are shown as paying more in taxes than lowerincome taxpayers even under a flat tax. Ed McCaffery and Jon Baron have thus demonstrated that displaying tax distribution information in dollar values can dramatically reduce voters’ support for progressivity.66 Overall, then, the bounded rationality framework provides a potential operative mechanism for the hypotheses that have been forwarded regarding both market salience and political salience, as discussed in Part II. However, alternative operational mechanisms may also explain and support these hypotheses. This Part thus proceeds to discuss two alternative operational mechanisms: time inconsistency and framing effects. B. Time Inconsistency Within a bounded-rationality framework, temporal gaps can decrease tax salience by making it more difficult to calculate post-tax prices. Temporal gaps are also key to the time-inconsistency framework, but the mechanism is not due to increasing the complexity of tax calculations. Instead, the time-inconsistency framework operates when taxpayers mispredict their future behavior or irrationally overdiscount the effects of a present decision on their future selves. More specifically, numerous laboratory and field experiments have demonstrated that individuals do not always discount the future implications of their decisions as predicted by standard economic models.67 Individuals frequently engage in what is often called “hyperbolic discounting” and apply a much higher discount rate when comparing the present to the near future than when comparing two time periods in the future.68 As DellaVigna elaborates: [E]vidence suggests that discounting is steeper in the immediate future than in the further future. For example, the median subject in Thaler (1981) is indifferent between $15 now and $20 in one 64. Gamage & Shanske, supra note 4, at 83. 65. Id. at 83-84. 66. McCaffery & Baron, supra note 38, at 113-14. 67. See DellaVigna, supra note 50, at 318-23; Lee Anne Fennell & Kirk J. Stark, Taxation Over Time, 59 TAX L. REV. 1, 13-15 (2005). 68. David Laibson, Golden Eggs and Hyperbolic Discounting, 112 Q.J. ECON. 443, 449 (1997).
186
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
month (for an annual discount rate of 345 percent) and between $15 now and $100 in ten years (for an annual discount rate of 19 percent). 69
Three related hypotheses have been forwarded to explain this hyperbolic-discounting behavior. First, taxpayers may simply not value the welfare of their future selves in the same fashion as they do the welfare of their present selves. 70 An important philosophical approach associated with Derek Parfit argues that personal identity is not stable over time. 71 The implications of this view are far from straightforward, and I will not attempt to do them justice in this Essay. Nevertheless, it is worth noting that if taxpayers care more about their present selves than their future selves, then a taxpayer operating at any specific moment in time may view the gap between her present self and her near-future self as considerably more important than the gap between her more-distant-future self and her self in a time period following that more-distant future.72 Hence, hyperbolic-discounting behavior may be caused by taxpayers valuing their present selves over their future selves. A second explanation for hyperbolic-discounting behavior is “selfcontrol problems.” Self-control problems operate when taxpayers make decisions inconsistent with their own judgments about welfare over time because they lack the willpower to refrain from immediately satisfying their present desires.73 Anyone who has consciously over-eaten when faced with a good meal or who has been unable to resist the in-the-moment temptations of candy, alcohol, or gambling, should understand what is meant by self-control problems. Finally, hyperbolic discounting may be due to an “optimism bias” wherein individuals make unrealistic predictions about their likely future behavior or about likely future conditions. For example, consumers appear to regularly over-predict the amount they will exercise in the future when purchasing health club memberships 74 and to
69. DellaVigna, supra note 50, at 318. 70. See Lawrence Zelenak, Tax Policy and Personal Identity over Time, 62 TAX L. REV. 333 (2009). 71. See DEREK PARFIT, REASONS AND PERSONS (1984). 72. If taxpayers limit their conception of self to their present self but have partialaltruistic preferences toward all of their future selves, they might well strongly prioritize the welfare of their present self over all future selves, but they might not strongly prioritize the welfare of a near-future self over a more-distant-future self. For further discussion more generally, see Daniel M. Bartels & Oleg Urminsky, On Intertemporal Selfishness: How the Perceived Instability of Identity Underlies Impatient Consumption, 38 J. CONSUMER RES. 182 (2011). 73. DellaVigna, supra note 50, at 318-24. 74. Stefano DellaVigna & Ulrike Malmendier, Contract Design and Self-Control: Theory and Evidence, 119 Q.J. ECON. 353, 373-77 (2004).
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
187
under-predict the amount they will borrow in the future when deciding whether to open credit-card accounts. 75 Under all three explanations, hyperbolic discounting can lead taxpayers to make choices in the moment that do not correspond with the taxpayers’ long-term preferences. If tax instruments are designed so as to create a temporal gap between when decisions regarding taxation are made and when tax liabilities are imposed, the impact of the tax liabilities may become less salient. In effect, taxes can be designed so as to facilitate present-oriented taxpayers exporting the tax consequences of their current decisions to their future selves. In regard to market salience, the time-inconsistency framework offers an alternative explanation for spotlighting behavior. Since most of the major empirical studies of spotlighting involved a temporal gap between when the tax liabilities were assessed and when the market decisions were made, observed spotlighting behavior could be a result of taxpayers’ hyperbolically discounting their future tax liabilities. In contrast, the time-inconsistency framework on its own probably does not explain ironing behavior; the difficulty in assessing non-linear price schedules probably does not result from temporal gaps. 76 With respect to political salience, the time-inconsistency framework offers clear support for the deficit-financing hypothesis. The deficit-financing hypothesis predicts that taxpayers tend to discount the future tax liabilities that result from accrued debt. If taxpayers engage in hyperbolic discounting with respect to future tax liabilities, then deficit financing should reduce the political salience of taxation. The time-inconsistency framework on its own probably does not support the other political salience hypotheses, which do not function based on time delays. 77
75. Id. at 377-79. 76. Although time inconsistency on its own does not explain ironing behavior, time inconsistency may work in tandem with bounded rationality to jointly cause ironing behavior. A boundedly rational taxpayer may be tempted to use her average tax rates rather than her marginal tax rates in order to avoid expending the cognitive resources necessary to calculate marginal tax rates. If there is a temporal gap between when tax rates are calculated and when tax liabilities are imposed, then time inconsistency may exacerbate the temptation to avoid calculating marginal tax rates. For instance, taxpayers make market decisions that affect their income-tax liabilities throughout the year; many important income-tax-relevant decisions must be made by December 31st, but income-tax forms are not due until April 15th. If bounded rationality tempts taxpayers to make income-tax-relevant decisions based on their average tax rates, time inconsistency can exacerbate these temptations since the tax consequences will not be felt until after the decisions are made. 77. However, time inconsistency may magnify the effects of bounded rationality. If bounded rationality tempts taxpayers to focus on reference prices when making voting decisions, to avoid expending the cognitive resources needed to more accurately assess their tax liabilities, time inconsistency can increase these temptations to the extent that the fiscal consequences of voting decisions seem remote in time from the voting.
188
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
Determining whether a tax salience effect results from time inconsistency or from bounded rationality can be important because the two operative mechanisms may respond differently to limiting factors, such as the size of a tax liability. 78 As with bounded rationality, there are limits to the operation of time inconsistency. Taxpayers who realize that they are prone to hyperbolic-discounting behavior may take steps to prevent their future selves from making decisions at the expense of their even-more-distant-future selves. 79 Such taxpayers might go so far as to sign contracts with third parties to bind the taxpayers’ future behavior. 80 Or taxpayers may use cognitive mechanisms to restrict the present-focused desires of their future selves, in a sense forming contracts between the taxpayers’ selves at various points in time.81 We might hypothesize that the more frequent and important a time-inconsistency scenario becomes, the more likely it becomes that taxpayers will take steps to prevent their future selves from engaging in hyperbolic-discounting behavior. However, many of the mechanisms taxpayers can use to overcome time-inconsistent behavior require the taxpayers to know in advance that they are subject to time inconsistency.82 When tax salience effects result from time inconsistency, the limiting factor of whether taxpayers can learn from experience may rise to central importance.83 C. Framing Effects The third potential operative mechanism, framing effects, might be thought of as a catch-all category for biases that do not operate 78. See infra Part IV. 79. See Roland Bénabou & Jean Tirole, Self-Knowledge and Self-Regulation: An Economic Approach, in 1 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF ECONOMIC DECISIONS 137, 137 (Isabelle Brocas & Juan D. Carrillo eds., 2003) (describing research on a variety of tools individuals can use to overcome time-inconsistent behavior). 80. See Nava Ashraf, Dean Karlan & Wesley Yin, Tying Odysseus to the Mast: Evidence from a Commitment Savings Product in the Philippines, 121 Q.J. ECON. 635, 635-38 (2006) (describing research on financial products that enable consumers to limit the discretion of their future selves); Richard H. Thaler & Shlomo Benartzi, Save More Tomorrow™: Using Behavioral Economics to Increase Employee Saving, 112 J. POL. ECON. 164, 168-69 (Supp. 2004) (explaining that employer-sponsored automatic-enrollment savings plans have been “remarkably successful”). 81. See Jess Benhabib & Alberto Bisin, Modeling Internal Commitment Mechanisms and Self-Control: A Neuroeconomics Approach to Consumption-Saving Decisions, 52 GAMES & ECON. BEHAV. 460, 462 (2005) (describing a model based on research in cognitive neuroscience wherein individuals “have the ability to either invoke automatic processes that are susceptible to impulses or temptations, or alternative control processes which are immune to such temptations.”); see also Bénabou & Tirole, supra note 79. 82. See, e.g., Ashraf et al., supra note 80, at 636 (“If individuals with time-inconsistent preferences are sophisticated enough to realize it, we should observe them engaging in various forms of commitment (much like Odysseus tying himself to the mast to avoid the tempting song of the sirens).”). 83. See infra Part IV.B.
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
189
based on bounded rationality or time inconsistency. Looking back to our discussion of reference-price strategies under the boundedrationality paradigm, the hypothesis was that partitioning an aggregate price into a lower reference price plus a tax surcharge makes it more difficult for consumers to calculate aggregate prices and thus tempts the consumers to instead make judgments using a reference price that is lower than the aggregate price. Yet the empirical findings on reference pricing have also been analyzed using a framingeffects approach. To the extent that framing effects is the operative mechanism, consumers form initial judgments and expectations based on the reference price and then allow these initial judgments and expectations to influence their perceptions of the aggregate price—even when the consumers do later fully calculate the aggregate price. Several studies have found that reference-price strategies can bias value judgments even when consumers do calculate aggregate (post-tax) prices.84 Biases that operate through individuals making preliminary judgments based on incomplete information, and then allowing these preliminary judgments to color their final evaluations even when they later receive complete information, are often called “anchoring biases.” 85 Anchoring may function as an alternative operative mechanism for all of the hypotheses that can be explained by the boundedrationality form of reference pricing. Consider first the market salience hypothesis of spotlighting. If taxpayers anchor on the spotlighted reference price, even later showing the taxpayers their aggregate tax liabilities may not counteract the market salience effects of spotlighting. Similarly, if taxpayers first consider their historic average tax rates when making market decisions—following the ironing hypothesis—they may anchor on this reference price such that later exposure to marginal tax rates may not counteract the initial anchoring. Anchoring can likewise potentially explain all of the political salience hypotheses. If voters use their direct tax burdens or current tax burdens as reference-price proxies, then anchoring can produce political salience effects even if the voters are later exposed to their indirect or future tax burdens. Similarly, if voters use politicians’ votes as a form of reference-price proxy, anchoring may influence voting behavior even if the voters also note the impact on their tax burdens of the phenomena underlying the sticky-baselines hypotheses. Simi84. See, e.g., Gretchen B. Chapman & Eric J. Johnson, Anchoring, Activation, and the Construction of Values, 79 ORGANIZATIONAL BEHAV. & HUM. DECISION PROCESSES 115 (1999); Robin M. Hogarth & Hillel J. Einhorn, Order Effects in Belief Updating: The BeliefAdjustment Model, 24 COGNITIVE PSYCHOL. 1 (1992); Thomas Mussweiler & Fritz Strack, The Semantics of Anchoring, 86 ORGANIZATIONAL BEHAV. & HUM. DECISION PROCESSES 234 (2001); Morwitz et al., supra note 40, at 30-31. 85. See Hayashi et al., supra note 7, at 217.
190
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
larly, if the pennies-a-day strategy has an anchoring component, then the framing approach may support the notions that the political salience of taxation can be lowered by dividing an aggregate tax liability into a series of smaller payments collected over time or through the use of multiple smaller tax instruments in place of a single larger tax instrument. Withholding may also trigger anchoring responses by making it so that an aggregate tax liability is paid in small increments over time. Anchoring may thus provide support for the view that withholding reduces the political salience of taxation even when taxpayers are forced to later calculate their aggregate tax liabilities through annual income-tax filing. Consequently, anchoring can lead to the same behaviors as bounded rationality and may thus exacerbate the consequences of bounded rationality. But where anchoring plays a strong role, it may be far more difficult to restore tax salience. In the context of bounded rationality, forcing taxpayers to perform tax calculations should usually suffice to counteract salience effects.86 The anchoring phenomenon is potentially more robust. The notion underlying anchoring is that the judgments taxpayers make using incomplete information are not always updated even if complete information later becomes available. Anchoring can be thought of as an even more extreme consequence of limited cognitive resources than in the more standard bounded-rationality framework. Not only do taxpayers often forgo fully calculating their tax liabilities, but they also do not always update their prior views and understandings even when they later receive better information than that which was available when the initial views and understandings were forged. In addition to anchoring, another potentially important framingeffects bias is the “endowment effect,” well known to even casual readers of the behavioral economics literature. Under the standard endowment effect, individuals have been shown to assign more disutility to “losses” than utility to equivalent “gains.” 87 Whether a change in circumstances is coded as a loss or as the absence of a gain depends on the framing of the individual’s endowment. In regard to taxation, whether taxpayers perceive taxes as losses from their pre-tax endowments or as reduced gains from engaging in market transactions may determine whether the endowment effect comes into play.88
86. To counteract market salience, taxpayers should be forced to calculate aggregate tax prices. To counteract political salience, taxpayers should be forced to calculate the tax components of prices. See Gamage & Shanske, supra note 4, at 54-58. 87. See McCaffery & Baron, supra note 55, at 290; see also Edward J. McCaffery, Cognitive Theory and Tax, 41 UCLA L. REV. 1861, 1875 (1994). 88. See id.
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
191
Compare the political salience of the employer-paid and employeepaid portions of the payroll tax. The employer-paid portion of the payroll tax is taken out before workers are told their salaries and thus is likely coded as smaller gains from working. In contrast, the employee-paid portion of the payroll tax is presented with the employees first seeing pre-tax salary totals and then being shown how much the government takes out of the pre-tax salary. The employeepaid portion of the payroll tax is thus more likely to be coded as a loss. Income-tax payments may be even more likely to be coded as losses, as taxpayers are instructed to calculate their aggregate pretax incomes before being told that the government will take a portion of this income figure from them. 89 Hence, the endowment effect supports the indirect-taxes political salience hypothesis. 90 If voters view direct taxes as losses and indirect taxes as forgone gains, then the use of direct taxes may trigger the endowment effect as compared to indirect taxes, thereby making indirect taxes less politically salient than direct taxes. 91 A related form of the endowment effect—often labeled as the status-quo bias—may support the sticky-baselines political salience hypotheses. If voters understand the tax laws on the books to constitute the status quo and view politicians’ votes to change these laws as departures from the status quo, then any votes to raise taxes may be coded as losses, whereas the increased tax revenue generated by the phenomena underlying the sticky-baselines hypotheses may be viewed as the status quo. 92 The endowment effect may also play a role in regard to the withholding political salience hypothesis. If withheld income is not incorporated into taxpayers’ endowments, 89. Related to the endowment effect, the framing of tax design might also affect whether tax payments are viewed as mandatory extractions or as voluntary payments. Anecdotal evidence suggests that taxpayers are more averse to property taxes than to real estate transaction taxes. See Marika Cabral & Caroline Hoxby, The Hated Property Tax: Salience, Tax Rates, and Tax Revolts (Nat’l Bureau of Econ. Research, Working Paper No. 18514, 2012). The standard endowment effect may explain this result if taxpayers view property taxes as coming from their pre-tax endowments and real-estate-transaction taxes as being extra amounts paid to purchase property. Yet in addition to being averse to losses, individuals may also be more averse to mandatory extractions than to voluntary payments. If real-estate-transaction taxes are viewed as resulting from the taxpayer’s choice to purchase real estate, while property taxes are viewed as being unrelated to the taxpayer’s choices, then an aversion to mandatory extractions might come into play in addition to the endowment effect. Of course, property taxes also result from the choice to purchase property, but taxpayers may view this connection as more tenuous. 90. McCaffery & Baron, supra note 55, at 290. 91. Id. More speculatively, the endowment effect could also lead voters to discount future tax liabilities—following the deficit-financing political salience hypothesis—if current taxes are viewed as losses and future taxes as forgone gains. 92. For instance, see the discussion of state-level revenue volatility in David Gamage, Preventing State Budget Crises: Managing the Fiscal Volatility Problem, 98 CALIF. L. REV. 749, 799-801 (2010).
192
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
then taxpayers may be more politically averse to paying additional taxes at the end of the year than to having amounts withheld regularly from their paychecks. The existence and importance of framing effects has been well demonstrated. The framing-effects approach is undoubtedly important for understanding tax salience. Unfortunately, the implications of framing effects are harder to predict than are the implications of bounded rationality or time inconsistency. Most crucially, it is more difficult to predict when individuals are likely to overcome the impact of framing effects. Research suggests that the market salience of at least some framing effects can be overcome through the use of agents. 93 Taxpayers increasingly use accountants or software to guide them through difficult income-tax decisions. 94 Wealthier taxpayers may rely on lawyers and financial advisers to assist with decisionmaking, particularly when large tax liabilities are at stake.95 Books and websites provide tools to assist even moderate-income taxpayers with weighing the tax and non-tax factors involved in making large purchases, such as for housing and automobiles. 96 Similarly, with regard to political salience, voters’ opinions about taxation may depend more on the information they receive from experts and from other trusted sources than from their direct experience with the tax system. 97 Political experts 93. See, e.g., Jennifer Arlen, Matthew Spitzer & Eric Talley, Endowment Effects Within Corporate Agency Relationships, 31 J. LEGAL STUD. 1 (2002) (finding that subjects situated in agency relationships do not exhibit a significant endowment effect); John A. List, Does Market Experience Eliminate Market Anomalies?, 118 Q.J. ECON. 41 (2003) (finding that market experience eliminates the endowment effect). 94. Marsha Blumenthal & Charles Christian, Tax Preparers, in THE CRISIS IN TAX ADMINISTRATION 201, 201-02 (Henry J. Aaron & Joel Slemrod eds., 2004); Lawrence Zelenak, Essay, Complex Tax Legislation in the TurboTax Era, 1 COLUM. J. TAX L. 91, 9495 (2010). 95. See Blumenthal & Christian, supra note 94, at 203-04 (describing factors correlated with taxpayers being more likely to hire tax practitioners). 96. See, e.g., Auto Loan Application, DRIVERS LANE, http://www.driverslane.com/ calculators/sales-tax-calc.htm (last visited Jan. 30, 2014); Home Purchase Calculator, PLANNING TIPS, http://www.planningtips.com/cgi-bin/howmuch.pl (last visited Jan. 30, 2014); Tax, Title, Tags, and Fees Calculator, CARMAX, http://www.carmax.com/enUS/taxtitle-tags-fees-calculator/default.html (last visited Jan. 30, 2014); TurboTax AnswerXchange – For Tax Years 2008-2010 Only: Claiming the First-Time Homebuyer Tax Credit, TURBOTAX, http://turbotax.intuit.com/support/kb/tax-content/tax-tips/6360.html (last visited Jan. 30, 2014); Used Vehicle Tax Calculator, DMV.ORG, http://search.dmv.org/dmv/usedvehicle-tax-calculator (last visited Jan. 30, 2014). 97. For instance, at the state level, the Tax Foundation’s “state business tax climate index” and “tax freedom day” rankings have had enormous influence. See State Tax and http://taxfoundation.org/tax-topics/state-tax-andSpending Policy, TAX FOUNDATION, spending-policy (last visited Jan. 30, 2014). For criticisms of the methodologies underlying these rankings, see NICHOLAS JOHNSON, IRIS J. LAV & JOSEPH LLOBRERA, CTR. ON BUDGET & POLICY PRIORITIES, TAX FOUNDATION ESTIMATES OF STATE AND LOCAL TAX BURDENS ARE NOT RELIABLE (2006), available at http://www.cbpp.org/cms/?fa=view&id=133.
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
193
and other opinion leaders may function much like agents and software do for market salience—allowing taxpayers to make more accurate voting decisions about taxation even when the taxpayers’ direct observations about taxation are biased due to framing effects. Agents and opinion leaders may also assist taxpayers in overcoming the impact of bounded rationality and time inconsistency. Yet agents and opinion leaders are likely to be even more crucial to framing effects, as it is less clear whether taxpayers can overcome framing effects without the use of agents. If taxpayers become aware that they are potentially susceptible to framing effects, and if they view the market or political decision as important enough, taxpayers may turn to agents or opinion leaders in order to overcome their impact. IV. LIMITING FACTORS The existing literature is far from clear about the factors affecting tax salience or the circumstances in which these factors are likely to come into play. I have tried to clarify the literature by discussing three potential operative mechanisms for tax salience in order to provide a foundation for discussing the normative implications of tax salience and for generating hypotheses to be tested by future empirical work. Yet it is important to emphasize that there are limits to these operative mechanisms. I will thus discuss three key potentially limiting factors, beginning with the size of the tax liability in question. A. Size of the Tax Liability The first limiting factor for tax salience that I will discuss is the size of a tax liability. How the size of a tax liability operates is most straightforward under a bounded-rationality framework, wherein increasing the size of a tax liability should generally increase taxpayers’ incentives to calculate the tax liability accurately. The boundedrationality framework imagines taxpayers performing implicit costbenefit analyses when deciding whether to expend the required cognitive resources. All else being equal, then, the more money at stake in calculating a tax liability, the more incentive taxpayers have to do so accurately. 98 Of course, all else is not always equal. The impact of the size of a tax liability depends on the opportunity cost of the taxpayer’s cognitive resources. The more a taxpayer has to give up in order to assess a tax liability accurately, the less likely the taxpayer will be to perform the calculations. Moreover, with regard to political salience, 98. Hence, levying smaller taxes across a wide variety of transactions (as in retail sales taxes) may create less incentive for taxpayers to calculate their aggregate tax burden accurately than would levying a larger tax on a fewer number of transactions (as in excise taxes on luxury goods or real-estate-transaction taxes). See supra Part III.A.
194
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
taxpayers arguably have little at stake in making accurate voting decisions. 99 Indeed, there is a large literature questioning why it is that individuals even bother to vote at all.100 Many have argued that individuals typically vote based on emotions and uninformed intuitions, rather than expending effort to process the information needed to vote rationally. 101 Yet regardless of whether voters process information based on logic or intuition, there is substantial evidence that voter opinions do respond to changes in the size of tax burdens. 102 The larger the size of a tax liability, the more information taxpayers are likely to receive about the tax instrument in question, whether the information comes from direct experience, from political-opinion leaders, or from the media. Even if voter judgments are largely emotional and intuitive, available evidence still suggests that voters are generally more averse to large tax liabilities then to small ones. 103 The impact of the size of a tax liability is less straightforward under a time-inconsistency framework. If taxpayers realize in advance that they are subject to time inconsistency, taxpayers may take steps (either concrete or cognitive) to limit the discretion of their future selves. 104 The size of a tax liability might then affect tax salience under a time-inconsistency framework much as it does under a bounded-rationality framework. The larger the size of a tax liability, the more incentive taxpayers would have to limit the discretion of their future selves. However, if taxpayers do not realize in advance that they are subject to time inconsistency, they may be unable to limit their future selves, and the relative size of a tax liability may have no effect on tax salience or may even increase the impact of tax salience. 105 It is hardest to predict how the size of a tax liability functions under the framing-effects paradigm. The literature has yet to develop a sufficiently deep understanding of how framing effects operate for us 99. See, e.g., BRYAN CAPLAN, THE MYTH OF THE RATIONAL VOTER: WHY DEMOCRACIES CHOOSE BAD POLICIES (2007). 100. See, e.g., GEOFFREY BRENNAN & LOREN LOMASKY, DEMOCRACY AND DECISION: THE PURE THEORY OF ELECTORAL PREFERENCE (1993). 101. Id. 102. ANDREA CAMPBELL, HOW AMERICANS THINK ABOUT TAXES: PUBLIC OPINION AND THE AMERICAN FISCAL STATE (forthcoming) (manuscript at 4-5) (on file with author). 103. Id. 104. See supra notes 79-82 and accompanying text. 105. The larger a tax liability, the more a present-self-focused taxpayer can gain by exporting tax consequences to the taxpayer’s future selves and the more tempting it may be for a taxpayer to succumb to self-control problems. Also, optimism biases may have greater impact if taxpayers mispredict that they will be in a better position to deal with tax liabilities in the future. Hence, when taxpayers cannot limit the discretion of their future selves, increasing the size of a tax liability can potentially exacerbate time-inconsistency problems.
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
195
to assess confidently predictions about the relationship between framing effects and the size of a tax liability. Moreover, since this Essay uses the term “framing effects” as a catch-all category for biases that do not operate through bounded rationality or time inconsistency, different forms of framing effects may exhibit varied responses to the size of a tax liability. Nevertheless, I expect that framing effects respond to the size of a tax liability much as does time inconsistency. When taxpayers realize in advance that they are subject to framing effects, they may take steps to counteract them. 106 If a tax liability becomes large enough, taxpayers may turn to agents or other thirdparty assistance in order to incorporate tax information into their decisionmaking more accurately. Ultimately, how the size of a tax liability affects tax salience is highly interrelated with the extent to which taxpayers learn from experience with their tax environments. This is particularly true under the time-inconsistency and framing-effects paradigms, where taxpayers may be unable to de-bias themselves unless they know in advance that they are likely to make sub-optimal tax decisions. I will thus proceed next to discuss the limiting factor of learning from experience. B. Learning from Experience Even when taxpayers cannot accurately assess a tax instrument directly, taxpayers may still note the connections between taxrelevant decisions and the tax consequences following those decisions.107 Through repeated exposure to the tax consequences of decisions, taxpayers may develop a rough sense of what affects their expected future tax liabilities, even without understanding the tax-law mechanics of how these liabilities are calculated. In addition to learning from their own experiences, taxpayers may learn from the tax experiences of their friends, families, and acquaintances, or from stories in the media. 108 In regard to political salience, taxpayers may learn by noting the consequences of tax-policy choices across different nations, states, or time periods. 109 Taxpayers can also learn about 106. See supra notes 93-97 and accompanying text. 107. See, e.g., Oren Bar-Gill & Franco Ferrari, Informing Consumers About Themselves, 3 ERASMUS L. REV. 93, 97-98 (2010) (arguing that seller interpretations of consumer mistakes exacerbates welfare costs associated with such mistakes); Alexander L. Brown, Zhikang Eric Chua & Colin F. Camerer, Learning and Visceral Temptation in Dynamic Saving Experiments, 124 Q.J. ECON. 197, 198 (2009) (explaining experimental results wherein subjects at first saved too little, but then learned to save near optimally after social learning). 108. One need only glance at any major newspaper either in December (before the close of the tax year) or in early April (before the April 15th income-tax filing date) to be bombarded by tax advice and discussions of the political impact of various tax provisions. 109. For instance, Americans who travel to Europe may note the higher prices Europe-
196
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
taxation from experts or from other political actors. The impact of tax design on voting behavior may largely occur through a process whereby tax design influences the views of key opinion leaders who then preach to the larger population. Hence, the extent to which a tax environment is conducive to taxpayer learning is a key factor in the operation of both market and political salience. Liebman and Zeckhauser outline several conditions relevant for whether individuals are likely to learn from experience, the most notable of which are: “delayed payoffs,” “bundled consumption,” and “false signals.” 110 Delayed payoffs refer to when the tax consequences of a decision are not felt until a long time period after the decision is made. 111 It becomes more difficult to learn from the consequences of a taxrelevant decision when those consequences do not occur for a long time period, both because more time will have elapsed before any potential learning can take place and because the decision is likely to become less salient over time, thus weakening the perceived connection between the decision and its consequences. 112 For example, there is a large literature analyzing how taxpayers respond to tax incentives for retirement savings.113 Because most taxpayers only retire once, well after their peak earning years, taxpayers have little opportunity to learn from observing the consequences of their earlier retirement-savings decisions. Taxpayers are thus far less likely to learn about the impact of taxes on their retirement decisions than on their everyday work and consumption decisions. Bundled consumption refers to when the consequences of one decision are intermingled with the consequences of other decisions.114 The ans pay for comparable goods and learn that these price differences are (at least partially) due to European value added taxes (VATs). 110. Jeffrey B. Liebman & Richard J. Zeckhauser, Schmeduling 5-6 (Oct. 2004) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://www.hks.harvard.edu/jeffreyliebman/ schmeduling.pdf. In addition to the factors discussed in this Essay, Liebman and Zeckhauser also analyze the additional factors of “heterogeneity in offered schedules,” “obscure pricing units,” “nonstationary economic environment,” and “frequent revisions of schedules.” Id. at 4-5. There are, of course, many other categorization schemas in the literature for factors affecting learning from experience. See, e.g., Bar-Gill & Ferrari, supra note 107, at 97 n.11 (“Learning from one’s mistakes relies on timely, clear and painful feedback . . . .”); Colin F. Camerer, Comment on Noll and Krier, “Some Implications of Cognitive Psychology for Risk Regulation,” 19 J. LEGAL STUD. 791, 794 (1990) (“Studies show that learning is difficult unless feedback is clear, frequent, and quick.”). 111. Liebman & Zeckhauser, supra note 110, at 5. 112. This condition is related to how temporal gaps can induce bounded rationality by making it more difficult to predict the tax consequences of a decision. But as a factor affecting taxpayer learning from experience, delayed payoffs operates ex post rather than ex ante (affecting after-the-fact learning rather than before-the-fact calculations). 113. See Olivia Mitchell & Stephen Utkus, Lessons from Behavioral Finance for Retirement Plan Design 35 (Pension Research Council, Working Paper No. 2003-6, 2003). 114. Liebman & Zeckhauser, supra note 110, at 5.
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
197
more difficult it becomes to identify which of many tax-related choices caused a particular outcome, the harder it becomes to learn about the connections between choices and outcomes. For example, the income-tax benefit produced by making a charitable contribution depends on how much the taxpayer claims for other itemized deductions. If a taxpayer claims different amounts in itemized deductions across different tax years, it may become difficult to learn from experience how much income-tax benefit is received by making a charitable contribution. Finally, the condition of false signals refers to when taxpayers receive potentially misleading information following a tax-relevant decision.115 When economic circumstances change over time, taxpayers may incorrectly associate tax decisions with outcomes caused by external events. Likewise, taxpayers who have idiosyncratic tax profiles may learn incorrect lessons from their friends, acquaintances, or the media. For instance, learning about deficit financing may be obscured by the tendency for deficits to rise during recessions and shrink during periods of economic growth. When deficit-financed tax cuts (or spending hikes) are made during economic downturns, voters may see deficits shrink as the economy recovers and thus conclude that the tax cuts (or spending hikes) did not negatively affect the governments’ debt levels. On their own, the conditions of delayed payoffs, bundled consumption, and false signals are neither necessary nor sufficient for taxpayer learning. My discussion of these conditions is aimed at outlining a few important considerations for whether learning from experience is likely, but this discussion is by no means exhaustive. Nevertheless, when conditions are conducive to learning, and when the size of a tax liability becomes large enough, I expect taxpayer learning to at least partially counteract the effects of both market and political salience. Indeed, the ironing hypothesis for market salience is based on the notion that taxpayers learn from their experience with tax rate schedules but then develop an imperfect ability to predict future consequences (as non-linear pricing schedules cause marginal rates to differ from average rates). Any discussion of tax salience that does not evaluate the possibility of taxpayer learning is unlikely to yield useful predictions for real-world taxpayer behavior. Taxpayer learning is particularly important for understanding tax salience under the time-inconsistency and framing-effects models. The existing literature has not fully determined the extent to which taxpayers can de-bias themselves from the consequences of time inconsistency or framing effects. To the extent taxpayers can de-bias themselves directly, the likelihood of taxpayer learning should work 115. Id. at 5-6.
198
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
together with the size of the tax liability to increase taxpayers’ incentives for de-biasing.116 But even when taxpayers cannot de-bias themselves directly, they may turn to agents, third-party tools, or market mechanisms to improve their tax decisionmaking. The likelihood of taxpayer learning and the size of a tax liability should thus work together to increase taxpayers’ motivations for de-biasing, regardless of whether taxpayers can de-bias themselves directly or only through the use of third-party assistance.117 Might some instances of framing effects be immune to de-biasing even through the use of third-party tools and agents? If so, tax-design techniques drawing on these framing effects could be sufficiently robust so as to be insurmountable even were governments to engage in massive use of these techniques under conditions where taxpayers could easily learn from experience. The existing literature does not rule out this possibility, yet I am skeptical. Framing effects function through how prices are displayed. I see no reason why agents or third-party tools could not train taxpayers to perceive tax prices using alternative frames. Reframing techniques may not fully counteract framing effects, but reframing techniques should enable taxpayers to perceive at least a portion of the costs of taxation. 118 And perceiving even a portion of these costs should affect taxpayer behavior for sufficiently large tax liabilities. Consequently, my intuition suggests that the potential for governments to employ low-salience tax designs depends largely on whether conditions are conducive to taxpayer learning. Where conditions are not conducive to learning, governments may have wide discretion to manipulate both forms of tax salience. Deficit financing is perhaps the most obvious example. Learning about deficit financing is hindered by delayed payoffs, bundled consumption, and false signals. 119 As such, taxpayers may not learn to incorporate the effects of deficit financing into their market or political decisions, even if governments engage in massive use of deficit financing. 120 116. The easier it is for taxpayers to learn from experience, the less costly de-biasing is likely to be. 117. When faced with important decisions with large consequences, taxpayers should often be more likely to take the time and incur the costs of seeking expert advice or otherwise acting so as to counteract salience effects. 118. For instance, anchoring biases function through taxpayers under-adjusting to new information. As under-adjustment does not imply non-adjustment, new information still partially improves taxpayers’ understandings of tax prices. 119. The negative effects of unsustainable deficit financing are not felt until long after the initial use of deficit financing; the impacts of deficit financing are intermingled with numerous other economic policy choices and with the effects of the political dynamics that first led to the deficit financing. Also, deficit financing may produce false signals when the impact of deficit financing is entangled with the effects of the economic cycle. 120. Whether bond markets can be fooled as easily as voters is another question.
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
199
In contrast, I expect that governments are more limited in their ability to reduce market salience through the use of retail sales taxes or to reduce political salience through the use of indirect taxes. If sales-tax rates were made high enough, I expect that consumers would take greater note of the additional sales-tax charges added at store registers. And evidence from comparing voter opinions across time periods and jurisdictions supports our expectation that increasing the use of indirect taxes heightens voter attention to these taxes. 121 None of this is to suggest that governments cannot reduce tax salience when the environment is conducive to taxpayer learning or that governments can completely reduce tax salience when the environment is not conducive to learning. The impact of taxpayer learning is a matter of degrees, not absolutes. I have argued that both the size of a tax liability and the conduciveness of an environment to taxpayer learning tend to inhibit the effectiveness of tax-design techniques aimed at reducing market or political salience. However, the magnitudes of these effects remain unanswered empirical questions. C. Aversion to Being Manipulated Further underscoring the complexity of how tax salience plays out in the real world, there is ample evidence from the consumer behavior literature that consumers react negatively if they perceive themselves as being manipulated. For instance, field studies have shown that the impact of price-presentation techniques can disappear if consumers become skeptical of vendors’ intentions or come to believe that vendors are using misleading price-presentation strategies.122 More generally, the empirical evidence suggests that moderate use of techniques for reducing price salience is often more effective than high use—as high use can lead to consumer backlash.123 As applied to tax salience, these findings imply that taxpayers’ perceptions of being manipulated place an additional limiting factor on techniques for reducing both the market and political salience of taxation. If taxpayers come to believe that the government is actively trying to reduce the market salience of taxes, the taxpayers may begin to look through devices for reducing market salience or even to anticipate non-salient (“hidden”) taxes where none are present. If 121. CAMPBELL, supra note 102. 122. Robert M. Schindler, Maureen Morrin & Nada Nasr Bechwati, Shipping Charges and Shipping-Charge Skepticism: Implications for Direct Marketers’ Pricing Formats, 19 J. INTERACTIVE MARKETING 41, 44-45 (2005); Morwitz et al., supra note 40, at 20. 123. Yih Hwai Lee & Cheng Yuen Han, Partitioned Pricing in Advertising: Effects on Brand and Retailer Attitudes, 13 MARKETING LETTERS 27, 28-29 (2002); Shibin Sheng, Yeqing Bao & Yue Pan, Partitioning or Bundling? Perceived Fairness of the Surcharge Makes a Difference, 24 PSYCHOL. & MARKETING 1025, 1039 (2007); Morwitz et al., supra note 40, at 26-27.
200
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
taxpayers perceive the government as attempting to reduce the political salience of taxation, taxpayers may become more resistant to supporting taxes (or to supporting politicians who favor taxes) in their voting decisions. 124 Moreover, taxpayers’ aversion to being manipulated through market-salience techniques can affect the taxpayers’ political decisionmaking, and vice versa. If taxpayers become hostile toward the governments’ attempts to reduce the market salience of taxation, they may react against all taxes in their voting decisions. Conversely, if taxpayers becomes angry about the government’s attempts to reduce the political salience of taxation, they may become more tax-averse (or less tax-accepting) in their market behavior. 125 The empirical literature on aversion to being manipulated is almost entirely focused on how consumers respond to pricepresentation techniques as employed by private-sector firms. Yet there is reason to suspect that aversion to being manipulated plays at least as strong a role with respect to tax salience. The media generally covers politics more attentively than it does the behavior of private-sector firms, and scandalous-seeming political behavior tends to make for good copy. This is not meant to suggest that governments are unable to employ techniques for reducing tax salience. Governments clearly do not design taxes to be as salient as possible.126 However, as with private-sector firms, governments may find that moderate attempts to reduce tax salience are more effective than aggressive attempts, as the aggressive attempts may backfire. Complicating matters, taxpayers’ aversion to being manipulated may be more a function of the perceived intent behind government actions rather than a direct function of the design of the tax system. Hence, taxpayers’ aversion to being manipulated does not necessarily play out differently depending on which of the three operative mechanisms is dominant. Whether taxpayers perceive themselves as being manipulated works somewhat independently of the mechanism by which taxpayers are (or are not) manipulated. Indeed, taxpayers’ hostility may depend as much on how the media reports on taxdesign techniques as on the nature of the techniques themselves. I therefore expect that governments have much greater scope for re124. For an example of this phenomenon, see Adam Nagourney & David M. Herszenhorn, Republicans Call Health Legislation a Tax Increase, N.Y. TIMES (Oct. 2, 2009), www.nytimes.com/2009/10/02/health/policy/02tax.html (describing Republican attacks on Obama’s health care reform proposal based on allegations that the proposal contains “hidden” tax increases). 125. If hostility toward the use of political salience techniques engenders tax-averse preferences, taxpayers may be less likely to engage in taxable transactions or more likely to underreport their income or engage in other forms of tax evasion. For a discussion of the connection between tax salience and tax-averse preferences, see Gamage & Shanske, supra note 4, at 50. 126. See Krishna & Slemrod, supra note 38.
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
201
ducing tax salience when the techniques employed for doing so are primarily directed toward other purposes. For instance, imagine what might happen were a future U.S. President to explicitly support an expansion of the Alternative Minimum Tax (AMT) on the grounds that the effective tax-rate hikes caused by expanding the AMT would be less salient to both voters and market participants than would raising income-tax rates directly. It is hard to imagine Congress approving an AMT expansion openly supported as a means of making the income tax less salient. But even if the expansion could be passed into law, we might expect that taxpayers’ aversion to being manipulated would counteract much (if not all) of the salience-reducing effects of the AMT expansion. 127 Conversely, imagine a future U.S. President supporting an AMT expansion with the stated goal of preventing high-income taxpayers from negating most of their tax liabilities through aggressive exploitation of tax credits and deductions.128 The President’s political opponents might claim that the true goal of the proposed AMT expansion was to reduce tax salience. But if taxpayers found the President’s position credible—believing that the AMT expansion was actually intended to combat aggressive tax planning—the expansion would be far less likely to trigger taxpayers’ aversion to being manipulated. All else being equal, attempts to reduce tax salience are more likely to be successful when the salience-reducing features of a tax reform are plausibly viewed as a side effect of a reform aimed at other purposes, rather than as the primary goal of the reform. Taxpayers’ aversion to being manipulated should generally work in concert with the other limiting factors—the size of a tax liability and learning from experience. After all, taxpayers can only react against the use of salience-reducing techniques if they know that these techniques are being employed. The larger the size of a tax liability, the more likely that taxpayers will take note of the tax liability and become averse to any salience-reducing techniques used to obscure it. Similarly, the easier it is for taxpayers to learn about a salience-reducing technique through experience, the more likely that taxpayers will perceive themselves as being manipulated. Particularly when tax liabilities are large and conditions are conducive to 127. Taxpayers’ aversion to being manipulated could more than counteract the salience-reducing effects. If taxpayers’ preferences became sufficiently more tax-averse, the AMT expansion could increase the market distortions caused by taxation. Similarly, if taxpayers became more distrustful of taxes in their role as voters, the AMT expansion might increase political resistance to taxation. 128. AMT has generally been supported on these grounds. See COMM. ON FIN., TAX EQUITY AND FISCAL RESPONSIBILITY ACT OF 1982, S. REP. NO. 97-494, at 108 (1982) (“The committee has amended the present minimum tax provisions applying to individuals with one overriding objective: no taxpayer with substantial economic income should be able to avoid all tax liability by using exclusions, deductions and credits.”).
202
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
learning, governments may thus find that moderate use of techniques for reducing tax salience are more effective than high use. V. CONCLUSION I have argued in this Essay (building on my prior article with Darien Shanske) that the existing tax salience literature is not yet sufficiently developed to offer concrete tax policy prescriptions. However, the literature on tax salience is advancing rapidly. I am thus hopeful that the tax salience literature will be made policy-ready before too long. Despite my conclusions about the state of the existing literature, I remain optimistic that the study of tax salience will prove to be one of the most important paths through which future scholarly advances can guide the improvement of tax policy. Importantly, that we currently lack the information needed to predict with confidence the circumstances in which tax salience effects are likely to manifest does not imply that normative scholars should simply ignore the possibility of tax salience effects. Normative prescriptions that hold only in the absence of tax salience effects are just as likely to prove erroneous as are prescriptions that are based on the assumption that tax salience effects will strongly manifest despite the possibility of limiting factors.129 The available evidence suggests that tax salience effects are real and that these effects are potentially important in at least some policy contexts. Instead, humility is the appropriate reaction to the nascent state of the tax salience literature. There is currently little that scholars can say with confidence about whether and when tax salience effects are likely to be important. Hopefully, this Essay’s analysis of potential operative mechanisms and limiting factors will aid in the development of a more refined literature on tax salience—a literature that may one day be capable of offering concrete policy recommendations. Moreover, although this Essay has focused on evaluating the circumstances under which tax salience effects are likely to manifest, this Essay’s analysis may also aid the development of the literature on the normative implications of tax salience. When taxpayers’ expressed preferences are manipu129. For instance, a number of influential arguments based on optimal tax theory assume that taxpayers will make labor decisions based on fully factoring in the price implications of excise taxes, capital-income taxes, and other tax and regulatory burdens that reduce the purchasing power of the money that taxpayers earn. Yet as Christine Jolls has speculated, it seems plausible to me that in many contexts these price effects may be significantly less salient for these decisions than are labor-income taxes. For further discussion, see Christine Jolls, Behavioral Economics Analysis of Redistributive Legal Rules, 51 VAND. L. REV. 1653, 1669-73 (1998); David Gamage, On Double-Distortion Arguments, Distribution Policy, and the Optimal Choice of Tax Instruments II.B.4 (Sept. 25, 2013) (unpublished manuscript) (on file with the author).
2013]
TAX SALIENCE SCHOLARSHIP
203
lable through salience effects, the question arises as to what are taxpayers’ “true preferences”—which of the multiple possible sets of expressed preferences should be most respected? These questions are especially important with respect to political salience, under the thought that democratic institutions should be designed so as to respect voters’ desires. But these questions also arise with respect to market salience, to the extent that policies are designed based on divergences between taxpayers’ market decisions and taxpayers’ preferences regarding the consequences of their market decisions. For these sorts of questions, assessing the normative implications of salience effects requires understanding the operative mechanisms underlying them. In any case, it is my hope that by the bicentennial anniversary of the income tax, 130 scholarly literature building on the currently nascent study of tax salience will have dramatically improved our understanding of how taxpayers respond to taxation. Models based on perfect economic rationality have generated powerful insights. But there can be little doubt that taxpayer behavior often departs from the assumption of perfect economic rationality. Ultimately, the study of tax salience must be a key part of our examination of taxpayer behavior. Even if we do not yet have the tools to answer fully questions related to tax salience, the importance of these questions demands continued scholarly attention.
130. Of course, this is assuming that the income tax survives for another hundred years. But even if the U.S. income tax no longer exists—or even if the U.S. no longer exists—we can reasonably expect that taxation will probably still exist one hundred years from now and that it will thus remain important to understand taxpayer behavior.
204
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:173
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION: AN AGENDA STEVE R. JOHNSON * I. INTRODUCTION.................................................................................................. II. CRITERIA FOR ASSESSING REFORMS ................................................................. A. Sources of Criteria ..................................................................................... B. Shaping Developments............................................................................... 1. Creation and Expansion of Refund Remedies ..................................... 2. The Anti-Injunction Act and Its Exceptions......................................... 3. Creation of Prepayment Remedies ....................................................... 4. Flora Full Payment Rule ..................................................................... 5. Powell and IRS Information Gathering .............................................. 6. Federal Tax Lien Act ............................................................................ 7. Shapiro, Laing, and Jeopardy Assessment Review.............................. 8. TEFRA Partnership Audit/Litigation Procedures .............................. 9. Brockamp and Equitable Tolling ........................................................ 10. IRS Restructuring and Reform Act...................................................... 11. Ballard and Tax Court Process ............................................................ 12. Administrative Law in Tax.................................................................. C. Criteria....................................................................................................... III. REFORMS AS TO AVAILABLE COURTS ................................................................. A. Tax Court Jurisdiction .............................................................................. 1. Historical Growth of Tax Court Jurisdiction ...................................... 2. Areas Where the Tax Court Lacks Jurisdiction ................................... 3. Where to Expand Tax Court Jurisdiction and Where Not to Expand ................................................................................................ B. National Court of Tax Appeals .................................................................. C. Court of Federal Claims Jurisdiction ........................................................ 1. History.................................................................................................. 2. Reasons for Change .............................................................................. IV. REFORMS AS TO AVAILABLE FORMS OF ACTION................................................. A. TEFRA Rules ............................................................................................. 1. Unnecessary ......................................................................................... 2. Harmful ............................................................................................... B. Judicial Review of CDP Determinations ................................................... V. REFORM AS TO PREREQUISITE TO SUIT ............................................................. A. Flora “Full Payment” Rule......................................................................... B. Changes Not Proposed ............................................................................... VI. CONCLUSION .....................................................................................................
205 208 208 211 212 215 217 219 222 226 229 231 233 235 237 240 244 246 247 247 249 249 252 254 254 256 258 258 259 261 264 267 267 271 272
I. INTRODUCTION King Vertigorn, it is said, wished to build a castle to defend Britain against invaders. Each day, his mason raised and set the stones. Each night, however, the earth would rumble, bringing the work * University Professor of Law, Florida State University College of Law. I thank participants in the Symposium—particularly Professor Leandra Lederman, the primary commentator on this Article at the Symposium—for their criticisms, observations, and encouragement. I also thank Mary McCormick of the Florida State University College of Law Research Center for research assistance.
206
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
crashing to the ground. Vexed, Vertigorn asked Merlin for an explanation. Merlin’s mystical divination revealed that, in a cavern far below the surface, there resided two foes, a red dragon and a white dragon. In their perpetual struggle for dominance, first one dragon then the other would gain temporary ascendancy. Their jostling unsettled the ground, rendering all construction temporary. In federal tax procedure, the red dragon and the white dragon are facilitation of revenue collection and fairness to taxpayers. Numerous times during the first century of the modern federal income tax, the courts have noted the centrality of the first value: “taxes are the lifeblood of government, and their prompt and certain availability an imperious need.” 1 But, were that the only value, we could return to brutal efficiency of the proscription system. We have refrained from doing so because our limited government traditions demand that citizens’ claims to due process under the law be taken seriously. Thus, tax administration in the United States—before, during, and (no doubt) after the income tax’s first one hundred years—has involved and will involve the balancing of the revenue facilitation and fairness protection imperatives. 2 Just as the power balance between the red and white dragons fluctuated, so have the relative weights accorded the two tax imperatives. During times of international or domestic crisis, we have looked to Government to save us from threats. This demands opening wider the spigot of fiscal flows, so the first tax value receives greater weight. During more placid times, menace recedes, causing the virtues of the second value to appear more attractive. In short, the pendulum swings between emphasis on revenue maximization and taxpayer protection. This affects legislative, regulatory, and judicial actions; it implicates not just substantive rules of tax liability and tax rates but also styles of statutory interpretation 3 and the rules and devices of tax procedure. 1. Bull v. United States, 295 U.S. 247, 259 (1935); see also United States v. Dalm, 494 U.S. 596, 604 (1990); United States v. Nat’l Bank of Commerce, 472 U.S. 713, 733 (1985); United States v. Kimbell Foods, Inc., 440 U.S. 715, 734 (1979). 2. The tension between the values has been evident since the founding of the American Republic. Alexander Hamilton, our first Secretary of the Treasury, proposed a general ad valorem duty on all imports. “Immediate opposition in the Congress was rooted in a fear of the alleged centralizing tendencies involved in creating a large force of collectors on the Federal level.” INTERNAL REVENUE SERVICE, U.S. TREASURY DEP’T, PUB. NO. 447, THE UNITED STATES TAX SYSTEM: A BRIEF HISTORY 4 (1960). One of the opponents described the proposal as the “horror of all free States,” one that was “hostile to the liberties of the people,” and which would “convulse the government; let loose a swarm of harpies, who, under the domination of the revenue officers, will range the country prying into every man’s house and affairs, and, like the Macedonian phalanx, bear down all before them.” Id. 3. This is reflected in the assertion, disappearance, and occasional reappearance in federal tax jurisprudence of a canon under which tax statutes were construed strictly against the Government and in favor of taxpayers. See, e.g., Gould v. Gould, 245 U.S. 151,
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
207
This Article is about the procedural rules. Specifically, it considers the mechanisms by which disputes as to federal tax liabilities are resolved. The Article identifies an agenda for reforming federal tax litigation. 4 Fully developing the justifications for and the particulars of the proposed changes necessarily is the work of more than one article. Thus, this Article sets the agenda, describing the core elements of the changes (and, in some cases, the reaffirmations) I propose. Subsequent articles will develop specific proposals in greater detail. Part II of this Article explores the criteria that should guide choices in this area. A fairly uncontroversial list of candidate criteria would include such things as decisional accuracy, efficiency, and actual and perceived equity. However, considerable controversy likely would exist, even among competent commentators, as to the relative weights that should be accorded the criteria, both generally and in application to particular situations. Hence, in Part II, I will not focus on the weightings that best comport with my personal constellation of values. Instead, Part II sketches key legislative, regulatory, and judicial events that have shaped our current tax procedure rules. By distilling these events, we can get a sense of the values that have actually driven the system. Parts III, IV, and V apply those values to features of the federal tax litigation system and thereby develop proposals. Specifically, Part III considers reforms as to the judicial fora that should be available for the resolution of federal tax controversies. It offers three principal recommendations: (1) the Tax Court should be given quasiplenary jurisdiction in civil tax matters (concurrent, not exclusive, 153 (1917) (“In case of doubt [statutes levying taxes] are construed most strongly against the Government, and in favor of the citizen.”). Gould cited authorities as far back as Justice Story’s opinion in United States v. Wigglesworth, 28 F. Cas. 595 (C.C.D. Mass. 1842). This canon was invoked in hundreds of federal cases in the 1800s and the first two decades of the 1900s, when limited government was the predominant electoral preference. It was largely replaced by pro-IRS canons (such as that I.R.C. § 61 is construed broadly, see Commissioner v. Glenshaw Glass Co., 348 U.S. 426, 429 (1955), and that tax deductions and exemptions are construed narrowly, see Commissioner v. Schleier, 515 U.S. 323, 328 (1995) (exclusions); INDOPCO, Inc. v. Commissioner, 503 U.S. 79, 84 (1992) (deductions)) during the 1930s through 1970s, when we looked to Washington to save us from the Great Depression, then Fascism, then Communism. Under the sway of the Reagan Revolution, the pro-taxpayer canon returned to the stage briefly in the 1980s and 1990s. See, e.g., United Dominion Inds., Inc. v. United States, 532 U.S. 822, 839 (Thomas, J., concurring); id. at 839 n.l (Stevens, J., dissenting). It has faded again since September 11, 2001. See Steve R. Johnson, Should Ambiguous Revenue Laws Be Interpreted in Favor of Taxpayers?, NEV. LAW., Apr. 2002, at 15-16. The canon retains greater potency in state and local tax litigation. See Steve R. Johnson, Pro-Taxpayer Interpretation of State-Local Tax Laws, 51 ST. TAX NOTES 441 (2009). 4. The reforms implicate litigation of all federal taxes, not just the income tax. However, the income tax is the most frequently litigated of the types imposed by the federal government.
208
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
jurisdiction); (2) proposals to create a national court of tax appeals should continue to be rejected; and (3) the Court of Federal Claims should be divested of jurisdiction to hear tax cases. Part IV offers reforms as to the available forms of civil tax actions. It urges two reforms: (1) repeal of the bulk of the TEFRA unified partnership audit and litigation procedures, 5 and (2) reduction in the scope of, but not elimination of, judicial review of Collection Due Process decisions by the IRS Appeals Office. 6 Finally, Part V addresses prerequisites to suits. It proposes that the Flora full payment rule (that taxpayers must pay the full amount of liability determined by the IRS as a prerequisite to bringing a tax refund suit) be abolished. 7 II. CRITERIA FOR ASSESSING REFORMS Law reform proposals based on idiosyncratic values preferences are built on a foundation of quicksand. They are unlikely to gain traction initially and to sustain it over time. I hope to erect this reform agenda on a more solid footing. Thus, I will emphasize not my values but the values I perceive as embodied in and reflected by leading facets of the federal tax litigation system as it has developed. Below, I describe the sources that generate relevant criteria, identify key events in the evolution of the current system, and adduce from those developments the values on which the system is based. A. Sources of Criteria There are four principal sets of actors shaping norms governing the procedural rules of taxation: Congress, the courts, federal tax regulators (Main Treasury, 8 the IRS, and the Department of Justice), 9 and the communities of taxpayers, their representatives, and
5. See I.R.C. §§ 6221-6234. These provisions were enacted in their original form by the Tax Equity and Fiscal Responsibility Act of 1982 (“TEFRA”), Pub. L. No. 97-248, 96 Stat. 324 (1982). 6. See I.R.C. §§ 6320, 6330. 7. See Flora v. United States (Flora II), 362 U.S. 145 (1960), reaff’g Flora v. United States (Flora I), 357 U.S. 63 (1958). 8. The IRS is part of the Treasury Department. Unlike the IRS (which handles dayto-day tax administration and issues lower-level administrative guidance), other parts of Treasury are involved in taxation at a more general level. So called “Main Treasury” finalizes tax regulations, represents the Administration in tax legislation, negotiates tax treaties, and, through its Treasury Inspector General for Tax Administration, monitors performance by the IRS. 9. For discussion of the roles and responsibilities of these actors, see LEANDRA LEDERMAN & STEPHEN W. MAZZA, TAX CONTROVERSIES: PRACTICE AND PROCEDURE 1-29 (3d ed. 2009); DAVID M. RICHARDSON, JEROME BORISON & STEVE JOHNSON, CIVIL TAX PROCEDURE 1-17 (2d ed. 2008).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
209
academic and other commentators. In routine situations, 10 Congress is the dominant actor, both constitutionally 11 and prudentially. 12 But it would be a mistake to see the relationships as strictly hierarchical. Often they are interactive. Courts, through constitutional analysis and statutory interpretation, and government and private professional communities, through advocacy and an “unwritten code” as to how things should be done, also have been highly influential in the development of values shaping the rules of tax procedure.13 The legitimate extent of such interaction is unsettled and is the subject of considerable debate in many areas of law. For example, some see statutory interpretation as a collaborative process by which courts and legislatures formulate law interactively.14 Others have offered similar visions of constitutional law15 and administrative law.16 Tax is about as positivistic as any field of law gets, but courts have made a great deal of the law even in tax. 17 This tradition was estab10. A non-routine situation would be, for example, when the courts hold that the Constitution forbids some item of tax legislation. The courts are reluctant to do so. Judicial deference to Congress is considerable in matters of revenue raising. See, e.g., Nordlinger v. Hahn, 505 U.S. 1, 11-12 (1992); Regan v. Taxation with Representation of Wash., 461 U.S. 540, 547 (1983). 11. See U.S. CONST. art I, § 8, cl. 1. 12. In dealing with the numerous complex considerations that formulating tax rules entails, Congress has natural advantages over the courts. See United States v. Nunnally Inv. Co., 316 U.S. 258, 264 (1942) (“The problem of legal remedies appropriate for fiscal administration rests within easy Congressional control. Congress can deal with the matter comprehensively, unembarrassed by the limitations of a litigation involving only one phase of a complex problem.”); see also United States v. Kales, 314 U.S. 186, 200 (1941). Some might argue that an expert agency could make better tax laws than a democratically selected legislature. Whether or not that is true, Congress surely possesses a legitimacy in this area that Treasury lacks. See generally Andre L. Smith, The Nondelegation Doctrine and the Federal Income Tax: May Congress Grant the President the Authority to Set the Income Tax Rates?, 31 VA. TAX REV. 763 (2012). 13. This fact has been recognized for a long time. Over a half century ago, for example, an Assistant Secretary of the Treasury remarked on “one very important factor”: “As our proposed regulations are published, a cumulative effect is being created. The regulations should give you an over-all indication of attitude on the part of the Treasury Department.” Laurens Williams, The Preparation and Promulgation of Treasury Department Regulations Under the Internal Revenue Code of 1954, 8 TAX EXECUTIVE 3, 7-8 (1956) (emphasis in original). 14. See, e.g., William D. Popkin, The Collaborative Model of Statutory Interpretation, 61 S. CAL. L. REV. 541 (1988). 15. See, e.g., Blakely v. Washington, 542 U.S. 296, 326 (2004) (Kennedy, J., dissenting) (“Constant, constructive discourse between our courts and our legislatures is an integral and admirable part of the constitutional design.”); Mistretta v. United States, 488 U.S. 361, 408 (1989) (“Our principle of separation of powers anticipates that the coordinate Branches will converse with each other on matters of vital common interest.”). 16. See, e.g., 1 KENNETH CULP DAVIS, ADMINISTRATIVE LAW TREATISE 138 (2d ed. 1978) (stating that administrative procedure is formulated by “[l]egislators and judges who are working [as] partners [to] produce better law than legislators alone could possibly produce”). 17. See, e.g., Dobson v. Commissioner, 320 U.S. 489, 499 n.25 (1943) (“Judge-made
210
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
lished early, and it has proved enduring.18 The benefits of judicial participation are doubted by some, however, 19 and the legitimacy of such collaboration was debated in a recent Supreme Court tax case. In the Home Concrete case,20 the Court invalidated an amended Treasury regulation dealing with the six-year statute of limitations on assessment in cases of substantial omissions of income.21 In the course of its analysis, a four-justice dissent remarked: “Our legal system presumes there will be continuing dialogue among the three branches of Government on questions of statutory interpretation and application.” 22 Unsurprisingly, Justice Scalia rose to defend his textualist sensibilities. He addressed and rejected the dissenters’ “romantic, judgeempowering image” and “mirage” of a legislative-executive-judicial troika.23 He found the dissenters’ vision to be “obliterated” by Vermont Yankee, whose teaching Justice Scalia took to be that “Congress prescribes and we [the Court] obey, with no discretion to add to the administrative procedures that Congress has created.” 24 I share Justice Scalia’s belief that in tax (and other statutory areas) a clear congressional command controls, unless unconstitutional and until Congress amends its direction. But his argument about constitutional primacy may have missed the point about practical realities. Congress is not hermetically sealed off from other legal actors. The elected Senators and Representatives are influenced by values and norms molded and expressed by judges who decide tax cases, Executive Branch officials who suggest and testify as to tax legislation, Congress’s staffs of tax professionals, the tax professionals who lobby Congress on behalf of their clients, and, of course, the
law is particularly prolific in connection with federal taxation . . . .” (quoting RANDOLPH PAUL, SELECTED STUDIES IN FEDERAL TAXATION 2 n.2 (1938))); Charlotte Crane, Pollock, Macomber, and the Role of the Federal Courts in the Development of the Income Tax in the United States, 73 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 1, 2 (2010) (“Although the income tax is quintessentially a matter of statute, a significant number of its doctrines are entirely a matter of judicial definition.”). 18. Initially, decisions of the Board of Tax Appeals (the predecessor of the Tax Court) were reviewed without any deference. This established a “habit” of free-wheeling review. During those early years, “[p]recedents had accumulated in which courts had laid down many rules of taxation not based on statute but upon their ideas of right accounting or tax practice. It was difficult to shift to a new basis.” Dobson, 320 U.S. at 497-98. 19. See, e.g., Crane, supra note 17; Martin D. Ginsburg, Making Tax Law Through the Judicial Process, 70 A.B.A. J. 74 (1984). 20. United States v. Home Concrete & Supply, LLC, 132 S. Ct. 1836 (2012). 21. See I.R.C. § 6501(e). 22. Home Concrete, 132 S. Ct. at 1852 (Kennedy, J., dissenting). 23. Id. at 1848 (Scalia, J., concurring). 24. Id. (construing Vermont Yankee Nuclear Power Corp. v. Natural Res. Def. Council, Inc., 435 U.S. 519 (1978)).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
211
clients themselves who are Senators’ and Representatives’ constituents and contributors. The values fought for and held by the many actors in the tax community are the womb from which tax laws issue. 25 We turn now to the key developments that have formed such values in the area of tax procedure. B. Shaping Developments Ruskin, the British author, critic, and social theorist, asserted that “[g]reat nations write their autobiographies in three manuscripts—the book of their deeds, the book of their words, and the book of their art.” 26 For Ruskin’s purposes, the book of art was the most trustworthy. For the purposes of this Article, the book of deeds and the book of words—that is, what mechanisms we have created in tax procedure and why we have said they needed to be created—are particularly illuminating. The norms governing the current federal tax procedure system—and the criteria that should govern reform efforts—crystallized as a result of a long skein of legislative, regulatory, and judicial events. In rough chronological order, the key events—the Defining Dozen—have included the following: (1) adapting the common law in the 1800s to fashion a refund remedy for taxpayers and the progressive expansion of that remedy over more than a century; 2) enactment of the Anti-Injunction Act in 186727 and creation of increasing numbers of statutory and judicial exceptions to it; (3) establishment, beginning in the 1920s, of prepayment administrative (and later judicial) remedies for taxpayers as to income and some other taxes;28 (4) the 1960 decision of the United States Supreme Court in Flora II,29 requiring full payment of liabilities determined by the IRS as prerequisite to a taxpayer’s bringing a refund suit; (5) the Supreme Court’s 1964 decision in Powell, 30 establishing standards to govern judicial challenges to IRS summonses and subsequent statutory elaboration of additional rules;31 (6) enactment of the Federal Tax Lien Act of 25. See generally LOUIS EISENSTEIN, THE IDEOLOGIES OF TAXATION (1961); see also William L. Cary, Pressure Groups and the Revenue Code: A Requiem in Honor of the Departing Uniformity of the Tax Laws, 68 HARV. L. REV. 745, 746, 773-80 (1955); Stanley S. Surrey, The Congress and the Tax Lobbyist—How Special Tax Provisions Get Enacted, 70 HARV. L. REV. 1145, 1146, 1181-82 (1957). 26. JOHN RUSKIN, ST. MARK’S REST: THE HISTORY OF VENICE (New York, John Wiley & Sons 1877) (author’s preface). 27. Currently codified at I.R.C. § 7421. 28. HAROLD DUBROFF, THE UNITED STATES TAX COURT: AN HISTORICAL ANALYSIS pt. 1 (1979). 29. Flora II, 362 U.S. 145 (1960). 30. United States v. Powell, 379 U.S. 48 (1964). 31. Id. at 57-58; see, e.g., I.R.C. § 7609.
212
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
1966 32 with subsequent statutory amendments and promulgation of extensive regulations; (7) the Supreme Court’s 1976 Shapiro and Laing decisions, 33 followed by enactment of administrative and judicial mechanisms for prompt review of jeopardy and termination assessments;34 (8) enactment of the unified partnership audit and litigation procedures in the Tax Equity and Fiscal Responsibility Act of 1982 (“TEFRA”); 35 (9) the Supreme Court’s 1997 Brockamp decision 36 and its partial reversal by legislation allowing limited equitable tolling of the statute of limitations on filing refund claims; 37 (10) enactment of numerous tax procedure changes in the Internal Revenue Service Restructuring and Reform Act of 1998; 38 (11) the Supreme Court’s 2005 Ballard decision 39 dealing with Tax Court opinion practice; and (12) the irreversible entry of principles of general administrative law into tax litigation, reflected in part in the Supreme Court’s 2011 Mayo decision. 40 Others might constitute the list differently. Clearly, there have been other important developments in federal tax procedure in the past century. I selected the Defining Dozen developments because they deal with rights and obligations as between the IRS and taxpayers. It is from these matters that criteria useful to reforming federal tax litigation are most likely to emerge. 1. Creation and Expansion of Refund Remedies “In present times, federal income taxes are of such a pervasive and significant influence that it is easy to forget their relatively recent origin.”41 For most of this country’s history, the federal government assumed limited responsibilities, and so could do with limited revenue, mostly supplied by tariffs, sale of public lands, and various excise taxes.42 32. Federal Tax Lien Act of 1966, Pub. L. No. 89-719, 80 Stat. 1125 (codified at I.R.C. §§ 6323-6325). 33. Commissioner v. Shapiro, 424 U.S. 614 (1976); Laing v. United States, 423 U.S. 161 (1976). 34. See I.R.C. § 7429. 35. Pub. L. No. 97-248, 96 Stat. 324. 36. United States v. Brockamp, 519 U.S. 347 (1997). 37. I.R.C. § 6511(h). 38. Internal Revenue Service Restructuring and Reform Act of 1998, Pub. L. No. 105206, 112 Stat. 685 (codified in various sections of the I.R.C.). 39. Ballard v. Commissioner, 544 U.S. 40 (2005). 40. See Mayo Found. for Med. Educ. & Research v. United States, 131 S. Ct. 704 (2011). 41. DUBROFF, supra note 28, at 1 (1979). 42. The idea of an income tax was not unknown, however. As early as 1643, the New Plymouth colony had a rudimentary income tax, and some other colonies and states also imposed income taxes in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Id. at 1-2.
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
213
Nonetheless, it is surprising, perhaps shocking, to contemporary sensibilities that until 1855 no suit as to tax overpayments was permitted against the federal government. 43 That caused lawyers and judges to do what they usually do when confronted by an inadequate statutory framework—use their creativity to fashion an alternative remedy. The constraint, of course, was the doctrine of sovereign immunity. The answer fashioned by the courts—upheld by the Supreme Court in 1936—was allowing federal tax collectors 44 to be sued personally for taxes allegedly collected illegally. 45 “Such a suit was based on the common-law [action] of assumpsit for money had and received . . . .” 46 This device was built on a fiction. 47 The real party in interest was the government, not the collector. 48 Much of the law involves fiction, of course, but a regime based on dubious premises often leads to convolution erected on convolution as doctrine is expounded. So it was with this fiction. There were at least three problems with the solution fashioned by the courts. First, suits against collectors initially depended on diversity jurisdiction. 49 Suit could be barred, therefore, because of acci43. If the taxpayer had not yet paid the tax at issue, she might be able to secure judicial review of the merits by posting bond for the tax, then, when the government brought suit on the bond, asserting the absence of substantive liability as a defense. In addition, Congress sometimes determined the merits of tax claims itself via special legislation. See William T. Plumb, Jr., Tax Refund Suits Against Collectors of Internal Revenue, 60 HARV. L. REV. 685, 687 (1947). 44. For discussion of the role of collectors in federal taxation during the nineteenth century, see Bryan T. Camp, Theory and Practice in Tax Administration, 29 VA. TAX REV. 227, 229-43 (2009). 45. Elliott v. Swartwout, 35 U.S. (10 Pet.) 137, 159 (1836). Elliott was a customs case. The “sue the collector” remedy was held to apply as well in tax cases. City of Philadelphia v. Collector, 75 U.S. (5 Wall.) 720, 730-33 (1866). 46. Flora II, 362 U.S. 145, 153 (1960). This common law action should be distinguished from a taxpayer suit on account stated, which is available when the IRS fails to make a stipulated refund. See, e.g., Bonwit Teller & Co. v. United States, 283 U.S. 258, 259 (1931); MARVIN J. GARBIS, RONALD B. RUBIN & PATRICIA T. MORGAN, TAX PROCEDURE AND TAX FRAUD: CASES AND MATERIALS 420-21 (3d ed. 1992). 47. “A suit against a Collector who has collected a tax in the fulfillment of a ministerial duty is today an anomalous relic of bygone modes of thought. . . . [Although t]here may have been utility in such procedural devices in days when the Government was not suable as freely as now. . . [t]hey have little utility today.” George Moore Ice Cream Co. v. Rose, 289 U.S. 373, 382-83 (1933). 48. The office of “Collector” has since been abolished. When the office existed, there was a collector for each district. “When the Commissioner [of Internal Revenue] certifie[d] an assessment to the collector, that official ha[d] a purely ministerial duty to effect its collection.” Plumb, supra note 43, at 687; see also Erskine v. Hohnbach, 81 U.S. (14 Wall.) 613, 616 (1871) (holding that “[t]he collector could not revise nor refuse to enforce the assessment regularly made”). 49. Collector v. Hubbard, 79 U.S. (12 Wall.) 1, 8 (1870). Subsequently, Congress established jurisdiction for “all causes arising under any law providing internal revenue.” Rev. Stat. § 629(4) (1874) (current version codified at 28 U.S.C. § 1340).
214
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
dents of residency. Second, notice of the alleged illegality was held to be an essential element of an action against a collector, requiring that the taxpayer have paid the amount in question under protest. 50 This created a trap for the unwary.51 The taxpayer who neglected this formality would be nonsuited. 52 Third, underlining the fiction, collectors were initially indemnified by the government for amounts for which they were held personally liable. 53 This led to the practice of collectors withholding amounts from collected taxes to provide cushion against the possibility of being held liable. In turn, this led to theft by collectors 54 and caused Congress in 1839 to prohibit the practice without creating an alternative indemnification mechanism. 55 This had an unintended consequence. The Supreme Court viewed a reliable indemnification procedure as fundamental to the common law remedy. The Court held that the remedy could not survive the removal of this foundation. 56 Justices Story and McLean filed separate dissents, arguing in part that taxpayers could not constitutionally be deprived of all judicial remedies for recovery of illegal or excessive taxes. There being no other remedy, they maintained, suits against collectors could not be abolished. 57 Congress reacted quickly. Within a few weeks, it passed a sostyled “explanatory Act” declaring that the 1839 legislation should not be understood as impairing the rights of persons to sue collectors. 58 The Court was satisfied; suits against collectors were rehabilitated as a remedy. 59 But, given the legislation, the Supreme Court “no longer regarded the suit as a common-law action, but rather as a statutory remedy which ‘in its nature [was] a remedy against the Government.’ ” 60
50. Elliott, 35 U.S. (10 Pet.) at 153-54. 51. This ran contrary to “[t]he ideal of the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure and of all modern code pleading . . . that a party who has timely brought a suit in a court having jurisdiction shall not be defeated by mere procedural technicalities.” Plumb, supra note 43, at 685. 52. The federal government abolished the “paid under protest” requirement in 1924. Revenue Act of 1924, ch. 234, § 1014, 43 Stat. 253, 343. 53. Rev. Stat. § 989 (1875); see, e.g., George Moore Ice Cream Co. v. Rose, 289 U.S. 373, 380-81 (1933). 54. See Cary v. Curtis, 44 U.S. (3 How.) 236, 243 (1845) (noting that the practice “led to great abuses, and to much loss to the public”). 55. Act of Mar. 3, 1839, ch. 82, § 2, 5 Stat. 339, 348-49 (1839). 56. Cary, 44. U.S. (3 How.) at 243-44. 57. Id. at 252-56 (Story, J., dissenting), 263-66 (McLean, J., dissenting). 58. Act of Feb. 26, 1845, ch. 22, 5 Stat. 727 (1845). 59. See, e.g., City of Philadelphia v. Collector, 72 U.S. (5 Wall.) 720, 731 (1866). 60. Flora II, 362 U.S. 145, 153 (1960) (quoting Curtis’s Adm’x v. Fiedler, 67 U.S. (2 Black) 461, 479 (1862)).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
215
Congress created a second refund remedy when it established the Court of Claims in 1855.61 That body originated as an administrative or advisory body but was elevated to judicial status, with jurisdiction to hear claims against the federal government, including tax claims. 62 Next, in 1887, Congress created another refund action in the Tucker Act. It conferred on federal district courts jurisdiction to hear claims against the United States not exceeding $1000.63 Taxpayers with larger refund claims could sue either the United States in the Court of Claims or the collector in district court. The utility of that second alternative was impaired, however, when the Supreme Court held that an action against a collector was personal in character and could not, in the event of the particular collector’s death or other vacation of office, be maintained against her successor.64 Congress responded to that holding by amending the statute to remove the ceiling amount in the event that the collector to whom the tax was paid was not in office when the suit was commenced.65 These historical artifacts have now been tidied up. Refund suits against collectors have been abolished.66 Instead, tax refund claims may be brought against the federal government in either the Court of Federal Claims (the current iteration of the Court of Claims) or federal district court, without any ceiling on the amount sought. 67 This history was driven by the desire to provide taxpayers effective remedies. Congress’ failure to so provide in early years impelled the courts to create a common law remedy, however unwieldy. Limitations on that judicial remedy spurred Congress to improve statutory remedies progressively. 2. The Anti-Injunction Act and Its Exceptions As we have just seen, taxpayers had the ability through refund suits to attempt to secure the return of taxes allegedly improperly collected by the federal government. But were taxpayers remitted to only this “back end” remedy? Lawyers are fond of seeking injunctions. Instead of paying the tax then trying for a refund, could tax61. Act of Feb. 24, 1855, ch. 122, 10 Stat. 612. 62. See Williams v. United States, 289 U.S. 553, 562-65 (1933); United States v. Klein, 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 128, 144-45 (1871). 63. Act of Mar. 3, 1887, ch. 359, § 2, 24 Stat. 505. This was held to include jurisdiction over tax refund claims. United States v. Emery, Bird, Thayer Realty Co., 237 U.S. 28, 32 (1915). 64. Smietanka v. Ind. Steel Co., 257 U.S. 1, 6 (1921). 65. Revenue Act of 1921, ch. 136, § 1310, 42 Stat. 227, 310. The amount-incontroversy ceiling was abolished entirely in 1954. Act of July 30, 1954, ch. 648, § 1, 68 Stat. 589, 589. 66. See Act of Nov. 2, 1966, Pub. L. No. 89-713, § 3, 80 Stat. 1107, 1108. 67. 28 U.S.C. § 1346(a)(1) (2006).
216
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
payers obtain earlier judicial determination of the merits of a particular case by bringing an injunction action against impending tax assessment or collection? From an early date—essentially contemporaneous with the abolition of the income tax imposed by the Union during the Civil War 68— Congress answered that question in the negative. In 1867, it enacted the earliest version of the Anti-Injunction Act (“AIA”). 69 The current version of the Act, embodied in I.R.C. § 7421(a), 70 provides, in the main, that “no suit for the purpose of restraining the assessment or collection of any tax shall be maintained in any court by any person, whether or not such person is the person against whom such tax was assessed.” 71 The AIA was adopted by voice vote as a floor amendment and so was not accompanied by committee reports. Nonetheless, the text of the statute makes the provision’s purpose plain enough. 72 “This statute protects the Government’s ability to collect a consistent stream of revenue . . . . Because of the [AIA], taxes can ordinarily be challenged only after they are paid, by suing for a refund.” 73 This understanding has existed essentially from the original enactment of the statute. 74 This strong “protect the revenue” measure has been modified by both Congress and the Supreme Court, however. Congress has amended § 7421 from time to time to allow injunction actions when the IRS proceeds with assessment or collection in disregard of statutorily prescribed taxpayer remedies and protections. 75 68. For description of the Civil War income tax, see INTERNAL REVENUE SERVICE, supra note 2, at 10-15. 69. Act of Mar. 2, 1867, Pub. L. No. 39-169, § 10, 14 Stat. 471, 475. 70. A parallel prohibition exists in I.R.C. § 7421(b) as to suits to restrain assessment or collection of transferee or fiduciary liabilities. 71. I.R.C. § 7421(a). Taxpayers or third parties seeking injunctions sometimes also desire judicial declaration of the illegality of the tax rule or its application in the particular case. Just as the AIA can be a barrier to an injunction, the Declaratory Judgment Act (“DJA”) can be a barrier to a declaration. The DJA withdraws authority from federal courts to grant declaratory relief in tax cases. 28 U.S.C. § 2201(a) (2006). The courts typically hold that the AIA and the DJA are coextensive. See, e.g., Sigmon Coal Co. v. Apfel, 226 F.3d 291, 299 (4th Cir. 2000) (citing In re Leckie Smokeless Coal Co., 99 F.3d 573, 583 (4th Cir. 1996)). 72. Even textualist judges use statutory purpose, as long as such purpose can be derived from the statute itself and its context, rather than from suspect committee reports. See ANTONIN SCALIA & BRYAN A. GARNER, READING LAW: THE INTERPRETATION OF LEGAL TEXTS 56-58 (2012). 73. Nat’l Fed. of Indep. Bus. v. Sebelius (NFIB), 132 S. Ct. 2566, 2582 (2012). 74. See Snyder v. Marks, 109 U.S. 189, 192 (1883); Taylor v. Secor, 92 U.S. 575, 61215 (1875). 75. Specifically, I.R.C. § 7421(a) allows injunction suits as provided in § 6015(e) (Tax Court review of spousal relief cases), §§ 6212(a), (c), 6213(a) (Tax Court review of deficiency actions), §§ 6225(b), 6246(b) (TEFRA proceedings), § 6330(e)(1) (collection due process cases), § 6331(i) (levies as to divisible taxes), § 6672(c) (trust fund recovery penalty
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
217
In addition, the Supreme Court created judicial exceptions to the AIA. Initially, the Court held that an injunction action will lie if all three of these conditions are satisfied: (1) under the most pro-IRS view of the facts and the law, there is no possibility that the IRS could prevail on the merits in the controversy; (2) the taxpayer is threatened with irreparable harm; and (3) no adequate legal remedy is available to the taxpayer. 76 Later, taking a purposive tack, the Court created a second exception. Under it, the AIA will bar injunction actions “only in situations in which Congress ha[s] provided the aggrieved party with an alternative legal avenue by which to contest the legality of a particular tax.” 77 A recent prominent appearance of the AIA was in NFIB, which tested the constitutionality of the individual mandate provision of the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act. Holding that the shared responsibility payment (which enforces the mandate) constitutes a penalty, not a tax, for statutory purposes, the Court held that the AIA did not prevent on-the-merits review of the constitutional issues.78 This chapter in our story reflects a dominant revenue protection purpose, of course. Dominant, but not unmixed. The AIA does not prevent all challenges to tax assessment and collection, just injunctions. The presence of an alternative taxpayer remedy—refund suits—is what makes prohibiting injunctions politically and constitutionally palatable. 79 Moreover, Congress has withdrawn even the prohibition on injunctions when necessary to maintain the integrity of a variety of protections for taxpayers and third parties. The judicial exceptions—although limited 80—further evince the system’s desire to protect the revenue only in cases of genuine necessity. 3. Creation of Prepayment Remedies National crises, especially wars, transform societies. Among other effects, America’s participation in World War I caused the federal income and profits taxes to emerge as the federal government’s pribonds), § 6694(c) (preparer penalty), § 7426(a), (b)(1) (wrongful levy and other suits), § 7429(b) (jeopardy and termination assessment review), and § 7436 (employment status determinations). 76. See Miller v. Standard Nut Margarine Co., 284 U.S. 498, 510-11 (1932), overruled by Enochs v. Williams Packing & Navigation Co., 370 U.S. 1, 6 (1962). 77. South Carolina v. Regan, 465 U.S. 367, 373 (1984). 78. NFIB, 132 S. Ct. at 2583-84; id. at 2656 (Scalia, Kennedy, Thomas & Alito, JJ., dissenting); see Steve R. Johnson, It’s Not a Tax (Statutorily), but It Is a Tax (Constitutionally), 32 A.B.A. SEC. TAX’N NEWS Q. 13 (2012). 79. See infra Part II.B.7. 80. See, e.g., United States v. Clintwood Elkhorn Mining Co., 553 U.S. 1, 14 (2008) (holding that the Williams Packing exception applies only when the taxpayer’s claim is “so obvious that the Government [would have] no chance of prevailing [on the merits]”).
218
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
mary means of finance. 81 This emergence created great stress on the then Bureau of Internal Revenue because, first, the taxes were highly conceptually complex and, second, numerous taxpayers were swept into the net when the income tax graduated from a class tax to a mass tax. Taxpayers who disagreed with the Bureau’s determination of their tax liability had the judicial remedies described in Part II.B.1, of course. But the absence of a pre-assessment remedy soon became a sore point. The first such remedy was administrative. In 1918, Congress confirmed and extended 1917 authority by creating an Advisory Tax Board, whose members were appointed by the Commissioner of Internal Revenue with approval of the Secretary of the Treasury.82 The Commissioner could on his own authority, and was required to on request by the taxpayer, submit to the Board any question as to interpretation or administration of income, war profits, or excess profits tax.83 In 1921, Congress required the Bureau to give the taxpayer notice of its intention to assess income tax and an opportunity to file an appeal with the Bureau’s Committee on Appeals and Review within thirty days of the notice. 84 Not surprisingly, some believed that taxpayers could not get a “square deal” while the appellate unit remained within the Bureau itself. 85 Accordingly, in 1924 Congress created the Board of Tax Appeals as an independent agency within the Executive Branch to hear appeals from deficiency determinations by the Bureau. Decisions by the Board were appealable to federal district court. 86 In 1942, Congress renamed the Board the “Tax Court of the United States,” although it continued to be an independent agency in the Executive Branch, with its jurisdiction, powers, and duties unaltered.87 Finally, in 1969, Congress ended the tribunal’s status as an agency. It “established, under article I of the Constitution of the United States, a court of record to be known as the United States Tax Court.” 88 As it is currently constituted, “[t]he Tax Court’s function 81. For discussion of this emergence, see DUBROFF, supra note 28, at 1-12, and David Laro, The Evolution of the Tax Court as an Independent Tribunal, 1995 U. ILL. L. REV. 17, 19-22. 82. Revenue Act of 1918, ch. 18, § 1301(d)(1), 40 Stat. 1057, 1141. 83. Id. § 1301(d)(2), 40 Stat. at 1141; see Williamsport Wire Rope Co. v. United States, 277 U.S. 551, 562 n.7 (1928). 84. Revenue Act of 1921, ch. 136, § 250(d), 42 Stat. 227, 255-56. 85. 62 CONG. REC. 8913-14 (1922) (statement of Sen. Pomerene); see also DUBROFF, supra note 28, at 58 (noting “the widespread belief that the Committee maintained a policy of resolving all doubts against the taxpayer”). 86. Revenue Act of 1924, Pub. L. No. 68-176, § 900, 43 Stat. 253, 336-38, amended by Revenue Act of 1926, Pub. L. No. 69-20, § 1000-05, 44 Stat. 9, 105-11. 87. Revenue Act of 1942, Pub. L. No. 77-753, § 504, 56 Stat. 798, 957. 88. I.R.C. § 7441.
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
219
and role in the federal judicial scheme closely resemble those of the federal district courts . . . .” 89 Its decisions are appealable to the circuit courts “in the same manner and to the same extent as decisions of the district courts in civil actions tried without a jury.” 90 This chapter in the saga of federal tax procedure is clear. The reasons for the creation of the prepayment remedy initially and for its evolution into greater independence and institutional dignity are evident. Congress was animated by notions of confidence, competence, and consistency. The confidence of the public in the fairness of the process was bolstered by the formalization of the Tax Court as a court, a tribunal separate from the IRS. 91 The competence of the tribunal to decide tax controversies fairly and correctly would be promoted by the tax experience of the members selected for it and their specialized tax dockets. 92 Consistency—nationwide uniformity in interpretation and application of the tax laws—also was hoped to result from the Tax Court’s nationwide jurisdiction. 93 4. Flora Full Payment Rule Part II.B.1 above traced the development of federal refund litigation remedies. An important question remained, however: was full payment of the assessed amount necessary before a refund case could be brought? For instance, assume the IRS has assessed $50,000 of additional income tax liability against Abigail. Can she pay only $20,000 (or even $100) of that amount and sue for refund of it? Or is Abigail precluded from bringing suit until she pays the full $50,000? The lower courts were divided.94 The Supreme Court granted certiorari to resolve the conflict. In Flora I, with only one justice dissent89. Freytag v. Commissioner, 501 U.S. 868, 891 (1991). 90. I.R.C. § 7482(a)(1). 91. John Nance Garner, then ranking Democrat on the House Ways and Means Committee, expressed the common concern that, as long as members of the reviewing body were subject to the Treasury Department, “if they did not decide cases to suit [the Treasury Secretary] he could kick them out and get somebody who would.” 65 CONG. REC. 3282 (1924). 92. For a while, Tax Court decisions were given greater influential weight than other decisions of lower courts because of this expertise. See, e.g., Dobson v. Commissioner, 320 U.S. 489, 498-502 (1943) (contrasting the “long legislative or administrative [tax] experience” of Tax Court judges to “the lack of a roundly tax-informed viewpoint of [generalist] judges”), abrogated in part by I.R.C. § 7482. 93. For this reason, the Tax Court originally took the position that when its sense of the law differed from that of the circuit court to which the case would be appealable, it would continue to adhere to its view despite the relevant circuit’s contrary view. Lawrence v. Commissioner, 27 T.C. 713, 716-20 (1957). The Tax Court later abandoned that position, deferring to the controlling circuit even when that meant that substantively identical cases would be decided inconsistently because they were within different circuits. Golsen v. Commissioner, 54 T.C. 742, 756-58 (1970), aff’d, 445 F.2d 985 (10th Cir. 1971). 94. Compare Flora v. United States, 246 F.2d 929 (10th Cir. 1957), aff’g 142 F. Supp. 602 (D. Wyo. 1956), and Suhr v. United States, 18 F.2d 81 (3d Cir. 1927) (holding that full
220
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
ing (in a dissent of only one paragraph), the Court held in favor of the full payment view. 95 The majority’s opinion turned mainly on statutory interpretation and precedent, not policy. It affirmed what it called “carefully considered dictum” in one of its 1876 decisions. 96 The majority saw the contrary lower court cases as interlopers. In its view, the full payment “understanding of the statutory scheme appears to have prevailed for the succeeding fifty or sixty years” after 1876.97 Thus, “there does not appear to be a single case before 1940 in which a taxpayer attempted a suit for refund of income taxes without paying the full amount the Government alleged to be due.” 98 This assertion was important because a long settled tradition of consistent interpretation is a powerful consideration of statutory construction.99 The Court’s historical assertions were inaccurate. As the Government later conceded, there were in fact pre-1940 cases in which taxpayers sued for refunds without having fully paid the assessment and without the Government or the court objecting to this omission. 100 Accordingly, the Court granted rehearing. Flora II, decided in 1960, was a much more searching exploration. Again the Court held in favor of the full payment approach, but only by five-to-four, with a much longer majority opinion, one long dissent, and one short dissent. 101 As befits the closeness of the vote, the majority acknowledged the closeness of the merits.102 As supporting a partial payment approach, the majority noted that suits against collectors 103 could be maintained without full payment and that there was an “absence of any conclusive evidence that Congress ha[d] ever intended to inaugurate a new rule.” 104 payment is necessary), with Bushmiaer v. United States, 230 F.2d 146 (8th Cir. 1956), Sirian Lamp Co. v. Manning, 123 F.2d 776 (3d Cir. 1941), and Coates v. United States, 111 F.2d 609 (2d Cir. 1940) (holding that partial payment suffices). 95. Flora I, 357 U.S. 63 (1958). 96. Id. at 68 (discussing Cheatham v. United States, 92 U.S. 85 (1876)). 97. Id. 98. Id. at 69. 99. See, e.g., United States v. Cleveland Indians Baseball Co., 532 U.S. 200, 219-20 (2001); Flora II, 362 U.S. 145, 177-78 (1960) (Frankfurter, J., dissenting) (“[I]n construing a tax law it has been my rule to follow almost blindly accepted understanding of the meaning of tax legislation, when that is manifested by long-continued, uniform practice, unless a statute leaves no admissible opening for administrative construction.”). 100. Although there was some wrangling over precisely how many such cases there were, there were at least two in the Supreme Court and a number in the lower courts. See Flora II, 362 U.S. at 181-85 (citing Bowers v. Kerbaugh-Empire Co., 271 U.S. 170 (1926); Cook v. Tait, 265 U.S. 47 (1924), and various lower court decisions). 101. Flora II, 362 U.S. 145. 102. Id. at 152. 103. See supra Part II.B.1. 104. Flora II, 362 U.S. at 157.
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
221
In favor of the full payment predicate, the majority enlisted its view of the 1876 decision, a 1921 statutory amendment, and— decisively—the “carefully articulated and quite complicated structure of tax laws.” 105 The majority perceived “that Congress ha[d] several times acted upon the assumption that [the Code] requires full payment before suit,” 106 these times being the establishment of the Board of Tax Appeals and the enactment of the Declaratory Judgment Act and § 7422(e) of the Code. 107 Although giving primary attention to statutory construction, the majority also invoked several policy arguments, including concerns about claim splitting, 108 allocation of caseloads between the Tax Court and refund fora, 109 and erosion of revenue collection. 110 In contrast, the dissenters expressed their “deep and abiding conviction that the Court today departs from the plain direction of Congress . . . , defeats its beneficent purpose, and repudiates many soundly reasoned opinions of the federal courts . . . .” 111 The dissenters read the statutes and precedents differently from the majority, and they disagreed at the level of policy as well. Specifically, the dissent maintained that a partial payment rule would not hamper tax collection, 112 but it would avoid “great hardships” by allowing suits by those lacking the resources to pay fully before litigating.113 The full payment rule has been settled since Flora II, but there are exceptions and ambiguities. For example, the taxpayer’s liability may include as many as three components: the deficiency, interest on the deficiency, and one or more penalties. To satisfy Flora II, the taxpayer must fully pay the deficiency, of course, but must she also pay all the interest and/or all the penalties? The Supreme Court has not addressed the issue, and lower court decisions have been divided.114
105. Id. 106. Id. (construing 28 U.S.C. § 1346(a)(1)). 107. Id. at 158-67. 108. Id. at 165-66. 109. Id. at 176. 110. Id. at 169 n.36, 176 n.41. 111. Id. at 178 (Whittaker, J., dissenting). 112. Id. at 194-95. 113. Id. at 195, 198. 114. Compare Horkey v. United States, 715 F. Supp. 259, 260-61 (D. Minn. 1989) (payment of penalty required), with Kell-Strom Tool Co. v. United States, 205 F. Supp. 190, 194 (D. Conn. 1962) (payment of interest and penalties not required). See also Martin M. Lore & L. Paige Marvel, Claims Court Does About Face on Flora Full-Payment Rule, 78 J. TAX’N 81, 81 (1993); Erika L. Robinson, Note, Refund Suits in Claims Court: Jurisdiction and the Flora Full-Payment Rule After Shore v. United States, 46 TAX LAW. 827, 831-34 (1993) (describing four different views of the issue announced within a two-year period by the Claims Court).
222
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
An important exception applies to so-called divisible taxes, that is, taxes based on separate transactions the assessments of which occur separately. Prominent examples include withholding taxes and the related trust fund recovery penalty under § 6672. 115 One facing the penalty can secure judicial review by paying the amount attributable to one employee for each calendar quarter at issue and posting a bond. The government will then counterclaim for the amounts attributable to the remaining employees.116 What values does this episode reflect? Since the Flora cases are primarily about statutory interpretation and precedent, the values of congressional primacy and stability in taxation are much in evidence. Process efficiency also is implicated. So are revenue protection and provision of effective taxpayer remedies—with no clear winner between the two. Revenue protection was a policy invoked by the majority, but that should not be overemphasized. The justices were closely divided. Moreover, the majority thought that the availability of prepayment Tax Court review ameliorated the concern about erosion of the refund remedy by enshrining a full payment predicate. 117 Thus, the majority did not see a sharp conflict between revenue protection and provision of effective taxpayer remedies. 5. Powell and IRS Information Gathering As Bacon observed, “knowledge itself is power.” 118 The IRS cannot test the accuracy of taxpayers’ returns without the ability to gather information on taxpayers’ transactions. Thus, Congress has granted the IRS authority “[t]o examine any books, papers, records, or other data which may be relevant or material to such inquiry,” and to summon taxpayers and third parties to give testimony under oath or produce “such books, papers, records, or other data . . . as may be relevant or material to such inquiry.”119 But the IRS’s need for information must be balanced with taxpayers’ interest in avoiding unnecessarily burdensome examinations.120 Thus, the Code contains a number of provisions to prevent undue in115. See also Susan V. Sample & Samira A. Salman, Tax Shelter Penalties: Are They Divisible? Or Does the Taxpayer Have to Pay the Balance Before Litigating?, 4 HOUS. BUS. & TAX L.J. 447, 455-58 (2004). 116. I.R.C. § 6672(c). 117. Flora II, 362 U.S. at 175. 118. FRANCIS BACON, RELIGIOUS MEDITATIONS (1597), reprinted in 7 THE WORKS OF FRANCIS BACON 243, 253 (James Spedding et. al. eds., Garrett Press 1968). 119. I.R.C. § 7602(a)(1)-(2). 120. For an excellent description of the history and premises of IRS information gathering in general, and of the summons power in particular, see Bryan T. Camp, Tax Administration as Inquisitorial Process and the Partial Paradigm Shift in the IRS Restructuring and Reform Act of 1998, 56 FLA. L. REV. 1 (2004).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
223
trusion. These provisions: (1) require that the times and places of examination be “reasonable under the circumstances;” 121 (2) control audio recording of interviews; 122 (3) require the IRS to explain the audit process and the taxpayer’s rights in it; 123 (4) limit IRS summonses when the Department of Justice has entered the case;124 (5) prohibit the IRS from using especially detailed financial status inquiry programs absent reasonable indication that there is a likelihood the taxpayer has unreported income; 125 (6) impose special restrictions on tax investigations of churches; 126 (7) establish rules as to IRS contacts with third parties; 127 (8) heighten requirements when the IRS seeks sensitive computer information; 128 (9) give taxpayers intervention rights when the IRS summonses information from third parties;129 and (10) create requirements for the enforcement of “John Doe” summonses.130 The IRS has established additional protections as a matter of administrative policy. 131 One of the early protective provisions is § 7605(b), enacted originally in 1921. 132 In current form, the section provides that taxpayers shall not “be subjected to unnecessary examination or investigations” and that taxpayers’ “books of account” shall be subject to only one inspection for each tax year unless the IRS “after investigation, notifies the taxpayer in writing that an additional inspection is necessary.” 133 The floor manager of the 1921 bill justified the measure thusly: Since these income taxes and direct taxes have been in force very general complaint has been made . . . at the repeated visits of tax examiners, who perhaps are overzealous. . . . [F]rom many of the cities of the country very bitter complaints have reached me . . . of unnecessary visits and inquisitions. . . . This section is purely in the interest of quieting all this trouble and in the interest of the peace of mind of the honest taxpayer. 134
121. I.R.C. § 7605(a). 122. Id. § 7521(a). 123. Id. § 7521(b)(1). 124. Id. § 7602(d)(1). 125. Id. § 7602(e). 126. Id. § 7611(b). 127. Id. § 7602(c). 128. Id. § 7609(a). 129. Id. § 7609(b)(1). 130. Id. § 7609(f). 131. See, e.g., IRS Establishes Five-Year Duration on Continuous Audits of Taxpayers, 25 TAX MGMT. WKLY. REP. 1811, 1811 (2006). 132. Revenue Act of 1921, ch. 136, § 1309, 42 Stat. 227, 310. 133. I.R.C. § 7605(b). 134. 61 CONG. REC. 5855 (1921) (statement of Sen. Penrose).
224
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
The interplay of § 7605(b) and the IRS’s summons was at the heart of Powell, 135 the most important case in our history as to the scope of the IRS’s investigatory power. Although the IRS issues summonses during relatively few examinations, the summons power lies behind all IRS information gathering. Taxpayers understand that, if they do not respond to informal IRS requests for information, the IRS has the ability to proceed to a summons. In Powell, the IRS was examining two income tax returns of a company of which Powell was the president. 136 The IRS summoned Powell to give testimony and produce records.137 Powell declined because the IRS had already examined the returns once before and because the normal statute of limitations on assessing deficiencies as to those returns had already expired (although the limitations period remained open if the returns were fraudulent). 138 Powell maintained that, before he could be forced to respond, it was incumbent on the IRS to state grounds for believing that the returns reflected fraud.139 The IRS refused to do so. 140 The Government brought an action in district court to enforce the summons,141 and the district court held for the Government. 142 The Third Circuit reversed.143 It reasoned that, because the returns could be adjusted only if fraudulent, § 7605(b)’s prohibition of “unnecessary examination” barred reexamination of the records unless the IRS had information “which might cause a reasonable man to suspect that there has been fraud in the return for the otherwise closed year.” 144 The Supreme Court granted certiorari because of conflict among the circuits as to the standards the IRS must meet in order to obtain judicial enforcement of its summonses.145 Although it acknowledged that a standard resembling the stringency of the circuit court’s test 135. United States v. Powell, 379 U.S. 48 (1964). 136. Id. at 49. 137. Id. 138. Id.; see also I.R.C. § 6501(a) (three-year “general” limitations period), (c)(1) (infinite limitations period in case of fraud). 139. Powell, 379 U.S. at 49. 140. Id. 141. Id. IRS summonses are not self-enforcing. In general, when a taxpayer does not comply with a summons, the Government must seek an order of enforcement. If that order is granted and not complied with, contempt of court sanctions follow. See, e.g., Reisman v. Caplin, 375 U.S. 440, 446 (1964). 142. Powell, 379 U.S. at 50. 143. Id. 144. United States v. Powell, 325 F.2d. 914, 915-16 (3d Cir. 1963), rev’d, 379 U.S. 48 (1964). 145. The conflicting circuit court cases are identified at Powell, 379 U.S. at 50, 51 & n.8.
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
225
was “possible,” 146 a 6-to-3 majority of the Court held that the IRS “need make no showing of probable cause to suspect fraud unless the taxpayer raises a substantial question that judicial enforcement of the administrative summons would be an abusive use of the court’s process.” 147 The majority supported its holding by reference to cases rejecting probable cause requirements as to summonses and subpoenas issued by other federal agencies. 148 Clearly, however, the fulcrum was the majority’s fear that a rigorous standard “might seriously hamper the [IRS] in carrying out investigations [it] thinks warranted.”149 In place of probable cause, the Powell Court erected the standard that has controlled summons enforcement cases ever since. It consists of an initial burden on the IRS, satisfaction of which causes the burden going forward to shift to the taxpayer. 150 The Government’s prima facie case consists of its establishing (typically by affidavit of the IRS examining agent) four matters: “that the investigation will be conducted pursuant to a legitimate purpose, that the inquiry may be relevant to the purpose, that the information sought is not already within the [IRS’s] possession, and that the administrative steps required by the Code have been followed.” 151 These elements are minimal, as subsequent cases have underscored. 152 Even if the IRS establishes these elements, the taxpayer or other summoned party may still “ ‘challenge the summons on any appropriate ground.’ ” 153 Illustratively, the Court noted that enforcement would be an abuse of process “if the summons had been issued for an improper purpose, such as to harass the taxpayer or to put pressure on him to settle a collateral dispute, or for any other purpose reflecting on the good faith of the particular investigation.” 154 The dominant impulse behind Powell was protection of the revenue, based on the centrality of information to IRS examination and enforcement. However, this impulse is tempered by the second stage 146. Id. at 53. 147. Id. at 51. 148. Id. at 57 (citing United States v. Morton Salt Co., 338 U.S. 632, 642-43 (1950); Okla. Press Pub. Co. v. Walling, 327 U.S. 186, 216 (1946)). For discussion of these and related cases, see Steve R. Johnson, Reasonable Relation Reassessed: The Examination of Private Documents by Federal Regulatory Agencies, 56 N.Y.U. L. REV. 742 (1981). 149. Powell, 379 U.S. at 54; see also id. at 56 (“For us to import a probable cause standard to be enforced by the courts would substantially overshoot the goal which [Congress] sought to attain.”). 150. Id. at 57-58. 151. Id. 152. See, e.g., United States v. Tex. Heart Inst., 755 F.2d 469, 474 (5th Cir. 1985). 153. Powell, 379 U.S. at 58 (quoting Reisman v. Caplin, 375 U.S. 440, 449 (1964)). 154. Id.
226
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
of the Powell test, as explained above. Moreover, the context must be considered. Summons enforcement is not a determination of the merits. 155 A pro-IRS doctrine at the investigation stage is tolerable as long as fair procedures are employed in the ensuing determination on the merits. Indeed, Powell merely reduces informational asymmetry between the parties, so that administrative and judicial determinations on the merits can be made on something approaching a level playing field. 6. Federal Tax Lien Act Assessment is a crucial act in federal taxation. Assessment is a mere mechanical act, essentially “a bookkeeping notation” by which the IRS fixes a dollar amount of liability for a particular period of a particular tax for a particular taxpayer. 156 But this mechanical act has great legal significance: the IRS has no legal authority to engage in enforced collection actions until there has been a valid assessment. 157 For the assessment to be valid, all preliminary steps prescribed by the Code must have been accomplished. Once the assessment has been made, the IRS bills the taxpayer for any amount not yet paid. If the taxpayer does not “voluntarily” pay in response to the bill, the IRS may engage in enforced collection. The IRS’s collection powers far exceed those of private creditors.158 Among the IRS’s collection tools are tax liens,159 filing notices of tax liens,160 levies on and administrative sale of property, 161 instigation of judicial sale of property, 162 and offsetting tax debts against otherwise due tax refunds. 163 Pre-assessment issues get much more attention from tax practitioners and scholars than do post-assessment issues. Nonetheless, the latter have great practical significance, not only for the taxpayers 155. See id. at 54 (noting the dubious wisdom of “forcing [the IRS] to litigate and prosecute appeals on the very subject which [it] desires to investigate”). 156. Laing v. United States, 423 U.S. 161, 170 n.13 (1976); see I.R.C. § 6203. 157. See, e.g., I.R.C. §§ 6322, 6331(a). 158. See, e.g., Steve R. Johnson, The IRS as Super Creditor, 92 TAX NOTES 655, 655 (2001). 159. The general federal tax lien attaches to “all property and rights to property” of the tax delinquent. I.R.C. § 6321. A variety of special tax liens also exist. See, e.g., id. §§ 6324(a) (estate taxes), 6324(b) (gift taxes), 6324A (estate taxes deferred under § 6166), 6324B (additional estate taxes attributable to property qualifying for special valuation under § 2032A). 160. See id. § 6323(f). Even before filing, the so-called “secret lien” is effective against the taxpayer. See, e.g., Don King Prods., Inc. v. Thomas, 945 F.2d 529, 533 (2d Cir. 1991). 161. I.R.C. §§ 6331 (levy, also sometimes called seizure or distraint), 6335 (administrative sale of property levied upon). 162. Id. § 7403. 163. See, e.g., id. § 6402(d).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
227
themselves but also for third parties. 164 Those who owe money to the IRS often owe money to others as well, and tax delinquents often coown property with persons who do not have tax debts. Accordingly, whether and how the IRS proceeds against the property of taxpayers can have powerful effects on the interests and behavior of third parties as well. The steady direction of federal tax collection law has been towards greater solicitude for the rights and interests of third parties, even to the point, in some instances, of according third party claims priority over IRS claims. The Federal Tax Lien Act is the most important landmark along this road, although neither the first nor the last. Early on, the law was highly protective of governmental revenues. Before the modern federal income tax, the Union imposed an income tax during the Civil War. That earlier income tax, too, was enforced in part by a tax lien.165 That lien was superior to the interests of third parties—even if the tax lien had not been filed and even if the third party was a subsequent bona fide purchaser. 166 However, in ensuing generations, Congress displayed “an increasing awareness of the public importance of security of titles, and of the need of certain creditors to be able to rely upon the taxpayer’s apparent unencumbered ownership of his property.”167 Part of this awareness was enlightened self-interest. Congress realized that protecting the interests of third parties in appropriate circumstances can induce them to engage in economic transactions with the tax delinquent, enhancing the ability of the delinquent to pay the IRS. Here are some of the steps in the unfolding awareness. In 1913, Congress accorded priority to purchasers, mortgagees, and judgment creditors over the IRS when notice of the federal tax lien was not properly filed in the designated office.168 In 1939, this was extended to pledgees. 169 In some instances, third parties should be protected even when the IRS has previously filed notice of its lien, either because searching the records is impracticable under the circumstances or because certain kinds of transactions should be encouraged. Thus, in 1939, Congress created superpriorities for some purchasers and for those 164. For example, federal tax liens attach to the tax debtor’s property even if notice of it is not filed. Filing affects priorities between the IRS and other creditors when the taxpayer has insufficient assets to satisfy all claims against him. See id. § 6323. 165. Act of July 13, 1866, ch. 184, § 9, 14 Stat. 98, 107; see also Act of Mar. 3, 1865, ch. 78, 13 Stat. 469, 470. 166. See United States v. Snyder, 149 U.S. 210 (1893). 167. William T. Plumb, Jr., Federal Liens and Priorities—Agenda for the Next Decade, 77 YALE L.J. 228, 229 (1967). 168. Act of March 4, 1913, ch. 166, 37 Stat. 1016 (reversing Snyder, 149 U.S. 210). 169. Revenue Act of 1939, ch. 247, § 401, 53 Stat. 862, 882-83.
228
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
lending on the security of “securities.” 170 A superpriority for purchasers of motor vehicles was established in 1964. 171 The 1966 Federal Tax Lien Act dwarfed in scope previous expansions of collection protections for third parties. Its origins lay in a decade-long study project by the American Bar Association. The 1966 Act contained important provisions related to the validity and priority of tax liens as against purchasers, security interest holders, mechanic’s lienors, and judgment creditors; release of tax liens and discharge of property from the reach of the liens; property seizures; release of tax levies and return of property levied upon; and judicial actions by the government, taxpayers, and third parties as to tax collection issues.172 A leading figure of the time described the Act thusly: Congress granted specific relief in a number of meritorious situations and, on the whole, achieved equity in a field that had been notorious for its absence. . . . Truly it could be said, to borrow a phrase used by Justice Cardozo in another connection, that a “high-minded Government renounced an advantage that was felt to be ignoble, and set up a new standard of equity and conscience.” 173
The 1966 legislation dramatically advanced the cause of fairness and economic rationality in federal tax collection, but it did not resolve all problems. 174 Incremental changes continued, and continue, to be made to the governing Code provisions. A brief survey of the safeguards as they currently stand follows. 175 Relief from tax liens: Upon request by the taxpayer or another affected person, the IRS may release the tax lien, subordinate it to other interests in or claims upon the property, discharge particular property from the lien, or certify that the lien does not attach to particular property.176 The IRS also may withdraw a filed notice of tax lien. 177 170. Id. 171. Revenue Act of 1964, Pub. L. No. 88-272, § 236, 78 Stat. 19, 127. 172. Federal Tax Lien Act of 1966, Pub. L. No. 89-719, §§ 101, 103, 104, 107-202, 80 Stat. 1125, 1125-49, reprinted at 1966-2 C.B. 623, 623-43. 173. Plumb, supra note 167, at 232-33 (quoting George Moore Ice Cream Co. v. Rose, 289 U.S. 373, 379 (1933)). 174. See id. at 297-98; William T. Plumb, Jr., Federal Liens and Priorities—Agenda for the Next Decade II, 77 YALE L.J. 605, 605 (1968); William T. Plumb, Jr., Federal Liens and Priorities—Agenda for the Next Decade III, 77 YALE L.J. 1104, 1188-89 (1968); William T. Plumb, Jr., The Tax Recommendations of the Commission on the Bankruptcy Laws—Tax Procedures, 88 HARV. L. REV. 1360, 1379-80 (1975). 175. For a more complete description, see RICHARDSON, BORISON & JOHNSON, supra note 9, at 364-75. 176. I.R.C. § 6325. 177. Id. § 6323(j).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
229
Relief from levies: Under a variety of conditions—some mandatory and some within the discretion of the IRS—the IRS may release a levy and notice of levy and may return property that has been levied on. 178 Other administrative relief: Taxpayers may secure review of collection controversies by the IRS Appeals Office through the Collection Due Process procedures 179 (with the possibility of subsequent judicial review) and through the Collection Appeals Program 180 (without the possibility of subsequent judicial review). In addition, the Office of the Taxpayer Advocate is empowered to issue Taxpayer Assistance Orders when the IRS fails to follow established collection procedures.181 Judicial remedies: Under § 7426, third parties and, in some cases, taxpayers may sue in federal district court for four kinds of relief: (1) determination that a levy is wrongful; (2) return of amounts received from sale of property in excess of tax liability; (3) obtaining funds held as substituted proceeds; and (4) determination of the IRS’s interest as to substituted proceeds. 182 Taxpayers and third parties may bring damages actions for improper collection actions by the IRS.183 In addition, a variety of ancillary judicial remedies are provided under statutes outside the Code. 184 7. Shapiro, Laing, and Jeopardy Assessment Review As seen in Part II.B.3 above, our system is committed to providing a prepayment mechanism for resolving disputes involving liability for income tax and some other kinds of taxes. But there is an obvious peril. In the years that can pass during audit, administrative appeal, and Tax Court litigation, the ability of the IRS to collect on the eventual judgment can be put at hazard. Taxpayers may secret themselves or their assets, may transfer their assets, or may become insolvent. The government’s legitimate revenue interests must be protected against such eventualities.
178. Id. § 6343. 179. Id. §§ 6320, 6330. These procedures are discussed further in Part IV infra. 180. See I.R.C. § 7123(a). 181. Id. § 7811. 182. Id. § 7426(a). 183. Id. §§ 7426(h), 7432-7433. For discussion of whether existing damages remedies should be expanded, see Steve Johnson, A Residual Damages Right Against the IRS: A Cure Worse than the Disease, 88 TAX NOTES 395 (2000); Leandra Lederman, Of Taxpayer Rights, Wrongs, and a Proposed Remedy, 87 TAX NOTES 1133 (2000); Leandra Lederman, Taxpayer Rights in the Lurch: A Response to Professor Johnson, 88 TAX NOTES 1041 (2000). 184. See, e.g., 28 U.S.C. § 2410(a) (2006) (authorizing quiet title, foreclosure, partition, condemnation, and interpleader actions).
230
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
Thus, the IRS has the power to make jeopardy and termination assessments and levies, shortcutting normal assessment and collection procedures in conditions of peril to the revenue.185 But the very power of those devices inspires concern about possible abuse. The right to adequate notice and opportunity to be heard as to governmental deprivation of property “is central to the Constitution’s command of due process.” 186 Normally, this is prior notice and opportunity to be heard. “The purpose of this requirement is not only to ensure abstract fair play to the individual. Its purpose, more particularly, is to protect his use and possession of property from arbitrary encroachment—to minimize substantively unfair or mistaken deprivations of property . . . .” 187 Post-deprivation notice and hearing are permissible only in “extraordinary situations where some valid governmental interest is at stake that justifies postponing the hearing until after the event.” 188 Due process would be traduced were the government to offer no notice and hearing at all, neither pre- nor post-deprivation. 189 In the mid-1970s, the Supreme Court decided two cases involving the then extant procedures for challenging IRS jeopardy and termination assessments. In Laing190 and Shapiro, 191 the Court expressed reservations about the constitutional adequacy of those procedures. Within a few months, Congress enacted § 7429, providing rapid and reasonably rigorous post-assessment review.192 The section: (1) requires that the IRS inform the taxpayer within five days of the reasons for the expedited assessment or levy; 193 (2) allows the taxpayer to seek review by the IRS Appeals Office of the expedited action;194 (3) permits the taxpayer, within ninety days thereafter, to seek district court or Tax Court review; 195 and (4) requires decision by the court within twenty days.196 This proceeding does not finally resolve the 185. I.R.C. §§ 6851-6852, 6861-6862. 186. United States v. James Daniel Good Real Prop., 510 U.S. 43, 53 (1993). 187. Fuentes v. Shevin, 407 U.S. 67, 80-81 (1972). 188. Id. at 82 (quoting Boddie v. Connecticut, 401 U.S. 371, 378-79 (1971)). 189. “[I]t is very doubtful that the need to collect the revenues is a sufficient reason to justify seizure causing irreparable injury without a prompt post-seizure inquiry of any kind into the [IRS’s] basis for [its] claim.” Commissioner v. Shapiro, 424 U.S. 614, 630 n.12 (1976); see also Bowles v. Willingham, 321 U.S. 503, 520 (1944). 190. Laing v. United States, 423 U.S. 161 (1976). 191. Shapiro, 424 U.S. at 629. 192. Tax Reform Act of 1976, Pub. L. No. 94-455, § 1204(a), 90 Stat. 1520, 1695 (codified at I.R.C. § 7429). 193. I.R.C. § 7429(a)(1)(B). 194. Id. § 7429(a)(2)-(3). 195. Id. § 7429(b)(1)-(2). Review may be sought in the Tax Court only if the IRS made the jeopardy assessment after a Tax Court deficiency action had already been commenced. Id. § 7429(b)(2)(B).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
231
merits.197 It addresses only whether the making of the expedited assessment and the amount of that assessment were reasonable under the circumstances. 198 Despite occasional murmurs, § 7429 is generally accepted as constitutionally adequate. This skein of our tax procedure history shows the delicate interplay of the “fair procedures for taxpayers” value and the “protect the revenue” value. The former value called into existence prepayment judicial determinations in the Tax Court as to income taxes and some other taxes. The latter value required modification, through the jeopardy and termination assessment mechanisms, of the prepayment procedures to obviate the possibility of abuse. But the former value again reared its head through § 7429, to modify the modification. 8. TEFRA Partnership Audit/Litigation Procedures Crises often provoke responses that, although dire in their nature and consequences, were necessary at the time or at least seemed so to sober persons lashed by the goad of circumstance. 199 In the 1960s through 1980s, the proliferation of tax shelters provoked a crisis in tax administration in the United States. Numerous legislative, regulatory, and judicial responses—of varying degrees of effectiveness and desirability—were called forth. One of them was the enactment of the so-called unified partnership audit and litigation procedures by the Tax Equity and Fiscal Responsibility Act of 1982 (“TEFRA”). 200 Tax shelters were designed, in the main, to generate “paper” losses that could offset real income, thus reducing the participants’ income subject to tax. Because they are “pass-through” entities, part196. Id. § 7429(b)(3). 197. The making of a termination or jeopardy assessment does not obviate the IRS’s obligation to issue a notice of deficiency triggering the opportunity for Tax Court review of the merits of the adjustments set out in the notice. In the case of a termination assessment, the notice for the full terminated tax year must be issued within sixty days after the due date of the return for the year or the date on which the return was filed. Id. § 6851(b). In the case of a jeopardy assessment, the notice must be issued within sixty days after the making of the assessment. Id. § 6861(b). 198. Id. § 7429(g). The reasonableness standard “means something more than ‘not arbitrary and capricious,’ and something less than ‘supported by substantial evidence.’ ” Harvey v. United States, 730 F. Supp. 1097, 1106 (S.D. Fla. 1990) (quoting Loretto v. United States, 440 F. Supp. 1168, 1172 (E.D. Pa. 1977)). 199. One thinks, for example, of Lincoln’s suspension of some civil liberties during the Civil War, and of, during World War II, Franklin Roosevelt’s internment of Japanese Americans, Churchill’s fire-bombing of Dresden, and Truman’s use of the atomic bomb on Hiroshima and Nagasaki. 200. Tax Equity and Fiscal Responsibility Act of 1982, Pub. L. No. 97-248, §§ 401-407, 96 Stat. 324, 648-71 (adding I.R.C. §§ 6221-6232). In ensuing years, some of the original provisions have been modified and complementary sections have been enacted. The most significant revisions came in the Taxpayer Relief Act of 1997, Pub. L. No. 105-34, §§ 12311243, 111 Stat. 788, 1020-30. The current TEFRA and related rules are in I.R.C. §§ 62216255.
232
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
nerships (including, later, limited liability companies taxable as partnerships) and, to a much lesser extent, S corporations were the vehicles through which tax shelters were structured and sold. Before TEFRA, if the IRS doubted the validity of tax benefits claimed through a partnership, the IRS was compelled to audit the returns of each partner, making common adjustments to each. However, the sheer volume of tax shelters and “investors” in them produced three serious effects. First, the audit resources of the IRS were overwhelmed. Untold tens of thousands of returns containing bogus shelter deductions were allowed to stand because the IRS was unable to audit the returns within the statute of limitations period for assessment of additional liability.201 Second, the returns the IRS was able to audit led to a volume of notices of deficiency, and petitions contesting those notices, that inundated the Tax Court.202 Third, the frenzy of activity sometimes led to a breach of horizontal equity. The same substantive items on different returns sometimes were treated differently by the IRS. 203 A new approach was needed. The IRS wanted to be able to audit at the entity (partnership) level, rather than having to audit all partners’ returns.204 The IRS sought such authority at least as early as 1978.205 When Congress acted four years later in TEFRA, it did not create a pure entity system. Instead, Congress created a mixed approach. The IRS audits the partnership return at the partnership level; the IRS issues any determination of adjustments to a person designated to represent the partnership; and that person may seek administrative and judicial review of the adjustments on behalf of the partnership. However, at each stage, all the substantial partners have notice and participation rights, preserving the potential for considerable participation by the individual partners in the audit and litigation.206
201. Normally three years from the dates on which the returns were filed. I.R.C. § 6501(a). 202. For example, between fiscal years 1978 and 1986, largely because of tax shelters, the number of petitions pending in the Tax Court rose from 23,140 to 83,686. The total rose each year and often dramatically. The 1979 increase was 16.9%, followed by a 28.9% increase in 1980 and a 31.7% increase in 1981. Harold Dubroff & Charles M. Greene, Recent Developments in the Business and Procedures of the United States Tax Court, 52 ALB. L. REV. 33, 35 (1987). Tax shelter petitions were the main drivers of these increases. 203. See, e.g., John B. Palmer III, TEFRA Treats Partnerships as Separate Entities Under Its New Procedural Rules, 58 J. TAX’N 34, 34 (1983). 204. See Jerome Kurtz, Auditing Partnerships, 134 TAX NOTES 977 (2012). 205. See, e.g., The President’s 1978 Tax Reduction and Reform Proposals: Hearing Before the H. Comm. on Ways & Means, 95th Cong., pt. 1, at 280-90 (1978). 206. See I.R.C. §§ 6223-6226. For detailed discussion of the procedures and participation rights, see RICHARDSON, BORISON & JOHNSON, supra note 9, at 161-74.
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
233
Manifold purposes were at work in the creation of the TEFRA partnership regime. The main inspiration, of course, was protecting the revenue by providing a more workable method for auditing tax shelters. 207 This was reinforced by process values, such as enhancement of accurate and consistent decisionmaking. 208 But it would be a mistake to limit the angle of vision to these values. Had they been the whole of Congress’s contemplation, they could have been achieved—and achieved better—by an unadulterated entity-based approach. Congress chose instead to impose a hybrid system including substantial notice and participation rights for partners as an essential part of the bargain.209 Thus, even in this context, Congress cared a lot about providing procedural options that were fair to taxpayers and perceived by them to be fair. 9. Brockamp and Equitable Tolling Statutes of limitations serve important functions of promoting finality and minimizing errors caused by stale evidence. But they also can erode fairness. Reflecting this tension, courts have noted that “statutes of limitations have numerous statutory and common law exceptions,” and those exceptions can “profoundly impact[] . . . strict and literal application[s] of the statute[s].” 210 One of these exceptions is equitable tolling, “a judge-made doctrine ‘which operates independently of the literal wording of the [statute]’ to suspend or extend a statute of limitations as necessary to ensure fundamental practicality and fairness.”211 At the federal level, it is rebuttably presumed that equitable tolling applies,212 and nearly all U.S. states recognize the doctrine in one form or another.213 Can equitable tolling apply when a taxpayer files a refund claim after the limitations period has passed? 214 Other than the Ninth Cir207. See, e.g., STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAX’N, 97TH CONG., GENERAL EXPLANATION OF REVENUE PROVISIONS OF THE TAX EQUITY AND FISCAL RESPONSIBILITY ACT OF 1982, at 268 (Comm. Print 1982). 208. See, e.g., A.B.A. Section of Taxation, Proposal as to Audit of Partnerships, 32 TAX LAW. 551, 551 (1979). 209. For an argument that partner participation should be increased beyond even the levels provided by TEFRA, see Don R. Spellmann, Taxation Without Notice: Due Process and Other Notice Shortcomings with the Partnership Audit Rules, 52 TAX LAW. 133 (1998). 210. Province v. Province, 473 S.E.2d 894, 903 (W. Va. 1996). 211. Lantzy v. Centex Homes, 31 Cal. 4th 363, 370 (Cal. 2003) (quoting Addison v. California, 578 P.2d 941, 943 (1978)). 212. Irwin v. Dep’t of Veterans Affairs, 498 U.S. 89, 95-96 (1990). 213. See Steve R. Johnson, Equitable Tolling in State and Local Tax Cases, 52 ST. TAX NOTES 917, 917 (2009). 214. In general, taxpayers who believe they have overpaid must file refund claims with the IRS “within 3 years from the time the return [for the year] was filed or 2 years from the time the tax was paid, whichever of such periods expires the later.” I.R.C. § 6511(a). THE
234
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
cuit, all federal circuit courts that had considered the matter said “no.” 215 In Brockamp, the Supreme Court granted certiorari to resolve this conflict. Brockamp involved two Ninth Circuit cases. In both, the taxpayers filed their refund claims well after expiration of the limitations period. In both, the taxpayers explained their failure to file timely as caused by disabilities (senility or alcoholism). In both, the circuit court accepted that the facts sufficed to trigger application of equitable tolling. The Supreme Court unanimously reversed both cases, holding that equitable tolling is not available as to tax refund claims. As a matter of statutory construction, the Court noted that “[s]ection 6511 sets forth its time limitations in unusually emphatic form . . . in a highly detailed technical manner [and] reiterates its limitations several times in several different ways.” 216 The Court also expressed concern about the impact of equitable tolling on orderly tax administration. Noting that the IRS processes over 200 million returns each year and issues over 90 million refunds, the Court remarked: To read an “equitable tolling” exception into § 6511 could create serious administrative problems by forcing the IRS to respond to, and perhaps litigate, large numbers of late claims. . . . The nature and potential magnitude of the administrative problem suggest that Congress decided to pay the price of occasional unfairness in individual cases (penalizing a taxpayer whose claim is unavoidably delayed) in order to maintain a more workable tax enforcement system. 217
Soon thereafter, Congress displayed a more liberal spirit. It partly overthrew Brockamp by enacting a limited tolling provision. The statute currently provides that the running of the normal § 6511 limitations period “shall be suspended during any period of such individual’s life that such individual is financially disabled.” 218 In general, one is financially disabled if he “is unable to manage his financial affairs by reason of a medically determinable physical or mental impairment . . . which can be expected to result in death or which has lasted or can be expected to last for a continuous period of not less than 12 months.” 219 215. The conflicting cases are cited in United States v. Brockamp, 519 U.S. 347, 348-49 (1997). 216. Id. at 350-51. 217. Id. at 352-53; see also id. at 352 (“Tax law, after all, is not normally characterized by case-specific exceptions reflecting individualized equities.”). 218. I.R.C. § 6511(h)(1). 219. Id. § 6511(h)(2)(A).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
235
This is a narrow statutory exception and has been read narrowly by the courts. 220 Cases which fall outside the narrow statutory exception are controlled by Brockamp’s “no equitable tolling” rule.221 10. IRS Restructuring and Reform Act The Internal Revenue Service Reform and Restructuring Act of 1998 (“RRA”) 222 is a particularly unlovely experience in the sausage factory. It is a story about an opportunistic Republican Senator, a spineless Democratic President, and a complicit media. Senator William Roth was in a tough reelection campaign. He decided to use his chairmanship of the Senate Finance Committee to generate favorable publicity and manufacture a campaign issue. The result was multiday hearings at which disaffected taxpayers, seemingly corroborated by disgruntled IRS employees (testifying, for dramatic effect, from behind screens to shield them from their employer’s possible retribution), testified as to IRS behavior appearing to range from callous indifference to jack-booted thuggery. President Clinton, employing his well-honed triangulation strategy, preferred to jump on the antiIRS bandwagon than to probe the worth of the assertions seriously. The media, staring at ratings gold, covered the circus enthusiastically.223 The result was a mood inside the Beltway (and even sometimes in more sober minds outside the Beltway 224) of “IRS bad; must punish bad IRS.” The result was the RRA, omnibus legislation containing numerous measures to rein in (actually or symbolically) IRS abuses. 225 The RRA “introduced seventy-one new taxpayer rights and re220. For a proposal to reform the tolling provisions, see T. Keith Fogg & Rachel E. Zuraw, Financial Disability for All (Villanova Law Sch. Pub. Law & Legal Theory Working Paper Series, Paper No. 2013-3009, 2012), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=2182772. 221. See, e.g., Haas v. United States, 107 Fed. Cl. 1, 7-8 (2012). 222. Internal Revenue Service Restructuring and Reform Act of 1998, Pub. L. No. 105206, 112 Stat. 685 (codified in various sections of the I.R.C.). 223. The story is told in greater detail in Steve R. Johnson, The Dangers of Symbolic Legislation: Perceptions and Realities of the New Burden-of-Proof Rules, 84 IOWA L. REV. 413, 446-57 (1999). See also Bryan T. Camp, Theory and Practice in Tax Administration, 29 VA. TAX REV. 227, 270 (2009) (“Congress became very concerned—one might say hysterical— . . . [and] worked itself into a lather, and mostly over the wrong problem.”). 224. A striking illustration occurred in our criminal tax jurisprudence. I.R.C. § 7212 criminalizes forcible or corrupt interference with tax administration. In a 1998 decision clearly influenced by the Senate Finance Committee hearings, the Sixth Circuit gave § 7212 a cramped reading. United States v. Kassouf, 144 F.3d 952, 958 (6th Cir. 1998) (“In this day, when Congress is attempting to curb the reach of the IRS into the homes of taxpayers, we cannot construe a penal law such as § 7212(a) to permit such an invasion into the activities of lawabiding citizens.”). A year later, the Sixth Circuit realized that the outrage of the moment had led it astray, and it limited Kassouf to its facts. United States v. Bowman, 173 F.3d 595, 600 (6th Cir. 1999). 225. For a description of the changes wrought by the RRA, see Robert Manning & David F. Windish, The IRS Restructuring and Reform Act: An Explanation, 80 TAX NOTES 83 (1998).
236
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
quired, [as of 2003], 1,900 implementation actions by the IRS.”226 Some of these measures were in fact constructive. 227 Others were partly good and partly bad. 228 Some were largely meaningless.229 Some were inimical to effective tax administration. 230 Subsequent investigations (which received far less publicity than the original allegations) were unable to confirm the veracity of the sensational testimony.231 But, in politics, perception often matters more than facts. 232 Thus, the point that matters for purposes of this agenda for reform is the value set that the RRA exercise revealed. Central to the thinking of Congress was “increas[ing] perceptions of procedural fairness by allowing taxpayers additional procedural rights and opportunities to tell their side of the story.” 233 This orientation was evident in the hearings described above and was confirmed by the legislative history. The Senate report, explaining reasons for change, was studded with remarks such as the following: “[A] key reason for taxpayer frustration with the IRS is the lack of appropriate attention to taxpayer needs.” 234 “The Committee is con226. Nina E. Olson, Taxpayer Rights, Customer Service, and Compliance: A ThreeLegged Stool, 51 U. KAN. L. REV. 1239, 1243 (2003). For description of the principal changes, see Manning & Windish, supra note 225. 227. For example, imposing an initial burden-of-production on the IRS when it asserts penalties, see Internal Revenue Service Restructuring and Reform Act of 1998, Pub. Law. No. 105-206, § 3001, 112 Stat. 685, 726 (codified at I.R.C. § 7491(c)), and strengthening the office of the National Taxpayer Advocate, see § 1102, 112 Stat. at 697 (codified at I.R.C. § 7803(c)). 228. Such as the Collection Due Process rules discussed infra Part IV.B. See § 3401, 112 Stat. at 746 (codified at I.R.C. §§ 6320, 6330). 229. Examples are the creation of the IRS Oversight Board, see § 1101, 112 Stat. at 691 (codified at I.R.C. § 7802), which has been generally insignificant in operation, and directing the IRS to revise its Mission Statement to put greater emphasis on serving the public and meeting taxpayers’ needs, see § 1002, 112 Stat. at 690. Priorities in the IRS swing between taxpayer service and enforcement (with the pendulum now more on the enforcement side), without close correlation to the current wording of the Mission Statement. 230. One example is the deceptive burden-of-proof shift provision, see § 3001, 112 Stat. at 726 (codified at I.R.C. § 7491(a)). The provision has induced taxpayers to argue the point in numerous cases, expending resources for all parties and the courts, but has almost never made a difference in how cases actually are decided. See, e.g., Johnson, supra note 223, at 427-46; see also Leandra Lederman, Does the Burden of Proof Matter?, 23 A.B.A. SEC. TAX’N NEWS Q. 10 (2004); Leandra Lederman, Unforeseen Consequences of the Burden of Proof Shift, 80 TAX NOTES 379 (1998). Similarly, the mandatory termination provisions, §§ 1201-1205, 112 Stat. at 71123 (not codified in the Code), had immediate and substantial negative effect on the morale and productivity of IRS employees. 231. See, e.g., Susan Meador Tobias, Letter to the Editor, IRS Abuse Debate Should Be a Two-Way Street, 79 TAX NOTES 1071 (1998); Stephen Barr, Report Labels IRS Testimony “Unfounded,” WASH. POST, Apr. 26, 1998, at A2. 232. Karma also matters. Despite the publicity generated by his hearings, Senator Roth lost his reelection bid. 233. Leandra Lederman & Stephen W. Mazza, Addressing Imperfections in the Tax System: Procedural or Substantive Reform?, 103 MICH. L. REV. 1423, 1441 (2005). 234. S. REP. NO. 105-174, at 8 (2d Sess. 1998).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
237
cerned that individual and small business taxpayers frequently are at a disadvantage when forced to litigate with the [IRS].” 235 Furthermore, [T]axpayers are entitled to protections in dealing with the IRS that are similar to those they would have in dealing with any other creditor. Accordingly, the Committee believes that the IRS should afford taxpayers adequate notice of collection activity and a meaningful hearing before the IRS deprives them of their property. 236
11. Ballard and Tax Court Process Ballard started out as a prosaic case 237 but ended as anything but. The IRS alleged that the taxpayers engaged in a scheme involving kickbacks that they failed to report on their federal income tax returns. 238 The taxpayers filed Tax Court petitions challenging the IRS’s determinations. The chief judge of the Tax Court assigned the cases for hearing to a special trial judge. 239 The trial lasted almost five weeks, producing a transcript exceeding 5400 pages and thousands of exhibits with hundreds of thousands of pages. The briefs reached nearly 4700 pages. The special trial judge eventually submitted a report on the consolidated cases to the chief judge as required by former Tax Court Rule 183(b).240 The chief judge assigned the cases, under the same rule, to a regular judge, who issued a decision on behalf of the court. The decision stated: “The Court agrees with and adopts the opinion of the Special Trial Judge, which is set forth below.” 241 The decision substantially upheld the IRS’s determinations. The taxpayers came to believe that the document entitled the “Opinion of the Special Trial Judge” was not, in fact, that judge’s work but that the original special trial judge’s report had been substantially modified by the regular judge or by a process of consultation between the special trial judge and the regular judge. The taxpayers filed motions with the Tax Court seeking access to the original
235. Id. at 44. 236. Id. at 67. 237. If a marathon case involving multiple fairly high-profile taxpayers, large deficiencies, and fraud penalties can so be described. The principal taxpayers were Burton Kanter, a prominent tax attorney, and Claude Ballard and Robert Lisle, both vice presidents of Prudential Life Insurance Company. 238. Ballard v. Commissioner, 321 F.3d 1037, 1038 (11th Cir. 2003). 239. The Tax Court’s nineteen regular judges are appointed by the President with the advice and consent of the Senate. I.R.C. § 7443. The chief judge of the Tax Court appoints special trial judges and may designate cases assigned to them. Id. § 7443A. 240. Ballard, 321 F.3d at 1038. 241. Investment Research Assocs., Ltd. v. Commissioner, 78 T.C.M. (CCH) 951, 963 (1999).
238
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
report or, at least, permission to place that report under seal in the record on appeal. The Tax Court denied the motions. The taxpayers appealed to the circuit courts within whose jurisdictions they resided. 242 All three appellate courts accepted the IRS’s argument that the appearance of the special trial judge’s signature on the Tax Court’s decision meant that the decision was the special trial judge’s report, and so rejected the taxpayers’ objection to the absence from the record of the original report.243 On the merits, the Seventh Circuit (over a dissent) and the Eleventh Circuit largely affirmed. The Fifth Circuit largely upheld the asserted deficiencies but reversed as to the fraud penalty. The Fifth Circuit taxpayer did not seek Supreme Court review. The Court granted certiorari as to the Seventh and Eleventh Circuit cases. The Court reversed as to the exclusion of the original report from the record.244 Justice Ginsburg wrote for the majority.245 Justice Kennedy, joined by Justice Scalia, concurred. 246 Chief Justice Rehnquist, joined by Justice Thomas, dissented.247 The majority held that the Tax Court had failed to follow its own rule. That rule, the Court held, contemplated an initial report by the special trial judge, the fact-finding of which the assigned regular judge owed deference. 248 Over time, however, the Tax Court’s practice under the rule had morphed into the regular judge treating “the special trial judge’s report essentially as an in-house draft to be worked over collaboratively by the regular judge and the special trial judge.” 249 Resolving the case on this ground, the majority found it unnecessary to address the taxpayers’ arguments that the Due Process Clause 250 and the applicable appellate review statute 251 compelled inclusion of the original report in the record on appeal. The majority’s choice of rationale may have reflected Justice Ginsburg’s well-known
242. See I.R.C. § 7482(b)(1)(A). 243. Estate of Lisle v. Commissioner, 341 F.3d 364, 384 (5th Cir. 2003); Estate of Kanter v. Commissioner, 337 F.3d 833, 840-41 (7th Cir. 2003); Ballard, 321 F.3d at 1042. 244. Ballard v. Commissioner, 544 U.S. 40 (2005). 245. Id. at 44. 246. Id. at 65. 247. Id. at 68. 248. Id. at 54. 249. Id. at 57. 250. U.S. CONST. amend. V. 251. I.R.C. § 7482(a)(1); see Brief of Amica Curiae Professor Leandra Lederman in Support of Petitioners at 2-3, Ballard v. Commissioner, 554 U.S. 40 (2005) (Nos. 03-184 & 03-1034).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
239
preference to resolve cases on the narrowest available ground, or it may have seemed the best way of letting the Tax Court down easily.252 Despite the majority’s stated rationale, other commentators 253 and I see Ballard as driven by the desire to provide fairness in judicial remedies, rather than by a technical construction of the language and history of a rule. Three facts point in this direction. First, it is striking that the Court granted certiorari in this case in the first place. There was no circuit conflict; the Fifth, Seventh, and Eleventh Circuits were in agreement as to the procedural issue. “It is likely that the Supreme Court granted certiorari out of a concern that the lack of transparency denied meaningful appellate review.” 254 Second, the majority picked its rationale in disregard of its accustomed practice. The rule construction argument was not made in the taxpayers’ circuit court briefs, in their certiorari petitions, or in their questions presented. The Court typically does not consider such arguments. 255 Something was going on beneath the surface. Third, although seemingly an exercise in rule construction, the majority opinion is peppered with words and phrases like “transparent,” 256 “undisclosed,” 257 “impedes fully informed appellate review,”258 and “concealment.” 259 Here the subtext is more revealing than the text. The Court remanded the cases, unfortunately without clear instructions. 260 The course on remand was not smooth. The three in252. Telling a court that it is violating due process is a serious move. On the other hand, it may be an even greater affront to tell a court that it doesn’t understand what its own rule says. One of the arguments made by the dissent was that the Tax Court’s interpretation of its own rule was due substantial deference by analogy to Bowles v. Seminole Rock & Sand Co., 325 U.S. 410, 414 (1945). See Ballard, 544 U.S. at 70 (Rehnquist, C.J., dissenting). The majority grudgingly conceded that “the Tax Court is not without leeway in interpreting its own Rules,” id. at 59, but found deference inappropriate because the Tax Court’s construction of the rule at issue was “arbitrary,” id. at 61. For discussion of this principle, see Steve R. Johnson, Auer/Seminole Rock Deference in the Tax Court, 11 PITT. TAX REV. (forthcoming 2013). 253. See, e.g., Katherine Kmiec Turner, No More Secrets: Under Ballard v. Commissioner, Special Trial Judge Reports Must Be Revealed, 26 J. NAT’L ASS’N ADMIN. L. JUDGES 247, 294 (2006) (“From the public’s perspective, Ballard ensures less secrecy and a fair trial.”). 254. Robin L. Greenhouse & Joshua D. Odintz, The Status of Tax Court Special Trial Judge Reports After Ballard: Where Do We Go From Here?, 102 J. TAX’N 352, 355 (2005). 255. See, e.g., DeShaney v. Winnebago Cnty. Dep’t of Soc. Servs., 489 U.S. 189, 195 n.2 (1989). This prompted Chief Justice Rehnquist to remark in his Ballard dissent: “Only by failing to abide by our own Rules can the Court hold that the Tax Court failed to follow its Rules.” 544 U.S. at 68 n.1 (Rehnquist, C.J., dissenting). 256. Ballard, 544 U.S. at 55 (majority opinion). 257. Id. at 57. 258. Id. at 59-60. 259. Id. at 62 n.15. 260. Justice Kennedy’s concurrence attempted to make good the deficiency of the majority’s opinion. Id. at 65-68 (Kennedy, J., concurring).
240
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
volved circuit courts remanded the cases to the Tax Court with instructions to review the matter in accordance with the Supreme Court’s opinion and to give due regard to the determinations in the special trial judge’s original report.261 The Tax Court rendered a decision which adhered in significant part to its prior view, that is, that the taxpayers were liable for large deficiencies and for fraud penalties.262 Again, the taxpayers appealed. The circuit courts were not pleased with the Tax Court’s work. Each concluded that the Tax Court again failed to give due deference to the special trial judge’s determinations. They again remanded, this time with instructions that the Tax Court adopt as its decision the special trial judge’s original decision holding for the taxpayers. 263 12. Administrative Law in Tax Authority in tax is a three-legged stool, consisting of statutes, case law, and administrative guidance. The last leg includes Treasury regulations, which have force-of-law status if they reasonably implement the statute,264 and a variety of lesser guidance documents,265 which typically are not binding but may have persuasive influence.266 Given the importance of administrative guidance, administrative law would seem to be important in tax. It is, but the tax community has recognized this only slowly and grudgingly. 267 For most of our tax history, courts reviewing challenges to tax regulations or practices steered clear of general administrative law, developing instead a taxspecific jurisprudence emphasizing reasonableness in general and a number of hallmarks of reliability in particular. 268 261. Estate of Lisle v. Commissioner, 431 F.3d 439 (5th Cir. 2005); Ballard v. Commissioner, 429 F.3d 1026 (11th Cir. 2005); Estate of Kanter v. Commissioner, 406 F.3d 933 (7th Cir. 2005). 262. Estate of Kanter v. Commissioner, 93 T.C.M. (CCH) 721 (2007). 263. Kanter v. Commissioner, 590 F.3d 410, 414 (7th Cir. 2009); Estate of Lisle v. Commissioner, 541 F.3d 595, 597 (5th Cir. 2008); Ballard v. Commissioner, 522 F.3d 1229, 1255 (11th Cir. 2008). 264. See, e.g., Helvering v. R.J. Reynolds Tobacco Co., 306 U.S. 110, 115 (1939); Boulez v. Commissioner, 810 F.2d 209, 212 (D.C. Cir. 1987), cert. denied, 484 U.S. 896 (1987). 265. For description of many types of such documents, see RICHARDSON, BORISON & JOHNSON, supra note 9, at 17-25. 266. See, e.g., Kristin E. Hickman, IRB Guidance: The No Man’s Land of Tax Code Interpretation, 2009 MICH. ST. L. REV. 239. 267. See, e.g., Leandra Lederman, “Civil”izing Tax Procedure: Applying General Federal Learning to Statutory Notices of Deficiency, 30 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 183, 183 (1996). This phenomenon has been called—and described as—“tax exceptionalism.” See Kristin E. Hickman, The Need for Mead: Rejecting Tax Exceptionalism in Judicial Deference, 90 MINN. L. REV. 1537 (2006). 268. See, e.g., Nat’l Muffler Dealers Ass’n v. United States, 440 U.S. 472, 477 (1979) (identifying six factors); Laurens Williams, The Preparation and Promulgation of Treasury Department Regulations Under the Internal Revenue Code of 1954, TAX EXEC., Jan. 1956, at
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
241
To regularize administrative practice among the numerous federal agencies, Congress enacted the Administrative Procedure Act (“APA”) in 1946. Treasury and the IRS are “agencies” as defined by the APA 269 and so are subject to its requirements. Nonetheless, for decades, both the APA 270 and general principles of administrative law 271 appeared only rarely in tax decisions. The frequency of appearance of administrative law doctrines in tax has increased markedly in the last fifteen years, in part because of the RRA. Some of the areas at issue involved rights created or expanded by the RRA, such as the CDP rules 272 and spousal relief.273 The greatest recent prominence of administrative law in tax, however, has been in two areas: the procedural validity of Treasury regulations and deference doctrine. Both are discussed below. For generations, tax regulations promulgated by the Treasury have been attacked by taxpayers discomfited by them. The standard attacks have been substantive in nature: that the regulation in question was inconsistent with the text, structure, or purpose of the relevant statute or with important extrinsic norms. 274 In recent years, however, taxpayers have added procedural arrows to their quivers.275 The use of these weapons is still in relative infancy. Here are examples of that use. First, subject to certain exceptions, the APA prescribes that in order for it to promulgate binding rules, an agency must first publish notice of its proposed rulemaking and give interested persons opportunity to submit comments. 276 Treasury, 3, 9-11 (1956). 269. 5 U.S.C. § 551(1) (2012). 270. See, e.g., Wing v. Commissioner, 81 T.C. 17, 28-29 (1983); Wendland v. Commissioner, 79 T.C. 355 (1982). 271. One area in which the analogy to general administrative law was made involved whether the IRS has a judicially enforceable duty to treat similarly situated taxpayers similarly. See Steve R. Johnson, An IRS Duty of Consistency: The Failure of Common Law Making and a Proposed Legislative Solution, 77 TENN. L. REV. 563 (2010) (reviewing the cases and commentary); Lawrence Zelenak, Should Courts Require the Internal Revenue Service to be Consistent?, 38 TAX L. REV. 411 (1985). 272. See, e.g., Robinette v. Commissioner, 123 T.C. 85 (2004), rev’d, 439 F.3d 455 (8th Cir. 2006); Kitchen Cabinets, Inc. v. United States, 87 A.F.T.R.2d (RIA) 1393 (N.D. Tex. 2001); Mesa Oil, Inc. v. United States, 86 A.F.T.R.2d (RIA) 7312 (D. Colo. 2000); see also Danshera Cords, Administrative Law and Judicial Review of Tax Collection Decisions, 52 ST. LOUIS U. L.J. 429, 440 (2008); Diane L. Fahey, Is the United States Tax Court Exempt from Administrative Law Jurisprudence when Acting as a Reviewing Court?, 58 CLEV. ST. L. REV. 603, 609 (2010). 273. See, e.g., Wilson v. Commissioner, 99 T.C.M. (CCH) 1552 (2010), aff’d, 705 F.3d 980 (9th Cir. 2013). 274. See Steve R. Johnson, Preserving Fairness in Tax Administration in the Mayo Era, 32 VA. TAX REV. 269 (2012). 275. See, e.g., Steve R. Johnson, Intermountain and the Importance of Administrative Law in Tax Law, 128 TAX NOTES 837 (2010). 276. 5 U.S.C. § 553(c), (d) (2012).
242
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
however, may not always honor these requirements in promulgating tax regulations.277 This argument has been presented in a number of recent high-profile tax cases.278 Second, under the APA, courts are empowered to strike down agency action that is “arbitrary, capricious, an abuse of discretion, or otherwise not in accordance with law.” 279 Under current doctrine, an agency’s rule can be arbitrary for a number of reasons, including that the agency relied on factors Congress did not want it to consider, the agency failed to take some important factor into account, or the agency gave an unjustifiable or implausible explanation for its action. 280 Among these, the “inadequate explanation” strand has received considerable attention recently. Cases 281 and commentary 282 are applying this strand to tax regulations with increasing frequency. Third, in general, “retroactive [tax] regulations are prohibited, except under limited circumstances.” 283 The meaning of retroactivity and the permitted exceptions to the prohibition of it potentially are at issue in a number of tax controversies. Retroactivity questions were raised, but avoided by the Supreme Court, in the recent Home Concrete decision.284 Inevitably, retroactivity issues will have to be squarely addressed in future tax cases. Deference doctrine entails the extent to which courts, as they interpret statutes, must or should accede to the views of the statutes’ meanings espoused by the agencies charged with implementing the statutes. Deference issues go back generations, but their promi-
277. See Kristin E. Hickman, A Problem of Remedy: Responding to Treasury’s (Lack of) Compliance with Administrative Procedure Act Rulemaking Requirements, 76 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 1153 (2008); Kristin E. Hickman, Coloring Outside the Lines: Examining Treasury’s (Lack of) Compliance with Administrative Procedure Act Rulemaking Requirements, 82 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1727 (2007). 278. See, e.g., Cohen v. United States, 650 F.3d 717, 721 (D.C. Cir. 2011); Intermountain Ins. Serv. of Vail, LLC v. Commissioner, 134 T.C. 211, 220-23 (2010), rev’d, 650 F.3d 691 (D.C. Cir. 2011), vacated, 132 S. Ct. 2120 (2012). 279. 5 U.S.C. § 706(2)(A) (2012). 280. Motor Vehicles Mfrs. Ass’n v. State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co., 463 U.S. 29, 43 (1983). 281. See, e.g., Dominion Resources, Inc. v. United States, 681 F.3d 1313, 1319 (Fed. Cir. 2012); Mannella v. Commissioner, 631 F.3d 115, 127 (3d Cir. 2011) (Ambro, J., dissenting); Fla. Bankers Ass’n v. U.S. Dep’t of Treasury, 2014-1 U.S. Tax Cas. (CCH) ¶ 50,133 (D.D.C. 2014); Carpenter Family Invs., LLC v. Commissioner, 136 T.C. 373, 395-96 (2011). 282. See, e.g., Patrick J. Smith, The APA’s Reasoned-Explanation Rule and IRS Deficiency Notices, 134 TAX NOTES 331 (2012). 283. Marriott Int’l Resorts, L.P. v. United States, 83 Fed. Cl. 291, 303 (2008), aff’d, 586 F.3d 962 (Fed. Cir. 2009); see I.R.C. § 7805(b), (e). 284. United States v. Home Concrete & Supply, LLC, 132 S. Ct. 1836 (2012). Compare Brief for the United States at 12, 132 S. Ct. 1836 (2012) (No. 11-139), with Brief for Respondents at 45-48, 132 S. Ct. 1836 (2012) (No. 11-139).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
243
nence has grown exponentially since the Supreme Court’s 1984 Chevron decision. 285 The extent to which Chevron or other doctrines of deference should operate in tax was controversial for decades, but now is moving towards greater clarity. In its 2011 Mayo decision, the Supreme Court held that, in general, Chevron provides the applicable standard when a tax regulation is challenged on substantive grounds, regardless of whether the regulation was promulgated under the general authority of I.R.C. § 7805(a) or specific authority set out in more particular sections of the Code. 286 Numerous details remain to be filled in as to both regulations and sub-regulation tax guidance documents, but Mayo sets the general frame for future discussions. 287 Thus, the profile of administrative law in tax has been raised dramatically and, I believe, irreversibly. What values does this trend further? The APA was a balance of “green light” and “red light” features. In some respects, the goal was to facilitate agency actions while, in other respects, the idea was to prevent agencies from trampling on citizens’ rights. 288 More specifically, the APA’s notice-and-comment rules are designed to improve the accuracy with which regulations implement congressional intent, to minimize unnecessary regulatory burdens, to provide interested parties meaningful participation in the rulemaking process, and to raise citizen confidence in government.289 Deference doctrine is designed to improve accuracy through bringing to bear agency expertise while preserving the role of the courts to keep agencies within their legitimate domains. 290 The increased prominence of administrative law in tax honors these objectives.291
285. Chevron U.S.A. Inc. v. Natural Res. Def. Council, Inc., 467 U.S. 837 (1984). Chevron is the most frequently cited case in American law. See STEPHEN G. BREYER, RICHARD B. STEWART, CASS R. SUNSTEIN & MATTHEW L. SPITZER, ADMINISTRATIVE LAW AND REGULATORY POLICY: PROBLEMS, TEXT, AND CASES 289 (5th ed. 2002). 286. Mayo Found. for Med. Educ. & Research v. United States, 131 S. Ct. 704, 714 (2011); see also Halbig v. Sebelius, 2014-1 U.S. Tax Cas. (CCH) ¶ 50,138 (D.D.C. 2014). 287. For evaluation of the significance of Mayo and appraisal of post-Mayo issues, see Johnson, supra note 274; Steve R. Johnson, Mayo and the Future of Tax Regulations, 130 TAX NOTES 1547 (2011); Leandra Lederman & Stephen W. Mazza, More Mayo Please? Temporary Regulations After Mayo Foundation v. United States, 31 A.B.A. SEC. TAX’N NEWS Q. 15 (2011); David J. Shakow, Who’s Afraid of the APA?, 134 TAX NOTES 825 (2012). 288. See ALFRED C. AMAN, JR., ADMINISTRATIVE LAW AND PROCESS: CASES AND MATERIALS 19-24 (2d ed. 2006). 289. See, e.g., Am. Hosp. Ass’n v. Bowen, 834 F.2d 1037, 1044 (D.C. Cir. 1987). 290. See Chevron, 467 U.S. at 864-65. 291. See, e.g., Leslie Book, A New Paradigm for IRS Guidance: Ensuring Input and Enhancing Participation, 12 FLA. TAX REV. 517 (2012); Rimma Tsvasman, Note, No More Excuses: A Case for the IRS’s Full Compliance with the Administrative Procedure Act, 76 BROOK. L. REV. 837 (2011).
244
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
C. Criteria What do we learn from the above key events? Important affairs over time rarely reveal the hand of only a single cause or influence. So it is here. Multiple purposes are evident in the legislative, regulatory, and judicial developments shaping tax procedure. The history shows four sets of values at work: (1) providing remedies for taxpayers and third parties that are both meaningful and perceived to be fair; (2) protecting revenue collection from unreasonable interference; (3) achieving decisional accuracy; and (4) promoting process efficiency, reducing costs and delays. Professor, later Judge, Sneed developed a number of criteria driving federal income tax policy generally. As is the approach in this Article, Sneed developed his topoi from distillation of our national experience rather than from his own values preferences. In his view, “the legislative, administrative, and judicial history of the federal income tax, as well as the pertinent literature, reveals the existence of seven pervasive purposes which have shaped its rates and structure.”292 Sneed identified these seven purposes thusly: (1) to supply adequate revenue, (2) to achieve a practical and workable income tax system, (3) to impose equal taxes upon those who enjoy equal incomes, (4) to assist in achieving economic stability, (5) to reduce economic inequality, (6) to avoid impairment of the operation of the market-oriented economy and (7) to accomplish a high degree of harmony between the income tax and the soughtfor political order. 293
Of these, the first, second, and seventh purposes bear with particular force on federal tax procedure. Taken as a whole, the value most strongly evident in the key events is providing remedies: mechanisms by which taxpayers and affected third parties may challenge IRS liability determinations and collection actions, mechanisms that are both efficacious and perceived to be fair. Henceforth, this Article will sometimes describe this as the Primary Value. The remaining desiderata will sometimes be called Second-Order Values. The Primary Value, then, will be the first criterion against which to measure the desirability of current features of the federal tax litigation system and of proposed changes to it. But, in practical affairs, single values rarely are absolute. At some point, the accumulation
292. Joseph T. Sneed, The Criteria of Federal Income Tax Policy, 17 STAN. L. REV. 567, 568 (1965). 293. Id. (emphasis in original).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
245
of powerful contrary consequences can overwhelm even highly cherished values. 294 Thus, there are two circumstances in which our evaluation of features and proposed changes will turn on Second-Order Values. First, there are some situations in which the Primary Value is not reasonably at stake. Second-Order Values will be decisive when the adequacy of remedies would not be either meaningfully advanced or meaningfully threatened by the current feature or the proposed change. Furthermore, there may be instances in which a trickle of remedies is outweighed by a torrent of revenue protection, decisional accuracy, or efficiency. In cases of stark disproportion, large Second-Order effects should be permitted to defeat small Primary effects. The following parts of this Article will apply the above criteria in several areas. Left to my own devices, I would weigh the criteria somewhat differently. Specifically, process efficiency shines brighter in my own constellation of values.295 For example, I am more inclined than Congress has been to say that taxpayers must live with the consequences of their choices, even if the consequences include losing opportunities to litigate.296 Efficiency also often has a preferred place for me relative to decisional accuracy. I share Justice Brandeis’ conviction that often it is more important that a question of “law be settled than that it be settled right.” 297 In addition, Congress has shown the ready ability to reverse tax decisions—both of the Supreme Court 298 and lower 294. For example, the Roman declaration “fiat justicia ruat coelem” (let justice be done even if the sky falls) is stirring but not a practical reality. No matter how much we aspire to do justice, every legal system makes decisions that subordinate the pursuit of justice to other values in some circumstances. 295. For example, I was among the few defenders of the Tax Court’s practice that the Supreme Court invalidated in Ballard v. Commissioner, 544 U.S. 40 (2005), discussed in Part II.B.11 supra. See Steve R. Johnson, Further Thoughts on Kanter and Ballard, 105 TAX NOTES 1235 (2004) (arguing that protection of the Tax Court’s decisional process was more important than doubtful gains to fairness or decisional accuracy). 296. For example, as discussed in Part II.B supra, in responding to the IRS’s plea for procedural help in auditing tax shelter partnerships, Congress in 1982 created entity-level audit combined with partner participation. As argued below, this hybridization has been the cause of great complication and confusion. To me, it would have been reasonable to dispense with partner participation, on the ground that the partners’ choice to conduct business in entity form should remit them to only entity-level procedures. 297. Burnet v. Coronado Oil & Gas Co., 285 U.S. 393, 406 (1932) (Brandeis, J., dissenting). Brandeis seemingly was paraphrasing—but with some difference in emphasis— Justice Swayne’s observation generations earlier in Gilman v. Philadelphia, 70 U.S. (3 Wall.) 713, 724 (1865) (“It is almost as important that the law should be settled . . . as that it should be settled correctly.”). I am indebted to my colleague Adam Hirsch for bringing Gilman to my attention. 298. See, e.g., Gitlitz v. Commissioner, 531 U.S. 206 (2001), superseded by statute, I.R.C. § 108(d)(7)(A). This Article has identified several Supreme Court decisions later overturned by Congress. See United States v. Brockamp, 519 U.S. 347 (1997) (see supra notes 210-17 and accompanying text); Cary v. Curtis, 44 U.S. (3 How.) 236 (1845) (see su-
246
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
courts 299—with which it disagrees. Courts should, of course, strive assiduously to reach results that correctly apply the provisions of the Code, but the possibility of legislative correction buffers the consequences in those instances in which such efforts come up short. Thus, my own criteria would accord efficiency concerns higher priority. I acknowledge the possibility that my personal values preferences may compromise the dispassion I hope to apply in reading the historical record. This is an ever present peril.300 Some scholars suggest that facts about the past are without meaning until they are woven into a story by the historian. Thus, in choosing which facts to emphasize and how to interpret them, the historian will often make choices based upon factors extrinsic to pure research. Although history is continuously refined through testing hypotheses against the facts, the story it tells will be decisively influenced by the “meta-theories,” the overarching views of the world, held by the historian. 301
However, the exercise in this Article is to apply faithfully to procedural choices the values that emerge from the system as it has developed, not the system as I might wish it had developed. 302 III. REFORMS AS TO AVAILABLE COURTS Based on the criteria developed in Part II, I advance three suggestions as to the courts that should be available as fora in which to litigate federal tax controversies. First, the Tax Court should be given pra notes 49-58 and accompanying text); Elliott v. Swartwout, 35 U.S. (10 Pet.) 137 (1836) (see supra notes 43-48 and accompanying text). 299. See, e.g., Commissioner v. Ewing, 439 F.3d 1009 (9th Cir. 2006), superseded by statute, I.R.C. § 6015(e)(1)(A); Commissioner v. United States & Int’l Sec. Corp., 130 F.2d 894 (3rd Cir. 1942), superseded by statute, Revenue Act of 1942, Pub. L. No. 77-753, § 116, 56 Stat. 798, 812; Cole v. Commissioner, 81 F.2d 485 (9th Cir. 1935), superseded by statute, Revenue Act of 1938, Pub. L. No. 75-552, §51(b), 52 Stat. 447, 476; Container Corp. v. Commissioner, 134 T.C. 122 (2010), aff’d, 2011 WL 1664358 (5th Cir. May 2, 2011), superseded by statute, I.R.C. § 861(a)(9). 300. As it is, for example, when judges apply legislative history. “It sometimes seems that citing legislative history is still, as my late colleague Harold Leventhal once observed, akin to ‘looking over a crowd and picking out your friends.’ ” Patricia M. Wald, Some Observations on the Use of Legislative History in the 1981 Supreme Court Term, 68 IOWA L. REV. 195, 214 (1983). 301. William N. Eskridge, Jr., Dynamic Statutory Interpretation, 135 U. PA. L. REV. 1479, 1510 (1987) (citing William E. Nelson, History and Neutrality in Constitutional Adjudication, 72 VA. L. REV. 1237, 1240-45 (1986); G. Edward White, The Text, Interpretation, and Critical Standards, 60 TEX. L. REV. 569, 569 (1982)). 302. Fitzerald described Omar Khayyam as “preferring rather to soothe the Soul . . . into Acquiescence with Things as he saw them, than to perplex it with vain disquietude after what they might be.” OMAR KHAYYÁM, THE RUBÁIYÁT OF OMAR KHAYYÁM 18 (Edward Fitzgerald trans., Three Sirens Press 1st ed. n.d.) (emphasis in original). That was an inaccurate description of the great Tent Maker. It is a fair description of the approach of this Article.
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
247
quasi-plenary, but nonexclusive, civil tax jurisdiction. Second, calls to create a national court of tax appeals should continue to be rejected. Third, the Court of Federal Claims should be divested of jurisdiction to hear tax cases. These suggestions are developed below. A. Tax Court Jurisdiction The jurisdiction of the ancestors of the Tax Court initially was limited to deficiency actions, but the Tax Court’s jurisdiction has expanded—piecemeal, but substantially—in ensuing decades. Nonetheless, holes remain in this patchwork quilt. Almost all these holes should be filled. I propose that Congress grant the Tax Court nearly plenary jurisdiction over civil tax controversies. Discussed below are: (1) expansions of the Tax Court’s jurisdiction beyond deficiency actions; (2) areas that remain outside the Tax Court’s jurisdiction; (3) areas to which that jurisdiction should be expanded; and (4) limits on such expansion. 1. Historical Growth of Tax Court Jurisdiction As discussed in Part II.B.3, what is now the United States Tax Court had its roots as an administrative agency, then morphed into an Article I court. As an Article I court, it is fundamental that “[t]he Tax Court is a court of limited jurisdiction and may exercise its jurisdiction only to the extent authorized by Congress.” 303 The Tax Court does not have authority to enlarge upon its statutory grants of jurisdiction.304 Starting from its original deficiency jurisdiction, the Tax Court’s jurisdiction has grown over the generations. In some instances, the Tax Court’s new jurisdiction over particular types of actions is exclusive. In other instances, such jurisdiction is concurrent with that of the district courts or the Court of Federal Claims. The Tax Court’s expanded jurisdiction includes TEFRA actions,305 Collection Due Process actions, 306 and jeopardy assessment review,307 303. Kasper v. Commissioner, 137 T.C. 37, 40 (2011); see also Cohen v. Commissioner, 139 T.C. 299 (2012); Judge v. Commissioner, 88 T.C. 1175, 1180-81 (1987); Naftel v. Commissioner, 85 T.C. 527, 529 (1985). 304. See, e.g., Phillips Petroleum Co. v. Commissioner, 92 T.C. 885, 888 (1989). This principle has had play in many areas, including whether the Tax Court has authority to apply equitable doctrines such as equitable recoupment. See, e.g., Leandra Lederman, Equity and the Article I Court: Is the Tax Court’s Exercise of Equitable Powers Constitutional?, 5 FLA. TAX REV. 357 (2001). It has since been confirmed that the Tax Court has such authority. I.R.C. § 6214(b). 305. I.R.C. §§ 6225(b), 6226(a), 6228(a)(1), 6234(c), 6246(b), 6247(a), 6252(a). 306. Id. § 6330(d); see, e.g., Brian Isaacson & Karen Phu, Jurisdiction in the Tax Court to Hear Section 6330 Challenges: A Need for Clarification, PRAC. TAX LAW., Spring 2008, at 27; Carlton M. Smith, The Tax Court Keeps Growing Its Collection Due Process Powers, 133 TAX NOTES 859 (2011).
248
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
all of which are discussed in greater detail elsewhere in this Article. In addition, Congress has granted the Tax Court authority to issue declaratory judgments in a variety of contexts, including declaratory judgments as to qualification of certain retirement plans, 308 valuation of gifts, 309 tax-exempt status of state and local bonds,310 eligibility for deferred payment of estate tax, 311 and eligibility of organizations for tax-exempt status. 312 The Tax Court also has received jurisdiction to review a variety of other actions and determinations by the IRS. These include decisions as to interest abatement, 313 redetermination of interest assessed on deficiencies, 314 restraint of premature assessment or collection,315 review of proposed sales of seized property, 316 determination of employment status of workers, 317 determinations of awards for tax whistleblowers,318 review of transferee liability, 319 and IRS decisions not to grant equitable spousal relief.320 In general, the pace of expansions of the Tax Court’s jurisdiction has accelerated. After slow growth for generations, such expansions have been occurring more often since the 1980s, inspired in part by the Taxpayer Rights movement. 321 The expansions have reflected the desire of Congress to enhance remedies for taxpayers, further judicial economy, and enhance procedural flexibility.322
307. I.R.C. § 7429(b)(2); see TAX CT. R. 56. 308. I.R.C. § 7476(a). 309. Id. § 7477(a). 310. Id. § 7478(a). 311. Id. § 7479(a). 312. Id. § 7428(a). 313. Id. § 6404(h)(1). 314. Id. § 7481(c); see TAX CT. R. 261. 315. I.R.C. § 6213(a); see TAX CT. R. 55. 316. I.R.C. § 6863(b); see TAX CT. R. 57. 317. I.R.C. § 7436(a). 318. Id. § 7623(b)(4); see, e.g., Cohen v. Commissioner, 139 T.C. 299, 304 (2012); Kasper v. Commissioner, 137 T.C. 37, 41 (2011). 319. I.R.C. § 6901(a). 320. Id. § 6015(e)(1)(A). 321. This movement included enactment of several Taxpayer Bills of Rights as well as pro-taxpayer sections in other measures. See, e.g., Omnibus Taxpayer Bill of Rights, enacted as Tit. VI, Subtit. J of Technical and Miscellaneous Revenue Act of 1988, Pub. L. No. 100-647, 102 Stat. 3342, 3730; Taxpayer Bill of Rights 2, Pub. L. No. 104-168, 110 Stat. 1452 (1996); Taxpayer Bill of Rights 3, enacted as Tit. III of Internal Revenue Service Restructuring and Reform Act of 1998, Pub. L. No. 105-206, 112 Stat. 685, 726. 322. See, e.g., F. Brook Voght, Amended Tax Court Rules Reflect New Jurisdiction and Goal of Increased Efficiency, 73 J. TAX’N 404, 404 (1990).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
249
2. Areas Where the Tax Court Lacks Jurisdiction In the pre-assessment context, perhaps the most significant subject over which the Tax Court lacks jurisdiction is refund suits. When the Tax Court has acquired jurisdiction in a deficiency action, it might conclude that, not only is there no deficiency for the tax year(s) at issue, but also that there had been an overpayment for the year(s). The Tax Court has jurisdiction to determine such overpayment and to command that it be refunded. 323 The Tax Court does not, however, have jurisdiction to hear free-standing refund actions. In the post-assessment context, the Tax Court’s jurisdiction over collection matters is limited. In the main, it can hear some collection matters but only if a Collection Due Process case is properly before it.324 In addition, there are several categories of actions that Congress has authorized to be brought in district court but not in Tax Court. These include a wide variety of suits by the government in aid of enforcement, 325 taxpayer suits to contest assessable penalties, 326 suits by taxpayers and others to quash IRS summons or other information gathering,327 and miscellaneous other taxpayer actions. 328 3. Where to Expand Tax Court Jurisdiction and Where Not to Expand The current jurisdiction of the Tax Court resembles a cloak with many holes of varying sizes. As seen above, the pattern is the product of history, not rationality. This hit-and-miss arrangement guarantees the existence of traps for the unwary. Taxpayers regularly discover
323. I.R.C. §§ 6214(a), 6512(b); see TAX CT. R. 260. 324. I.R.C. § 6330. 325. E.g., I.R.C. §§ 7323(a) (action to enforce forfeiture), 7402(a) (miscellaneous actions), 7403(a) (lien enforcement action), 7404 (estate tax enforcement action), 7405(a) (erroneous refund recovery action), 7407(a) (return preparer enforcement action), 7409(a)(1) (action to enjoin political expenditures), 7611(c)(2)(A)(ii) (government action as to church tax investigation). 326. E.g., id. §§ 6679(b) (penalty for failure to file foreign returns), 6693(d) (penalty as to retirement accounts), 6694(c)(2) (preparer penalty), 6696(b) (review of penalties under §§ 6694, 6695, 6695A), 6698 (penalty for failure to file partnership return), 6699(d) (penalty for failure to file S corporation return), 6703(b), (c)(2) (penalties under §§ 6700, 6701, 6702), 6706(c) (original-issue-discount information penalty), 6707A(d)(2) (failure to rescind § 6707A penalty), 6713(c) (penalty as to disclosure by return preparer). 327. E.g., id. §§ 982(c)(2)(B) (proceeding to quash formal document request), 6038A(e)(4)(C) (proceeding to quash summons as to foreign-owned corporations), 6038C(d)(4) (proceeding to quash summons as to foreign corporation engaged in a U.S. trade on business), 7609(h)(1) (action to quash third-party summons), 7611(c)(2)(A)(i) (taxpayer action as to church tax investigation). 328. E.g., id. §§ 6402(g) (review of § 6402 reduction), 7426(a) (taxpayer and third party actions as to collection).
250
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
that they have no Tax Court remedy, despite the fact that the cause is a core tax matter and is well within the competence of the court.329 The logic behind creation of the Tax Court supports extending the court’s jurisdiction. As seen in Part II.B.3 above, the Tax Court was created to bring special expertise to bear and to develop a nationally uniform body of tax law. Tax Court judges—by virtue of their preappointment backgrounds and their tax-only dockets—are more technically expert in tax than are the generalist judges of the district courts, the bankruptcy courts, and the partly-tax/partly-nontax Court of Federal Claims. This expertise differential is not confined to deficiency cases. It extends, in varying degrees, to all tax matters. For example, there is no reason why the Tax Court should not be able to hear refund suits. The same substantive issues arise in both deficiency and refund suits. Some procedural issues are unique to refund cases.330 However, many Tax Court judges are likely to have handled refund cases before their elevation to the bench, and most district court judges decide tax refund procedural issues quite rarely. The Tax Court already has refund jurisdiction incident to its deficiency jurisdiction. 331 It should have independent refund jurisdiction as well. In addition, the Tax Court should have widespread jurisdiction as to tax collection controversies. Such controversies often do entail application of state property and other laws, for example, in the determination of the property interests possessed by the tax delinquent 332 and in assessing the validity and priority of competing claims of third parties.333 It is sometimes thought that district courts, which deal with state law more regularly, have an advantage over the Tax Court in this regard. However, practicing tax lawyers—which are what most Tax Court judges once were—are often required to work with state property laws. 334 Moreover, Tax Court judges routinely work with state 329. See, e.g., Roberts v. Commissioner, 103 T.C.M. (CCH) 1787 (2012) (holding that the Tax Court lacks jurisdiction to review applications of overpayments made pursuant to § 6402); Adrianne Hodgkins, Getting a Second Chance: The Need for Tax Court Jurisdiction Over IRS Denials of Relief Under Section 66, 65 LA. L. REV. 1167, 1167 (2005) (“[I]f the taxpayer filed a separate return while living in a community property state, the Tax Court will not review of denial [sic] [joint-and-several liability] relief under section 66 of the Code because Congress failed to give the Tax Court jurisdiction over such denials.”). 330. See RICHARDSON, BORISON & JOHNSON, supra note 9, ch. 9. 331. I.R.C. § 6214. 332. See, e.g., Steve R. Johnson, After Drye: The Likely Attachment of the Federal Tax Lien to Tenancy-by-the-Entireties Interests, 75 IND. L.J. 1163, 1174-80 (2000); Steve R. Johnson, Fog, Fairness, and the Federal Fisc: Tenancy-by-the-Entireties Interests and the Federal Tax Lien, 60 MO. L. REV. 839, 855-68 (1995). 333. See supra Part II.B.6. 334. See, e.g., Erwin N. Griswold, The Need for a Court of Tax Appeals, 57 HARV. L. REV. 1153, 1183-84 (1944).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
251
property law in estate and gift tax cases, and often in income tax cases as well. Moreover, as noted in the preceding subpart, the expansion of the Tax Court’s jurisdiction over the decades has given it experience with collection issues in many contexts. In particular, the thousands of Collection Due Process cases that the Tax Court has heard in the last fifteen years has exposed the court to numerous collection controversies. Also, Part V.B below notes the phenomenon of “pure” APA tax suits. The Tax Court’s expanded jurisdiction should include them. There would be relatively few such suits, and the Tax Court is being forced to learn and grapple with administrative law principles even in cases already within its jurisdiction.335 The expanded Tax Court jurisdiction should be concurrent, not exclusive. Such other courts as Congress has already designated, or may in the future designate, able to hear the various categories of cases should still be able to hear them. This proposal is not a stealth initiative; a stalking horse for eventually exclusive Tax Court jurisdiction. I propose that the Tax Court have nearly plenary, not plenary, tax jurisdiction. I would reserve three areas. First, criminal tax cases should remain the exclusive province of the district courts, just as all criminal cases are. The Tax Court is and should remain a civil tribunal. Second, I would keep Tax Court cases as taxpayer, not IRS, initiated events. As seen in Part III.A above, there is concern in some quarters that the Tax Court has a pro-IRS bias. That concern is misplaced, but it does exist. If the IRS were able to go into Tax Court to secure compulsive orders, 336 the concern would rise. The Primary Value of providing taxpayer remedies that are both fair and perceived to be fair could be compromised. To prevent this, the reform would give the Tax Court jurisdiction over taxpayer-initiated actions only. Third, judicial review of jeopardy and termination assessments under § 7429 337 should continue to take place only in the district courts, not the Tax Court (except to the limited degree currently permitted). 338 A paramount need—a Primary Value need—in such review is expedition.339 The district courts sit in ninety-five districts with divisions in multiple cities within the districts. The Tax Court sits only in Washington, D.C., except when it periodically sends out 335. See supra Part II.B.12. 336. Such as summons enforcement orders, writs of entry, search warrants, promoter and preparer injunctions, and other types of writs and orders. 337. See supra Part II.B.7. 338. See I.R.C. § 7429(b)(2)(B). 339. Hence the short time frames for requesting review and for decision by the reviewing court. See id. § 7429(a)(1)(B), (b)(3).
252
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
judges to “ride circuit.” District court can best provide the speedy resolution required by § 7429 at reasonable cost and convenience to taxpayers. B. National Court of Tax Appeals Discussion of the jurisdiction of the Tax Court—a tax specialist trial court—invites inquiry as to appellate level tax specialization. This involves a long-playing controversy. Proposals often have been made to create a national court of tax appeals. Not surprisingly, the details of the proposals vary. 340 At the core, however, the idea is to centralize federal tax appeals—now heard by thirteen circuit courts—in a single, new tax appellate court. The decisions of the new court would be final absent Supreme Court certiorari review, legislative reversal, or regulatory reversal as sanctioned by the Brand X decision.341 This idea is most frequently associated with Dean Griswold,342 but many others, including an impressive array of luminaries, have associated themselves with the proposal. 343 The eminence of the proponents, however, did not stifle opposition. The proposal has been decried with at least as much vigor as it has been urged. 344 The debate comes in and goes out like the tide but never is silent for too long. 345
340. The details of some of the early proposals, and of alternatives to them, are described by H. Todd Miller, Comment, A Court of Tax Appeals Revisited, 85 YALE L.J. 228 (1985). See also Gary W. Carter, The Commissioner’s Nonacquiescence: A Case for a National Court of Tax Appeals, 59 TEMP. L.Q. 879 (1986). 341. Nat’l Cable & Telecomms. Ass’n v. Brand X Internet Servs., 545 U.S. 967, 982 (2005) (holding that Chevron-entitled regulations can reverse prior contrary decisions of the lower federal courts). 342. Griswold, supra note 334. 343. The idea was advanced at least as early as 1925. Oscar E. Bland, Federal Tax Appeals, 25 COLUM. L. REV. 1013 (1925). Among other advocates, see Henry J. Friendly, Averting the Flood by Lessening the Flow, 59 CORNELL L. REV. 634, 644 (1974); Charles L. B. Lowndes, Taxation and the Supreme Court, 1937 Term: Part II, 87 U. PA. L. REV. 165, 200 (1938); Stanley S. Surrey, Some Suggested Topics in the Field of Tax Administration, 25 WASH. U. L.Q. 399, 414-23 (1940); Roger John Traynor, Administrative and Judicial Procedure for Federal Income, Estate and Gift Taxes—A Criticism and a Proposal, 38 COLUM. L. REV. 1393 (1938). 344. See, e.g., Montgomery B. Angell, Procedural Reform in the Judicial Review of Controversies Under the Internal Revenue Statutes: An Answer to a Proposal, 34 ILL. L. REV. 151 (1939); E. Barrett Prettyman, A Comment on the Traynor Plan for Revision of Federal Tax Procedure, 27 GEO. L.J. 1038, 1048-50 (1939); William A. Sutherland, New Roads to the Settlement of Tax Controversies: A Critical Comment, 7 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 359, 360-61 (1940). 345. For a recent call for creation of the court, see Jasper L. Cummings, Jr., Creation of National Appellate Tax Court Will Improve Tax Law, in TOWARD TAX REFORM: RECOMMENDATIONS FOR PRESIDENT OBAMA’S TASK FORCE 30, 30-32 (Tax Analysts ed., 2009).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
253
It is sometimes hoped that a tax-specialized appellate court would make decisions of higher quality. 346 However, decisional harmony and doctrinal clarity—there would be fewer inconsistent tax precedents— always has been the more heavily emphasized justification.347 Opponents of the idea discount the extent to which the tax law will be made more predictable.348 They also assert that tax specialization would create its own problems, such as that the court would forfeit a valuable perspective by losing contact with the general law and would tilt in favor of the IRS. 349 The last of these objections—pro-IRS orientation—is a species of the well-known administrative law theory of “agency capture,” the idea that when an agency (in this case the court) deals repeatedly with a party (usually the regulated industry; here the IRS), it comes to sympathize and identify with that party’s needs and concerns. 350 These objections have thus far made the proposal politically nonviable. 351 If a tax appellate court could be “captured” by the IRS, one would expect that the Tax Court already has been so captured. There is long-running disagreement about whether this has occurred. Some practitioners and commentators believe that the Tax Court favors the IRS, 352 and they point to studies suggesting that the IRS wins more often in Tax Court than in district court.353 I am convinced that this view is incorrect. The studies that may seem to hint at bias typically do not adequately control for differences between the types of cases and the types of taxpayers appearing in
346. It is not obvious that a far higher caliber of decisions would ensue. “Tax law is undeniably complex, but [several justices without much pre-judicial tax experience] have demonstrated that it is not beyond the capacity of generalist judges and Justices to write thoughtful and sophisticated opinions in tax cases.” Lawrence Zelenak, The Court and the Code: A Response to The Warp and Woof of Statutory Interpretation, 58 DUKE L.J. 1783, 1787 (2009). 347. See, e.g., ROSWELL MAGILL, THE IMPACT OF FEDERAL TAXES 209 (1943). 348. Madaline Kinter Remmlein, Tax Controversies—Where Goes the Time?, 13 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 416 (1945). 349. See Robert N. Miller, Can Tax Appeals Be Centralized?, 23 TAXES 303 (1945). 350. See generally MARVER H. BERNSTEIN, REGULATING BUSINESS BY INDEPENDENT COMMISSION 87-90, 270 (1955); James M. Landis, S. SUBCOMM. ON ADMIN. PRACTICE & PROCEDURE, 86TH CONG., REP. ON REGULATORY AGENCIES TO THE PRESIDENT-ELECT 71 (Comm. Print 1960). But see Richard A. Posner, Theories of Economic Regulation, 5 BELL J. ECON. & MGMT. SCI. 335, 342 (1974) (arguing that “agency capture” lacks theoretical foundation and is unsupported by evidence). 351. See, e.g., Cummings, supra note 345. 352. See Glenn Kroll, Are Tax Court Judges Partial to the Government?, 45 OIL & GAS TAX Q. 135, 136 (1996). 353. See, e.g., Deborah A. Geier, The Tax Court, Article III, and the Proposal Advanced by the Federal Courts Study Committee: A Study in Applied Constitutional Theory, 76 CORNELL L. REV. 985, 998 (1991).
254
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
Tax Court versus district court.354 The better studies refute rather than confirm the Tax Court’s alleged pro-IRS bias. 355 Nonetheless, perceptions sometimes matter as much as (or even more than) reality. “Legislation concerning judicial organization throughout our history has been a very empiric response to very definite needs.” 356 Those needs include widespread and stubborn misconceptions as well as accurate perceptions. By the criteria adduced in this Article, we should continue to reject a national court of tax appeals. Such a court might contribute to efficiency and uniformity, although the extent of such contribution is difficult to estimate. But those are Second-Order Values, which yield to the Primary Value in most cases. The Primary Value includes remedies that are perceived to be fair, not just are in fact fair. Suspicion of the fairness of specialized tax tribunals is too widespread to be ignored. Confidence in the system is too important to risk. 357 C. Court of Federal Claims Jurisdiction As maintained above, the civil tax jurisdiction of the Tax Court should be expanded substantially. The tax jurisdiction of the Court of Federal Claims and the Federal Circuit should be abolished, however. Below, I first sketch the relevant history of these courts and then explain why abolition of their tax jurisdiction would promote the values identified in Part II.C above. 1. History As noted in Part II.B.1, the United States Court of Claims—the original ancestor of the current Court of Federal Claims and the Federal Circuit—was created in 1855. Its jurisdiction was significantly expanded by the Tucker Act in 1887, granting the court nationwide
354. See, e.g., Robert M. Howard, Comparing the Decision Making of Specialized Courts and General Courts: An Exploration of Tax Decisions, 26 JUS. SYS. J. 135, 138 n.1 (2005). For example, there are more pro se taxpayers in Tax Court and more wealthy taxpayers in district court. 355. See, e.g., James Edward Maule, Instant Replay, Weak Teams, and Disputed Calls: An Empirical Study of Alleged Tax Court Judge Bias, 66 TENN. L. REV. 351, 353 (1999). 356. FELIX FRANKFURTER & JAMES M. LANDIS, THE BUSINESS OF THE SUPREME COURT 13 (photo. reprint 1993) (1927). 357. Tax-specialized courts—whether trial or appellate—are parts of a larger topic. There is a substantial and growing literature on specialized courts. See, e.g., Lawrence Baum, Probing the Effects of Judicial Specialization, 58 DUKE L.J. 1667 (2009); Steve R. Johnson, The Phoenix and the Perils of the Second Best: Why Heightened Appellate Deference to Tax Court Decisions Is Undesirable, 77 OR. L. REV. 235, 235 & n.1, 236 & n.2 (1998) (citing sources). Thorough evaluation of proposals to create a national court of tax appeals should address this literature.
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
255
jurisdiction over most suits for monetary claims against the government, including claims for overpaid taxes.358 The jurisdiction of the Court of Claims and its successors was further expanded by subsequent enactments, so that the Court of Federal Claims now hears a wide array of matters, including claims for just compensation when the federal government takes private property, military and civilian compensation controversies, contract disputes, claims against the government for patent and copyright infringement, suits by Indian tribes, compensation claims for injuries attributed to specified vaccines, suits by disappointed bidders in federal procurements, and congressional references of legislative proposals for compensation of individual claims.359 Beginning in 1925, the Court of Claims’ trial jurisdiction was vested in a separate trial function consisting of commissioners, review of which was available from the court’s appellate judges (with the later possibility of certiorari review by the Supreme Court). In 1973, the commissioners were renamed the trial judges. 360 The courts took their modern form in 1982 when the Court of Claims was split. The old court’s trial jurisdiction was vested in a new Article I court: the United States Claims Court (later renamed the Court of Federal Claims). The old court’s appellate jurisdiction was combined with that of the United States Court of Customs and Patent Appeals to comprise an Article III court: the United States Court of Appeals for the Federal Circuit. 361 During 2006, the Court of Federal Claims had about 8700 cases on its docket, of which about 3100 involved the court’s general jurisdiction and 5600 were vaccine cases.362 The court had 302 tax cases pending as of October 2010 and 263 as of October 2011.363 Sixty-one new tax cases were commenced in the court in 2010 and fifty-four in 2011. 364
358. 28 U.S.C. §§ 1346(c), 1491(a)(1) (2006). 359. United States Court of Federal Claims: The People’s Court, U.S. CT. FED. CLAIMS, http://www.uscfc.uscourts.gov/sites/default/files/court_info/Court_History_Brochure.pdf (last visited Feb. 2, 2014). “In recent years, the Court’s docket has been increasingly characterized by complex, high-dollar demand, and high profile cases in areas such areas as . . . the savings and loan crisis of the 1980s, the World War II internment of JapaneseAmericans, and the federal repository of civilian spent nuclear fuel.” Id. at 9-10. 360. Id. at 8. 361. Federal Courts Improvement Act of 1982, Pub. L. No. 97-164, 96 Stat. 25. 362. An Overview of the United States Court of Federal Claims, U.S. CT. FED. CLAIMS, http://www.uscfc.uscourts.gov/sites/default/files/court_info/Court_History_Brochure.pdf (last visited Feb. 2, 2014). 363. STATISTICS DIV., ADMIN. OFFICE OF THE U.S. COURTS, JUDICIAL BUSINESS OF THE UNITED STATES COURTS: 2011 ANNUAL REPORT OF THE DIRECTOR 291. 364. See id. at 35.
256
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
In contrast, the number of tax cases commenced in district court in 2011 was 1194, in 711 of which the government was the plaintiff and in 481 of which the government was the defendant. 365 Both the Court of Federal Claims and district court totals are dwarfed by Tax Court cases: 29,720 Tax Court cases were started in 2011. 366 2. Reasons for Change The original acquisition of tax jurisdiction by the Court of Claims was a felicitous development. As shown in Parts II.B.1 and II.B.3 above, prepayment remedies did not yet exist and other refund remedies were underdeveloped. The subsequent development of Tax Court and district court channels of redress, however, has rendered superfluous the Court of Federal Claims tax jurisdiction. It should be abolished. Some taxpayers and their representatives would oppose this reform. First, it is human nature—and especially lawyers’ nature—to want as many options as possible. When the Tax Court and the relevant district court have rejected a particular argument, those who wish to press that argument take comfort in having a third available forum. Second, the Court of Federal Claims possesses, or is believed to possess, certain useful characteristics. It has gained a reputation in some quarters as being a taxpayer-friendly tribunal. 367 Some consider it the forum of choice when the taxpayer has a weak case on the law—one likely to be rejected by the Tax Court. 368 And the court styles itself as the “keeper of the nation’s conscience” and “the People’s Court,” 369 so taxpayers with good litigating equities may view the court as an attractive forum. 370 Nonetheless, the Primary Value does not counsel in favor of retaining the tax jurisdiction of the Court of Federal Claims. That value means that taxpayers should have remedies that both are fair and effective and are perceived to be fair and effective. That requirement 365. Id. at 127. New district court tax cases were 1522 in 2007, 1451 in 2008, 1306 in 2009, and 1190 in 2010. Id. at 130. 366. INTERNAL REVENUE SERVICE, DATA BOOK 61 (2011). 367. See Christopher R. Egan, Checking the Beast: Why the Federal Circuit Court of Appeals is Good for the Federal System of Tax Litigation, 56 SMU L. REV. 721, 725 (2003). 368. For example, before being reversed, the Court of Federal Claims was the only court to have held that the judicially crafted economic substance doctrine—the IRS’s principal weapon against recent tax shelters—is illegitimate as a violation of the separation of powers doctrine. Coltec Indus., Inc. v. United States, 62 Fed. Cl. 716, 755-56 (2004), vacated & remanded, 454 F.3d 1340 (Fed. Cir. 2006). 369. United States Court of Federal Claims: The People’s Court, supra note 359, at 1. 370. For instance, the court, on the basis of sparing taxpayers unnecessary expense, created a de minimis exception to the capitalization doctrine. Cincinnati, New Orleans & Tex. Pac. Ry. Co. v. United States, 424 F.2d 563 (Ct. Cl. 1970). The Tax Court rejected Cincinnati Railway. Alacare Home Health Servs., Inc. v. Commissioner, 81 T.C.M. (CCH) 1794 (2001).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
257
is not synonymous, however, with affording taxpayers redundant options simply to multiply their convenience and advantages. Under the federal tax litigation structure proposed by this Article, taxpayers would have prepayment opportunities in the Tax Court and, when bankruptcy jurisdiction exists, in the bankruptcy court. Taxpayers would have refund opportunities in the Tax Court, district court, and, when bankruptcy jurisdiction exists, in the bankruptcy court. The Primary Value does not require that taxpayers have yet another refund opportunity, this time in the Court of Federal Claims. The Primary Value not being engaged, the matter turns on Second-Order Values. Removing one redundant level of refund litigation will decrease the potential for conflict among the courts, reducing forum shopping and increasing predictability and efficiency. One of the reasons for creation of the Court of Federal Claims was development of a uniform body of law for cases within its jurisdiction.371 That rationale works well as to the numerous areas, sketched above, in which the court has exclusive jurisdiction. Because of the multiplicity of alternative tax refund fora, however, the uniformity rationale would be better served in the tax area by abolishing the Court of Federal Claims’ tax jurisdiction.372 If one tax forum is to be removed, which should it be? The Tax Court should be retained because of its expertise and its opportunity for prepayment review. The bankruptcy court should be retained because the tax issues of debtors are best handled as part of the total complexion of the debtor’s situation. As between the district court and the Court of Federal Claims, the district court should be retained. Jury trials are possible in district court but not in the Court of Federal Claims. 373 More importantly, district courts are Article III courts while the Court of Federal Claims is an Article I court. Thus, district court judges have life tenure while Court of Federal Claims judges have renewable fifteen-year terms (like Tax Court judges). 374 Those suspicious that courts may favor the IRS are more likely to see the district court as the more vigilant sentinel. Accordingly, the Primary Value reinforces the Second-Order Values. We should dispense with the tax jurisdiction of the Court of Fed371. An Overview of the United States Court of Federal Claims, supra note 362. 372. See, e.g., Martin D. Ginsburg, Commentary, The Federal Courts Study Committee on Claims Court Tax Jurisdiction, 40 CATH. U. L. REV. 631, 635-36 (1991). 373. Jury trials are not the norm in tax cases. But they are fairly common in cases involving the trust fund recovery penalty under § 6672, and they occasionally are used in refund cases involving other issues, e.g., Scriptomatic, Inc. v. United States, 74-1 U.S. Tax Cas. (CCH) ¶ 9246, 33 A.F.T.R.2d (RIA) 827 (E.D. Pa. 1973), aff’d, 555 F.2d 364 (3d Cir. 1977) (§ 385 case). 374. 28 U.S.C. § 172 (2006).
258
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
eral Claims. That court would be left with the heavy workload and the important duties entailed with the other types of cases, described above, that comprise its jurisdiction. IV. REFORMS AS TO AVAILABLE FORMS OF ACTION The prior Part advanced proposals as to the courts that should be available to hear federal tax disputes. This Part addresses the forms of actions and the kinds of relief that should be available regardless of the court. I propose two such changes. First, the TEFRA partnership audit and litigation rules enacted in 1982 have proved to be more harmful than beneficial. In the main, they should be repealed. This would return us to partner-level audit and litigation, with some collateral rules to promote efficiency. Second, among the major products of the IRS Restructuring and Reform Act of 1998 were the Collection Due Process (“CDP”) rules. In the main, these rules have entailed great expenditure of effort and resources by taxpayers, the IRS, and the courts without producing commensurate genuine and lasting benefits for taxpayers. Some commentators have urged abolition of the CDP regime. This Article does not go that far. It proposes reducing the scope of, but not eliminating, judicial review of CDP decisions by the IRS Appeals Office. A. TEFRA Rules When originally enacted, the rules governing taxation of partnerships and their partners were intended to be, and largely were, simple, in order to facilitate the flexibility partnerships offer for non-tax purposes. These rules are, in the main, embodied in Subchapter K of Chapter 1 of the Code. Over time, Subchapter K has become anything but simple, both because of unresolved tensions in its original design and because—flexibility being the spawning ground of creative tax planning 375—Congress has superimposed numerous complex étages of anti-abuse on the originally simple edifice. 376 In my view, the game is no longer worth the candle. Some others and I have advocated the
375. “A partnership is a magic circle. Anything that is dropped into it becomes exempt from taxation. Forever. . . . Adherents to this view of subchapter K understand the word ‘flexible’ to mean that you can do absolutely anything you want without incurring tax.” Lee A. Sheppard, Partnerships, Consolidated Returns and Cognitive Dissonance, 63 TAX NOTES 936, 936 (1994). 376. See, e.g., Lawrence Lokken, Taxation of Private Business Firms: Imagining a Future Without Subchapter K, 4 FLA. TAX REV. 249, 250 (1999) (“Subchapter K is a mess.”); Andrea Monroe, What’s in a Name: Can the Partnership Anti-Abuse Rule Really Stop Partnership Tax Abuse?, 60 CASE W. RES. L. REV. 401, 402 (2010) (“Partnership taxation is a disaster.”).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
259
abolition of Subchapter K, leaving S corporations as the Code’s principal “pass-through” form. 377 This radical suggestion is unlikely to be adopted any time soon, however. Thus, we should direct our attention to a lesser reform: the abolition of the bulk of the TEFRA regime. Others 378 and I 379 have advocated this reform previously, but additional persuasion will be required to forge an effective consensus. There are two reasons for ending the principal aspects of the TEFRA rules. First, the TEFRA rules are unnecessary. The circumstances causing creation of the regime in 1982 no longer exist. Second, the TEFRA rules have proved to be harmful. From far promoting clarity, consistency, and efficiency in resolving partnership related controversies, the TEFRA rules have undermined these values. 1. Unnecessary There is some question as to whether the TEFRA rules truly were needed by the time of their enactment in 1982, 380 but let us assume they were. That necessity has evaporated as a result of post1982 developments. In 1986, Congress enacted § 469, the passive activity loss rules, and strengthened the § 465 at-risk rules. Section 469 especially struck at the core of tax shelter marketing. It prevented taxpayers from using losses from passive activities (tax shelters) to offset their income from other sources. 381 It was no longer necessary to examine tax shelters individually and to disallow their alleged benefits on technical or substantive grounds. 377. See Steve R. Johnson, The E.L. Wiegand Lecture: Administrability-Based Tax Simplification, 4 NEV. L.J. 573, 589-96 (2004); Philip F. Postlewaite, I Come to Bury Subchapter K, Not to Praise It, 54 TAX LAW. 451 (2001). 378. See, e.g., Peter A. Prescott, Jumping the Shark: The Case for Repealing the TEFRA Partnership Audit Rules, 11 FLA. TAX REV. 503 (2011); Burgess J.W. Raby & William L. Raby, TEFRA Partnership Rules: The Solution Becomes the Problem, 88 TAX NOTES 795 (2000); see also N. Jerold Cohen & William E. Sheumaker, When It’s Broke, Fix It! It’s Time for TEFRA Reform, 136 TAX NOTES 815 (2012) (expressing concerns about the TEFRA rules but stopping short of urging their repeal). 379. Johnson, supra note 377, at 596-602; Steve R. Johnson, Letter to the Editor, TEFRA: No Fix Possible, Just Get Rid of It!, 136 TAX NOTES 964 (2012). 380. In the time before Congress acted in 1982, the IRS and the courts developed improved techniques for identifying, processing, and managing tax shelter cases. See Johnson, supra note 377, at 601. Of course, in the decades since 1982, technological capacities have improved greatly, further undermining the bureaucratic necessity of the TEFRA rules. See Prescott, supra note 378, at 562-64. 381. See generally Boris I. Bittker, Martin J. McMahon, Jr. & Lawrence A. Zelenak, A Whirlwind Tour of the Internal Revenue Code’s At-Risk and Passive Activity Loss Rules, 36 REAL PROP., PROB. & TR. J. 673 (2002); Robert J. Peroni, A Policy Critique of the Section 469 Passive Loss Rules, 62 S. CAL. L. REV. 1 (1988); Lawrence Zelenak, When Good Preferences Go Bad: A Critical Analysis of the Anti-Tax Shelter Provisions of the Tax Reform Act of 1986, 67 TEX. L. REV. 499 (1989).
260
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
As a result and in short order, the old tax shelter market collapsed. After some years, shelter promoters found new strategies, and new tax shelter vehicles were marketed in the 1990s and early 2000s. Critically, however, that second wave differed fundamentally from the first wave, in ways that makes the TEFRA rules obsolete. Before 1986, shelters were mass marketed to upper middle class as well as rich taxpayers—thousands of shelters, most of which were sold to scores or hundreds of “investors” each. Now, shelters are rifle shots, not shotgun blasts. There are far fewer of them, and typically each shelter partnership or LLC has only a few “investors,” mainly large corporations or extremely high-wealth individuals, who are likely to be audited in any event. The audit and litigation challenges posed by current shelters are barely a shadow of challenges posed by pre-1986 shelters. Moreover, investors in current shelters typically can avoid the TEFRA regime if they wish. In general, the regime does not apply to “any partnership having 10 or fewer partners each of whom is an individual . . . , a C corporation, or an estate of a deceased partner.” 382 Since very few current tax shelter partnerships have over 10 investors, the TEFRA regime adds little to the IRS’s ability to combat current shelters. This observation leads to a broader point about the demography of partnerships. At the “small” end of the spectrum, the TEFRA rules have little applicability as a result of the “10 or fewer partners” exception.383 Depending on the year studied, partnerships have on average only five or six partners, 384 well within the exception. At the “large” end of the spectrum, “electing large partnerships” with 100 or more partners and “publicly traded partnerships” (which may have thousands of partners) also are outside of TEFRA. 385 Thus, TEFRA is potentially meaningful only in the middle of the partnership spectrum, but that middle is not densely populated. Less than ten percent
382. I.R.C. § 6231(a)(1)(B)(i). This exclusion, if applicable, is automatic unless the partnership affirmatively elects into TEFRA treatment. Id. § 6231(a)(1)(B)(ii). Many current shelters do elect in. At least sometimes, this decision is motivated by the harms caused by TEFRA described in the following subpart. In a number of important respects, the TEFRA rules are unpredictable in their application, so electing into TEFRA treatment gives the taxpayers additional opportunities to prevail if the IRS “messes up” or guesses incorrectly how the reviewing court eventually will interpret TEFRA’s requirements. 383. This exception has been in the TEFRA rules from the start, and Congress has shown little inclination to repeal or modify it. Id. § 6231(a)(1)(B). 384. See Prescott, supra note 378, at 558. 385. Electing large partnerships are outside of TEFRA under I.RC. § 6240(b)(1). With narrow exceptions, publicly traded partnerships are treated as corporations for federal tax purposes and so are outside of TEFRA. Id. § 7704.
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
261
of partnerships are in this range, 386 and, as noted above, current tax shelter partnerships typically are not there. In the main, therefore, the TEFRA procedures are dispensable. There are three particular rules that should be retained, though. First, in general, partners are required on their returns to treat items derived from partnerships consistently with the way those items are treated on the partnership’s return. 387 Inconsistency allows the IRS to automatically assess any resulting deficiency388 and may expose the partner to a penalty. 389 Second, if the IRS settles some or all partnership items with some partners, the other partners are generally entitled to settle their items on similar terms.390 Both of these consistency rules—the consistent reporting rule and the consistent settlement rule—advance the Second-Order Value of process efficiency and should be retained. Third, § 6229 sets out limitation periods for IRS assessment of partnership items. There was initial uncertainty as to the relationship between these periods and the general assessment limitation periods prescribed by § 6501. It is now settled that the § 6229 rules may extend the period allowable under § 6501 but may not contract it. 391 This rule too should be retained to protect audits in case of late filed partnership returns. 392 2. Harmful The preceding subpart mentioned unresolved tensions in the original design of Subchapter K. A principal tension involves the “entity versus aggregate” question: are partnerships entities separate from their owners or are they mere aggregates of the activities of their owners? 393 Creating unending confusion on specific substantive issues, Subchapter K sometimes applies an entity approach, some386. In 2011, slightly over 3,285,000 partnerships filed returns with the IRS. Slightly over 3,082,000 of them (93.8% of the total) had under ten partners. Rob DeCarlo, Lauren Lee & Nina Shumofsky, Internal Revenue Service, Partnership Returns, 2011, STAT. OF INCOME BULL., Fall 2013, at 81, 83 fig. C. 387. I.R.C. § 6222(a). Deviation is permitted, however, when the partner specifically notifies the IRS. Id. § 6222(b). 388. Id. § 6222(c). 389. Id. § 6222(d). 390. Id. § 6222(c)(2). 391. See Andantech L.L.C. v. Commissioner, 331 F.3d 972 (D.C. Cir. 2003). 392. I have argued that repeal of the main TEFRA rules should not create problems for the IRS auditing partnership items within I.R.C. § 6501’s statute of limitations. Nonetheless, should Congress harbor concern on this score, it could amend § 6229 to extend the limitations period. Cf. I.R.C. § 6901(c)(1), (2) (extending the limitations period with respect to transferee liability). 393. See, e.g., Bradley T. Borden, Aggregate-Plus Theory of Partnership Taxation, 43 GA. L. REV. 717, 719 (2009).
262
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
times an aggregate approach, and sometimes a mixed entityaggregate approach. 394 TEFRA—a mix of the aggregate and entity approaches—extends that confusion to the procedural realm. This tension is responsible for many ambiguities and inefficiencies in the TEFRA rules. They showed up early in numerous cases, many of which the IRS lost. Undoubtedly, the TEFRA rules sometimes resulted in the government being able to assess and collect amounts it would otherwise have lost. Equally undoubtedly, however, in other cases the IRS lost money because it construed the TEFRA rules in ways the courts later held to be erroneous. Neither side of this revenue ratio ever has been (nor, probably, can it ever be) reliably quantified, so we do not know the extent to which TEFRA succeeded in its fiscal objectives, or even whether it succeeded at all. Even more troubling than the immense confusion the TEFRA rules spawned early on is the fact that great confusion and dysfunction as to them persist even today. In an en banc opinion, the Tax Court noted the “distressingly complex and confusing” nature of TEFRA rules.395 Similarly, the Treasury has acknowledged that the TEFRA rules sometimes “generate[] complex and burdensome procedural issues that do not contribute to the determination of the [partners’] tax liabilities.” 396 A trifurcation at the core of TEFRA is the source of many of these problems. For TEFRA purposes, one needs to distinguish among partnership items, non-partnership items, and affected items. Partnership items are items “more appropriately determined at the partnership level than at the partner level.” 397 Examples include each partner’s share of the partnership’s income, gain, loss, deductions, credits, non-deductible expenditures, and liabilities. 398 Penalties also are partnership items to the extent that they relate to partnership items.399 Affected items are not partnership items but are influenced in their availability or extent by partnership items. 400 Examples include items that vary in accordance with the partner’s income, 394. See ROBERT J. PERONI, STEVEN A. BANK & GLENN E. COVEN, NESS ENTERPRISES: CASES AND MATERIALS 1002-04 (3d ed. 2006).
TAXATION OF BUSI-
395. Rhone-Poulenc Surfactants & Specialties, L.P. v. Commissioner, 114 T.C. 533, 540 (2000); see also Shamik Trivedi & Jeremiah Coder, TEFRA Raises Complex Jurisdictional Issues, Judge Says, 135 TAX NOTES 985 (2012) (reporting remarks of Tax Court Judge Mark V. Holmes). 396. Tax Avoidance Transactions, 74 Fed. Reg. 7205, 7206 (proposed Feb. 13, 2009) (to be codified at 26 C.F.R. pt. 301) (proposing new regulations under § 6231). 397. I.R.C. § 6231(a)(3). 398. Treas. Reg. § 301.6231(a)(3)-1(a)(1). 399. I.R.C. § 6221. 400. Id. § 6231(a)(5).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
263
a partner’s basis in her partnership interest, and a partner’s atrisk limitation. 401 Even when the rules are clear, the potential for inefficiency is considerable. Partnership items are determined in TEFRA proceedings.402 Nonpartnership items are determined in separate, traditional partner-level deficiency proceedings. Affected items are determined after the partnership adjustments have been resolved, sometimes through automatic computational adjustments and other times through deficiency procedures.403 Thus, when a partner’s individual return for a given year includes both partnership and nonpartnership items, multiple separate proceedings can be required before the partner’s correct tax liability for the year is established with finality. Similarly, assume the partnership engages in a transaction that the IRS finds abusive. Assume further that both the partnership and a particular partner obtained legal opinions supporting the transaction’s tax legitimacy. When the reasonable reliance defense is raised against the penalties asserted by the IRS, 404 it will have to be litigated in two separate cases. Reasonable reliance based on the opinion obtained by the partnership is a partnership item that must be determined in a TEFRA proceeding. Reasonable reliance based on the opinion obtained by the partner is an affected item that must be determined outside the TEFRA case.405 Every first-year law student is told that our legal system abhors claim splitting. TEFRA requires it. All of this inefficiency is compounded by the fact that the demarcations TEFRA requires are often difficult to make. In many situations, there can be reasonable disagreement as to whether an item is a partnership, non-partnership, or affected item. If a party makes the wrong choice and commences a proceeding on the wrong track, the court will lack jurisdiction. Numerous recent cases have tested such TEFRA jurisdictional issues, often with surprising results. 406 Under the trifurcation central to TEFRA, “[t]he potential for overlapping effects and hidden boomerangs is mind-numbing.” 407 And, of 401. Treas. Reg. § 301.6231(a)(5)-1. 402. I.R.C. § 6221. 403. See, e.g., N.C.F. Energy Partners v. Commissioner, 89 T.C. 741, 744 (1987); Treas. Reg. § 301.6231(a)(6)-1(a)(1). 404. See I.R.C. § 6664(c)(1). 405. See Treas. Reg. § 301.6221-1(d). 406. See Petaluma FX Partners, LLC v. Commissioner, 591 F.3d 649, 650-51, 656 (D.C. Cir. 2010); Tigers Eye Trading, LLC v. Commissioner, 138 T.C. 67 (2012); see also Karen C. Burke & Grayson M.P. McCouch, Reflections on Penalty Jurisdiction in Tigers Eye, 136 TAX NOTES 1581 (2012). 407. F. Brook Voght, Frederick H. Robinson & Michael E. Baillif, New Rules for TEFRA Partnerships Provide More Flexibility in Resolving Disputes with the IRS, 88 J. TAX’N 279, 279-80 (1998).
264
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
course, this is not the only source of the uncertainties and inefficiencies TEFRA has engendered.408 In short, the harms of the TEFRA partnership audit and litigation rules now exceed the regime’s benefits. In 1982, TEFRA-like procedures also were enacted for S corporations. 409 They were repealed in 1996, however.410 We should learn that lesson in the partnership context as well. B. Judicial Review of CDP Determinations The Collection Due Process rules were enacted as part of the RRA blizzard of reforms, discussed in Part II.B.10 above. They were not the most ballyhooed aspect of the RRA at the time, but they have proved to be the most consequential and controversial. 411 Before enactment of the CDP rules, once tax had been properly assessed and notice and demand for payment had been made, the IRS was permitted to file notice of the tax lien and to levy on the taxpayer’s property with minimal statutory hurdles to jump. The CDP rules create speed bumps. Now, within five days after the IRS files notice of the lien 412 or not less than thirty days before levy is effected, 413 the IRS is required to notify the taxpayer of its action or intended action. Among other things, the notice explains the nature of the IRS action and the taxpayer’s rights, including the right to administrative hearing. The taxpayer has thirty days from the issuance of the notice to request review by the IRS Appeals Office.414 The request operates to stay IRS collection action and also to stay the running of the statute of limitations on collection.415 Appeals Office CDP hearings are conducted informally. 416 What matters may be considered at the Appeals Office hearing? First, the Appeals Officer is required to verify that the IRS Collection Division has complied with applicable statutory and regulatory provisions.417 408. See, e.g., Raby & Raby, supra note 378, at 795 (noting the persistence of TEFRA statute of limitations uncertainties nearly two decades after TEFRA’s enactment). 409. Subchapter S Revision Act of 1982, Pub. L. No. 97-354, § 4(a), 96 Stat. 1669, 169192 (formerly codified at I.R.C. §§ 6221-6245). 410. Small Business Job Protection Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-188, § 1307(c)(1), 110 Stat. 1755, 1781. 411. Tens of thousands of CDP hearing requests are made each year. Danshera Cords, Collection Due Process: The Scope and Nature of Judicial Review, 73 U. CIN. L. REV. 1021, 1022 n.7 (2005). 412. I.R.C. § 6320(a)(2)(C). 413. Id. § 6330(a)(2)(C). 414. Id. § 6330(a)(3)(B). 415. Id. § 6330(e). Normally, IRS efforts to collect unpaid taxes become time-barred ten years after assessment. Id. § 6502(a). 416. See Treas. Reg. § 601.106(c). 417. I.R.C. § 6330(c)(1).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
265
Second, the taxpayer may raise “any relevant issue relating to the unpaid tax or the proposed levy, including—(i) appropriate spousal defenses; (ii) challenges to the appropriateness of collection actions; and (iii) offers of collection alternatives . . . .” 418 Third, the taxpayer may contest the underlying tax liability if she “did not receive any statutory notice of deficiency for such tax liability or did not otherwise have an opportunity to dispute such tax liability.”419 The CDP rules expressly recognize the tension between revenue collection and taxpayer protection. Congress directed Appeals Officers to determine in their resolution of the matter “whether any proposed collection action balances the need for the efficient collection of taxes with the legitimate concern of the person that any collection action be no more intrusive than necessary.” 420 If the taxpayer is dissatisfied with the Appeals Office’s determination, she may appeal within thirty days to the Tax Court.421 The standard of review is de novo when the underlying tax liability is properly at issue and abuse of discretion when it is not.422 Despite its beguiling name (who could possibly be against due process in collection?), CDP was controversial from the start. A lively debate has gone on for years, with knowledgeable, passionate, and eloquent champions on both sides.423 Defenders see the judicial review component of CDP as “a step in the progression of the rule of law principles that came to permeate twentieth century legal culture.” 424 Detractors find it “an outstanding regulatory failure” that “likely hurts those who most need its promised protection from arbitrary agency action,” and argue that CDP demonstrates how “adversarial process, used in the wrong place and the wrong time, becomes a rule of deception rather than a rule of law.” 425 There is little question that CDP has been extremely expensive in terms of the Second-Order Value of efficiency. The many tens of thousands of CDP cases claim substantial resources from the IRS 418. Id. § 6330(c)(2)(A). 419. Id. § 6330(c)(2)(B). 420. Id. § 6330(c)(3)(C). 421. Id. § 6330(d)(1). 422. H.R. REP. NO. 105-599, at 266 (1998) (Conf. Rep.). 423. See, e.g., [2004] 1 NAT’L TAXPAYER ADVOCATE ANN. REP. 226-45, 451-70, 498-510 (discussing critiques of CDP and proposals for its reform). The debate between Professor Leslie Book and Bryan Camp identified key issues. Bryan Camp & Leslie Book, Point & Counterpoint: Should Collection Due Process Be Repealed?, 24 A.B.A. SEC. TAX’N NEWS Q. 11 (2004). 424. Leslie Book, The Collection Due Process Rights: A Misstep or a Step in the Right Direction?, 41 HOUS. L. REV. 1145, 1161 (2004). 425. Bryan T. Camp, The Failure of Adversarial Process in the Administrative State, 84 IND. L.J. 57, 57-58 (2009).
266
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
and the Tax Court. They also delay collection and, by extending the collection limitations period, postpone the day of repose. 426 These costs have not been justified by appreciable gains to the Primary Value of taxpayer protection. First, the IRS wins the overwhelming majority of CDP cases. 427 Second, most of the relatively few taxpayer “wins” are victories in name only. They result in recommital of the case to the administrative process, with the taxpayer’s ultimate position often benefitted little at the end of the day. Third, the deferential abuse-of-discretion standard of proof may cause losing taxpayers to feel they did not receive a fair day in court. Another problem is that CDP litigation mixes and confuses the executive and judicial roles. The Executive Branch (in this case, the IRS) applies the law. The courts exist to make sure the IRS follows the law, not to interfere with the IRS’s exercise of administrative discretion or second-guess the choices the IRS made among options legally available to it. 428 The notoriously loose standards for judicial review of Appeals Office CDP determinations 429 can tempt the reviewing court to overstep its legitimate role. The Tax Court sometimes displays a regrettable tendency to operate as a self-appointed superintendent of tax administration.430 That is properly the role of Congress, the Treasury, and the IRS Oversight Board, not of a court of law, 431 except when Congress expressly provides to the contrary. 432 426. One sorry aspect of this has been the use (or abuse) of CDP by tax defiers (the now in-vogue name for those once called “tax protestors”) to delay the system through assertion of worthless arguments. See Steve Johnson, The 1998 Act and the Resources Link Between Tax Compliance and Tax Simplification, 51 U. KAN. L. REV. 1013, 1061 (2003) (proposing changes to reduce this problem). 427. See Camp, supra note 425, at 57 (noting, as of 2009, that “[o]f the over sixteen million collection decisions made since 2000, courts have reviewed at most 3,000 and have reversed only sixteen”). 428. For an example of a court overstepping its role—and later having to retract its excesses—see Fidelity Equip. Leasing Corp. v. United States, 462 F. Supp. 845 (N.D. Ga. 1978), vacated in part, 81-1 U.S. Tax Cas. (CCH) ¶ 9319 (N.D. Ga. 1981) (§ 7429 case). 429. See, e.g., Cords, supra note 411, at 1024 (arguing that judicial review of CDP determinations “is an unsettled and problematic area of law because it lacks clear direction from Congress”). 430. See, e.g., Rauenhorst v. Commissioner, 119 T.C. 157, 169-73 (2002) (holding the IRS to a position expressed in previous Revenue Rulings despite the fact that Revenue Rulings do not have the force of law); Walker v. Commissioner, 101 T.C. 537, 550-51 (1993) (same). 431. The Tax Court has struggled for generations to be recognized as a court, not an agency. See, e.g., DUBROFF, supra note 28, at 165-215. 432. For example, the IRS is authorized to relieve spouses of the normal joint and several liability as to joint income tax returns when “taking into account all the facts and circumstances, it is inequitable to hold the individual liable.” I.R.C. § 6015(f)(1). Persons denied such relief by the IRS may bring an action in Tax Court. In such action, the Tax Court may “determine the appropriate relief.” Id. § 6015(e)(1)(A). Two courts have held that this provision empowers the Tax Court to go outside the administrative record and proceed de novo in determining the demands of equity. Wilson v. Commissioner, 705 F.3d 980, 987
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
267
Despite these problems, I do not join those who call for complete repeal of the CDP rules. These rules have been salutary in at least one respect. In recent years, “the IRS has implemented procedures and controls significantly improving [its] compliance with legal and internal guidelines” applicable to its seizure of property to satisfy tax debts. 433 This is the wholesome product of spotlights on IRS derelictions cast by Congressional oversight, reports by the National Taxpayer Advocate, 434 investigations by the Treasury Inspector General for Tax Administration, 435 and—yes—by the CDP process. CDP hearings and litigation act as a tripwire alerting the IRS to, and prodding it to correct, its breaches of tax collection rules. Based on the foregoing, I propose two changes to CDP. First, the current rule—§ 6330(c)(2)(A)(iii)—that authorizes consideration of collection alternatives offered by the taxpayer should be amended. Taxpayers should still be able to present such alternatives to the Appeals Office. However, the Appeals Office’s decision with respect to such alternatives should no longer be judiciary reviewable. Second, the current rules—§ 6330(c)(1) and § 6330(c)(2)(A)(ii)— that require verification of and permit challenges to collection procedures should be amended. Only failures to follow procedures required by a statute or regulation should be judicially reviewable. Failures to follow lesser requirements—such as those set out in the Internal Revenue Manual—should be fodder for administrative review (to serve the tripwire function) but not for judicial review. 436 V. REFORM AS TO PREREQUISITE TO SUIT A. Flora “Full Payment” Rule We need not explore whether the majority or the dissenters in Flora II had the better of the statutory construction argument. Our inquiry is whether the full payment rule is wise as a matter of policy.
(9th Cir. 2013); Commissioner v. Neal, 557 F.3d 1262, 1263-64 (11th Cir. 2009). The Neal court expressly distinguished the language of § 6015(e) from that of § 6330(d)(1). Neal, 557 F.3d at 1276. But see id. at 1287 (Tjoflat, J., dissenting) (“Today, the court has given the Tax Court the authority to second-guess the Commissioner at its whim . . . .”). 433. TREASURY INSPECTOR GEN. FOR TAX ADMIN., FISCAL YEAR 2011 REVIEW OF COMPLIANCE WITH LEGAL GUIDELINES WHEN CONDUCTING SEIZURES OF TAXPAYERS’ PROPERTY 3 (2011). 434. See I.R.C. § 7803(c)(2)(B). 435. See id. § 7803(d)(1)(A), (B). 436. Cf. United States v. Caceres, 440 U.S. 741, 756-57 (1979) (holding that the exclusionary rule does not prevent use of evidence obtained in violation of procedures set out in the Internal Revenue Manual); see also Sandin v. Conner, 515 U.S. 472, 487 (1995) (holding that an agency regulation—a state prison regulation—did not create a protected liberty interest entitling the affected prisoner to procedural due process protections).
268
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
I join those who believe that it is not. 437 I.R.C. § 7422 and 28 U.S.C. § 1346(a) should be amended to permit refund suits to be brought even upon partial payment of the assessed liabilities. The full payment rule traduces the Primary Value: it blunts the efficacy of taxpayer remedies. A full payment requirement shuts the courthouse door to some taxpayers who have reasonable claims that they overpaid their taxes. The Flora II dissenters explained this consequence of a full payment rule: Where a taxpayer has paid, upon a normal or a “jeopardy” assessment, either voluntarily or under compulsion of distraint, a part only of an illegal assessment and is unable to pay the balance within the two-year period of limitations, he would be deprived of any means of establishing the invalidity of the assessment and of recovering the amount illegally collected from him, unless it be held . . . that full payment is not a condition upon the jurisdiction of District Courts to entertain suits for refund. Likewise, taxpayers who pay assessments in installments would be without remedy to recover early installments that were wrongfully collected should the period of limitations run before the last installment is paid. 438
It is impossible to quantify the extent of this problem, but one fact is certain and two facts are probable. It is certain that some taxpayers experience the problem. It is probable that some of those taxpayers experience significant economic distress when the problem hits them. And it is probable that enough taxpayers experience enough hardship that this concern is worth addressing. The four Flora II dissenters certainly thought so. They referred to “great hardships,” “harsh injustice,” and a “grossly unfair and . . . shockingly inequitable result.” 439 Commentators have echoed the concern. 440 The Flora I majority conceded that “the requirement of full payment may in some instances work a hardship.” 441 The Flora II major437. See, e.g., Thomas Vance McMahan, Note, Income Tax—Federal Tax Court— Election of Remedies—Federal District Court Lacks Jurisdiction of Suit for Refund of Income Tax Payments Which Do Not Discharge Taxpayer’s Entire Assessment. Flora v. United States, 362 U.S. 145 (1960), 39 TEX. L. REV. 353, 355 (1961) (“Viewed from a policy standpoint[,] . . . [the Flora II Court] chose the less desirable of the two [options].”). 438. Flora II, 362 U.S. 145, 195-96 (1960) (Whittaker, J., dissenting) (footnotes omitted). A refund claim must be made within the later of three years after the return was filed or two years after the tax was paid. I.R.C. § 6511(a). If the three-year period applies, the amount that can be refunded is generally limited to the amount paid within three years before the claim is made. Id. § 6511(b)(2)(A). If the two-year period applies, the amount that can be refunded is limited to the amount paid within two years before the claim is made. Id. § 6511(b)(2)(B); see also id. § 6532(a)(1). 439. Flora II, 362 U.S. at 195 & n.22, 198 (Whittaker, J., dissenting). 440. See, e.g., McMahan, supra note 437, at 355; J.Q. Riordan, Must You Pay Full Tax Assessment Before Suing in the District Court?, 8 J. TAX’N 179, 181 (1958); Carlton Smith, Let the Poor Sue for Refund Without Full Payment (Benjamin N. Cardozo Sch. of Law, Working Paper No. 256, 2009), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1354145. 441. Flora I, 357 U.S. 63, 75 (1958).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
269
ity sought to alleviate the concern by maintaining that the taxpayer so harmed should have challenged the IRS adjustments before assessment in the Tax Court. “If he permits his time for filing such an appeal [to the Tax Court] to expire, he can hardly complain that he has been unjustly treated, for he is in precisely the same position as any other person who is barred by a statute of limitations.” 442 This is not a full answer to the problem. First, as proposed in Part III.A above, this Article would expand the Tax Court’s jurisdiction. Under current law, however, the Tax Court does not have deficiency jurisdiction over all types of federal taxes. 443 Second, the taxpayer may not have realized until after expiration of the Tax Court petition period 444 that the adjustments proposed by the IRS are legally questionable. For example, the IRS’s adjustment may have appeared correct initially but was cast into doubt by a decision handed down after the Tax Court petition period lapsed. Or, the adjustment may have been dubious from the start, but the taxpayer received bad advice from her lawyer or accountant, the error of which was discovered only after the petition period ended. Third, the taxpayer may have been unaware that a notice of deficiency had been issued, and thus unaware that the clock had started to run on a Tax Court petition. This is especially possible for poor taxpayers—the very ones least likely to be able to satisfy a full payment prerequisite. One highly regarded director of a low-income taxpayer clinic reported: In my experience, some common reasons why the poor fail to receive the notice [of deficiency] are: First, the poor tend to move frequently, failing to notify either the IRS or the Post Office of address changes—particularly in cases of eviction. Second, they often live in group housing situations where their names are not on the mailbox, so either the Postal Service employees do not deliver the certified notices or another household member picks up the notice but fails to give it to the taxpayer. Third, their mail is often stolen from mailboxes that have their locks perpetually broken. 445
In such situations, the Flora II majority’s “you should have filed a Tax Court petition” rebuke is too harsh. 446 442. Flora II, 362 U.S. at 175. 443. See I.R.C. § 6211(a) (limiting the Tax Court’s deficiency jurisdiction to income, estate, and gift taxes). 444. In general, the Tax Court petition must be filed within ninety days after the IRS issues it. Id. § 6213(a). 445. Smith, supra note 440, at 3 n.7. 446. Congress has already made this value judgment (although only after Flora II was decided). See I.R.C. § 6330(c)(2)(B) (allowing taxpayers to challenge at a CDP hearing “the existence or amount of the underlying tax liability . . . if [she] did not receive any statutory notice of deficiency for such tax liability or did not otherwise have an opportunity to dis-
270
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
Sometimes, taxpayers may have an administrative remedy. For instance, they might be able to challenge the liability via an offer-incompromise based on doubt as to liability under § 7121 or via a CDP hearing under § 6320 and § 6330. However, such remedies will not always be available, often for reasons similar to the reasons why Tax Court review may be an empty remedy. Thus, there is a Primary Value objection against the full payment rule. Are there Second-Order Values of sufficient moment to overcome that objection? I think not. The Flora II majority expressed three policy concerns about a partial payment rule: (1) it could encourage claims splitting, with taxpayers paying part of the liability and bringing a refund action but challenging most of the asserted liability in a Tax Court case; (2) it could shift cases away from the Tax Court and into district court; and (3) it could threaten revenue collection. 447 None of these concerns are substantial. There are psychological and financial barriers to claims splitting. It is nerve-wracking enough for a taxpayer to litigate against the IRS in one case; few would have the appetite to “double their fun.” And, of course, two cases are more expensive to prosecute than one. Were claims to be split, the courts have tools by which to protect themselves. For example, one court can stay its case pending resolution in the other court, then apply a doctrine of preclusion or a “show cause order” to expedite resolution of its case. Finally, if I have underestimated the gravity of the concern, Congress could amend the jurisdictional statutes of the Tax Court or the district courts to prohibit them from hearing matters when substantially related matters already are at issue in other courts. The channeling concern is diminished by this Article. When Flora II was decided, and still today, the Tax Court was and is without general refund jurisdiction. Part III.A above proposes giving the Tax Court such jurisdiction. Were both proposals adopted, a taxpayer in a partial payment world could obtain a desired refund remedy without abandoning the Tax Court for district court. There sometimes would be reasons—perhaps desire for a jury or better precedents—for preferring district court over Tax Court, but one may doubt that this would occur with unacceptable frequency. In any event, Flora II’s channeling goal is a bit dated. The Court endorsed the Tax Court as the preferred tax trial tribunal in Dobson, and Dobson influenced Flora II.448 Congress partially reversed Dobpute such tax liability.”). 447. Flora II, 362 U.S. at 165-66, 176. 448. See Flora v. United States, 246 F.2d 929, 931 (10th Cir. 1957) (quoting Dobson v. Commissioner, 320 U.S. 489, 501-02 (1943)).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
271
son by directing that appellate courts give district court decisions no less deference than they give Tax Court decisions.449 The threat to revenue concern is the weakest of all. A refund suit comes after assessment. Following assessment and notice and demand for payment, the IRS is authorized to employ its full panoply of collection tools, described in Part II.B.6 above. The filing of a refund suit after partial payment would impose no bar to the IRS proceeding with enforced collection of the unpaid portion of the assessment. The IRS might choose to stay such collection in the exercise of its administrative discretion, but one must presume that the IRS would use this discretion in a fashion consistent with its statutory duties. Thus, any adverse Second-Order Values effects of a partial payment rule would be manageable. They do not outweigh the Primary Value benefits of such a rule. Congress should amend the relevant statutes to overturn Flora II. B. Changes Not Proposed Among the core problems of litigation generally are its cost and, derivatively, the prospect of unequal access to justice. These problems do exist as to federal tax litigation. I make no proposals along these lines, however, for two reasons. First, these challenges are far from unique to federal tax litigation. They pervade many kinds of litigation in the United States and elsewhere. Second, and more significantly, strides have been made in addressing the problems. The IRS Appeals Office has been effective in resolving tax controversies informally, inexpensively, and without the need for litigation. The Tax Court’s small case procedures allow taxpayers, often appearing pro se, to resolve cases faster and less expensively. 450 The growth of low-income taxpayer clinics 451 and the existence of the Office of the Taxpayer Advocate 452 have been boons to many. A recent phenomenon has been the institution of suits against Treasury or the IRS based, not on traditional remedies set out in the Internal Revenue Code or related statutes, 453 but upon the general judicial review provisions of the APA. 454 The applicability of the AIA has been and is being tested in such “pure” APA tax suits.
449. I.R.C. § 7482(a). 450. See id. §§ 7436(c), 7463; TAX CT. R. 170-174. 451. Among the useful provisions of the RRA was federal financial support for such clinics. See I.R.C. § 7526. 452. See id. §§ 7803(c), 7811. 453. Such as the provisions governing deficiency, refund, and CDP actions. See supra Parts II.B.1, II.B.3, IV.B. 454. 5 U.S.C. § 706(2) (2012).
272
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
In the Cohen line of cases, 455 for example, taxpayers used the APA to obtain judicial invalidation of an IRS procedure for returning overpayments of telephone excise taxes. The APA was held not to foreclose such suit. 456 Similarly, in Oklahoma v. Sebelius, a case currently pending in district court, Oklahoma is using the APA to challenge regulations under § 36B as to tax credits with respect to medical insurance coverage purchased through federally established exchanges. The government has moved to dismiss, in part on AIA grounds.457 Such “pure” APA tax suits raise potentially troubling questions about their effect on orderly tax administration and their consistency with the purposes behind the AIA. 458 Nonetheless, this Article refrains from offering a specific proposal in this context. There need to be more decided cases before the reality and magnitude of the potential problems can be accurately ascertained and the contours of condign correction can be responsibly proposed. VI. CONCLUSION Unlike Athena, the current federal tax litigation system did not spring full-blown from the brow of Zeus. As we have seen, it developed piecemeal over nearly two centuries, with the pace of change being greatly accelerated by the enactment of the modern federal income tax. The federal tax litigation system has been especially shaped by the Defining Dozen events and trends described above. From them, we can infer the values that drive the system. The most powerful of those goals—the Primary Value—is providing remedies for taxpayers and affected third parties that are fair and effective and are perceived to be fair and effective. In situations in which this imperative does not operate or operates only weakly, a variety of Second-Order
455. To date, there are four decisions in this line: In re Long-Distance Tel. Serv. Fed. Excise Tax Refund Litig. (Cohen I), 539 F. Supp. 2d 281 (D.D.C. 2008), rev’d in part sub nom. Cohen v. United States (Cohen II), 578 F.3d 1 (D.C. Cir. 2009), aff’d in part, Cohen v. United States (Cohen III), 650 F.3d 717 (D.C. Cir. 2011) (en banc), on remand In re LongDistance Tel. Serv. Fed. Excise Tax Refund Litig. (Cohen IV), 853 F. Supp. 2d 138 (D.D.C. 2012) (holding on remand that refund mechanism established by the IRS violated the APA’s notice-and-comment procedure requirements). 456. Cohen II, 578 F.3d at 7-11, aff’d in part, 650 F.3d at 724-27 (D.C. Cir. 2011); see also Swisher v. United States, 2009-2 U.S. Tax Cas. (CCH) ¶ 70,293 (M.D. Pa. 2009). 457. Memorandum in Support of Defendants’ Motion to Dismiss the Amended Complaint at 16-18, Oklahoma v. Sebelius, No. 6:11-cv-00030-RAW (E.D. Okla. Dec. 3, 2012). 458. Not all pure APA tax suits implicate the AIA, at least as the AIA is currently understood. See, e.g., Loving v. IRS, 917 F. Supp. 2d 67 (D.D.C. 2013) (invalidating Treasury regulations as to tax return preparers); Anonymous v. Commissioner, 134 T.C. 13 (2010) (holding that the APA did not prevent the IRS from disclosing a private letter ruling adverse to the taxpayer).
2013]
REFORMING FEDERAL TAX LITIGATION
273
Values govern. These include protecting the revenue, enhancing decisional accuracy, and promoting process efficiency. Based on these criteria, major portions of the current system are sound. However, some features should be altered. In some instances, they were unwise from the start, the result of momentary exuberances that ill serve the system over the longer haul. In other instances, the features reasonably balanced the relevant values at the time of their enactment or promulgation, but the constellation of pertinent considerations has subsequently realigned. Based on the relevant values, this Article has set out an agenda for reform of federal tax litigation. The proposals include expanding the tax jurisdiction of the Tax Court, abolishing the tax jurisdiction of the Court of Federal Claims, continued rejection of a national court of tax appeals, substantially repealing the TEFRA partnership audit and litigation rules, limiting judicial review of CDP determinations, and abolishing the Flora II “full payment” prerequisite to refund suits. The agenda having been defined by this Article, it will be the work of future articles to develop these proposals in greater detail.
274
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:205
WILL THE FEDERAL INCOME TAX HAVE A BICENTENNIAL? * LAWRENCE A. ZELENAK † I. INTRODUCTION.................................................................................................. II. CONSUMPTION TAXES AS INCOME TAXES, ACCORDING TO THE DISSENTING EXPERTS ........................................................................................................... III. THE ELUSIVE ESSENCE OF THE INCOME TAX .................................................... IV. CONCLUSION .....................................................................................................
275 277 278 288
I. INTRODUCTION Will there be a Florida State University Law Review symposium issue in 2113 celebrating (or lamenting) the bicentennial of the federal income tax? In the conventional usage of tax policy wonks, “income” tax has a specific technical meaning. The defining characteristics of an income tax are that it taxes saved income (in addition, of course, to taxing income devoted to current consumption) and that it taxes the investment return on savings. 1 The taxation of saved income distinguishes an income tax from a consumption tax, and the taxation of investment returns distinguishes an income tax from a wage tax. Despite the income tax label, the federal income tax has very significant consumption tax features, including most prominently the exclusion from the tax base of unrealized appreciation and the long-term deferral of tax on most retirement savings. 2 To the extent the income tax really does tax income, it has been under both academic and political assault for the past few decades. On the academic side, as noted by Daniel Shaviro, there are signs of “an emerging new consensus . . . that an ideal consumption tax is unambiguously superior to an ideal income tax, taking into account concerns of both efficiency and distribution.”3 * This Essay is a revised version of a portion of an earlier article. Lawrence A. Zelenak, Foreword: The Fabulous Invalid Nears 100, 73 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. i, vii-xvii (2010). † Pamela B. Gann Professor of Law, Duke University School of Law. 1. The inclusion in the income tax base of savings and of investment returns follows from the standard economist’s definition of a person’s income for a particular period as “the algebraic sum of (1) the market value of rights exercised in consumption and (2) the change in the value of the store of property rights between the beginning and end of the period in question.” HENRY C. SIMONS, PERSONAL INCOME TAXATION 50, 61-62, 206 (1938). 2. I.R.C. §§ 1001 (indicating that gains are taxed only when realized), 219 (providing for deferral of tax on contributions to individual retirement accounts), and 401-20 (providing rules for employer-provided pensions and individual retirement accounts). 3. Daniel Shaviro, Beyond the Pro-Consumption Tax Consensus, 60 STAN. L. REV. 745, 747 (2007). For examples of representative pro-consumption tax scholarship, see EDWARD J. MCCAFFERY, FAIR NOT FLAT: HOW TO MAKE THE TAX SYSTEM BETTER AND SIMPLER (2002) and Joseph Bankman & David A. Weisbach, The Superiority of an Ideal Consumption Tax Over an Ideal Income Tax, 58 STAN. L. REV. 1413 (2006). The emerging
276
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:275
On the political side, the federal income tax has been in the crosshairs of House Republicans for the last twenty or so years. In the mid-1990s, the Chairman of the House Ways and Means Committee repeatedly expressed his desire to “tear the income tax out by its roots and throw it overboard.” 4 In 1998, the Republican-controlled House of Representatives did what it could to grant his wish, voting in favor of a bill to terminate the income tax at the end of 2002 (with the tax to be replaced by some unspecified new federal tax). 5 More recently, one of the two fundamental tax reform proposals offered in 2005 by President George W. Bush’s Advisory Panel on Federal Tax Reform had so many consumption or wage tax features—including immediate expensing of all long-lived business assets and a tremendous expansion of the availability of Roth IRA-type 6 wage tax treatment for savings—that the Panel made a point of not labeling the proposed tax an income tax. 7 The income tax may be in no danger of being replaced by a consumption tax or a wage tax as long as any one of the White House, the Senate, or the House of Representatives is controlled by Democrats. If, however, the survival of the income tax for a second century depends on a Republican monopoly over Congress and the White House never emerging at any point in the next hundred years, the income tax would seem to be in deep trouble. This Essay contends that the long-term survival prospects of the income tax are better than the preceding discussion might suggest— but not because continued taxation of savings and of investment return is anywhere close to assured. Rather, this Essay offers two arguments demonstrating how the conventional wisdom has misunderstood what it is that makes the income tax the income tax. According to these arguments, the income tax could meaningfully be said to have survived even if the current system were replaced by certain forms of taxation that are not income taxes in the standard expert usage.
consensus has certainly not gone unchallenged. Significant challenges include Shaviro, supra, and Chris William Sanchirico, A Critical Look at the Economic Argument for Taxing Only Labor Income, 63 TAX L. REV. 867 (2010). 4. Barbara Kirchheimer, Archer Addresses Contract Compromises and Reform, 66 TAX NOTES 1083, 1083 (1995) (quoting Rep. Bill Archer). 5. Tax Code Termination Act, H.R. 3097, 105th Cong. (2d Sess. 1998). 6. I.R.C. § 408A. 7. THE PRESIDENT’S ADVISORY PANEL ON FED. TAX REFORM, SIMPLE, FAIR, AND PROGROWTH: PROPOSALS TO FIX AMERICA’S TAX SYSTEM 163-64 (Nov. 2005), available at http://www.treasury.gov/resource-center/tax-policy/Documents/Simple-Fair-and-Pro-GrowthProposals-to-Fix-Americas-Tax-System-11-2005.pdf [hereinafter PRESIDENT’S ADVISORY PANEL] (describing the expensing of business assets under the “Growth and Investment Tax Plan”).
2013]
FEDERAL INCOME TAX
277
The first argument points out that there is significant expert dissent from the standard usage, and that according to the dissenters some types of consumption taxes are also properly described as income taxes. The second argument (in my view the more interesting and more important of the two) considers public understandings and intuitions about the essence of the income tax, and concludes that— despite the income tax label—the taxation of saved income and investment returns is rather far down the list of the defining features of the income tax. According to this argument, if enough of the other (and more important) defining features continued to exist after fundamental tax reform had eliminated the taxation of saved income and investment returns, then the income tax would have survived. II. CONSUMPTION TAXES AS INCOME TAXES, ACCORDING TO THE DISSENTING EXPERTS There is less-than-total agreement among experts concerning tax base terminology; some experts apply the income tax label to tax bases that would be considered consumption tax bases under conventional usage. A little more than a century ago, the prominent economist Irving Fisher argued that income should be defined as consumption.8 Henry Simons strongly objected to Fisher’s terminology, 9 but some later experts have followed Fisher’s lead. Consider, for example, the title of William D. Andrew’s seminal 1974 article extolling the merits of a cash-flow consumption tax, which would be administered in a manner similar to the income tax, but under which all savings would be deductible (and all spending out of savings would be taxable): “A Consumption-Type or Cash Flow Personal Income Tax.”10 Other scholars have also referred to a cash flow tax as a “consumed income tax,” 11 despite the fact that under the standard usage a cash flow tax is a quintessential consumption tax. In fact, this usage can be traced back at least as far as John Stuart Mill, who claimed that “[n]o income tax is really just from which savings are not exempted.” 12 The implication, of course, is that a tax from which savings are exempted can still qualify as an income tax. 8. IRVING FISHER, THE NATURE OF CAPITAL AND INCOME 101-18 (1906). What is usually called income, Fisher referred to as earnings or as earned income. Id. at 332-33. 9. SIMONS, supra note 1, at 98. 10. William D. Andrews, A Consumption-Type or Cash Flow Personal Income Tax, 87 HARV. L. REV. 1113 (1974) (emphasis added). 11. See, e.g., J. Clifton Fleming, Jr., Scoping Out the Uncertain Simplification (Complication?) Effects of VATs, BATs and Consumed Income Taxes, 2 FLA. TAX REV. 390 (1995); George K. Yin, Accommodating the “Low-Income” in a Cash-Flow or Consumed Income Tax World, 2 FLA. TAX. REV. 445 (1995). 12. JOHN STUART MILL, PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY 814 (Sir William Ashley ed., Augustus M. Kelley Publishers 1969) (1848).
278
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:275
The cash flow tax is not the only consumption tax (in standard expert usage) to be described by some experts as an income tax. The flat tax, designed by economists Robert E. Hall and Alvin Rabushka, 13 and formerly championed politically by Steve Forbes 14 and Dick Armey,15 is basically a value-added tax, bifurcated into a business tax and a wage tax. In the standard usage, it is indisputably a kind of consumption tax. According to Hall and Rabushka, however, the flat tax is an income tax. 16 They describe the base of the tax as a “comprehensive definition of income.” 17 Although they also describe the base of the flat tax as consumption, 18 they avoid contradicting themselves by explaining that, in their view, an income base and a consumption base are the same thing. 19 In sum, there is a significant amount of non-standard expert usage under which at least some forms of consumption taxes— especially cash flow taxation and the Hall-Rabushka flat tax—are considered income taxes. Adoption of this non-standard usage would improve considerably the long-term survival chances of the federal income tax, as the income tax would be considered to have survived if the current system were replaced by either a cash flow tax or the flat tax. To be sure, improving the odds of survival of the income tax by adopting an unconventional definition of income is not a very profound move and may even be something of a trick. A more interesting question is whether the basic premise of this approach—the assumption that the survival of the income tax depends on the continued use of income as the tax base—is mistaken. Perhaps the income tax label does not capture the essence of the tax. Perhaps what makes the income tax the income tax is something other than the fact that its base is (in a very imperfect sort of way) income. I consider that possibility in the next part. III. THE ELUSIVE ESSENCE OF THE INCOME TAX I suspect the public, if asked, 20 would identify five defining features of the federal income tax: (1) it is a mass tax, imposed on the 13. ROBERT E. HALL & ALVIN RABUSHKA, THE FLAT TAX (2d ed. 1995). 14. Ernest Tollerson, Bowing Out: Forbes Quits and Offers His Support to Dole, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 15, 1996, at A26 (summarizing the 1996 Forbes presidential campaign). 15. Freedom and Fairness Restoration Act of 1995, H.R. 2060 and S. 1050, 104th Cong. (1st Sess. 1995) (sponsored by Rep. Armey and Sens. Shelby, Craig, and Helms). 16. Robert E. Hall & Alvin Rabushka, The Flat Tax: A Simple, Progressive Consumption Tax, in FRONTIERS OF TAX REFORM 27 (Michael J. Boskin ed., 1996). 17. Id. 18. HALL & RABUSHKA, supra note 13, at 40-41. 19. Id. at 40 (“[I]t is a comprehensive income tax (the base is GDP) with a 100 percent immediate write-off of all business investment at the level of the business enterprise. It is a consumption tax because it removes all investment spending from the tax base.”). 20. There has been extensive public opinion polling on a wide range of tax issues, but
2013]
FEDERAL INCOME TAX
279
bulk of the population; (2) it is imposed directly on individuals as taxpayers (as contrasted with the indirect effects of a retail sales tax or a value-added tax); (3) it is imposed on inflows (receipts) rather than on outflows (expenditures); (4) it features progressive marginal tax rates; and (5) it uses exclusions, deductions, and credits to adjust tax liabilities in response to various aspects of taxpayers’ economic circumstances. Perhaps the public would also include (as the experts would think it should) a sixth feature: (6) its base is income, as distinguished from either wages or consumption. My guess, however, is that the sixth feature is considerably less perspicuous to the public than the first five. Whether or not the tax base includes investment income is of little or no personal significance to most taxpayers because most taxpayers have little or no investment income.21 Similarly, that the tax base includes some saved income is of little or no personal significance to most taxpayers, both because they currently consume the bulk of their earnings and because most of what they do save is excluded from their tax base under either the rules governing qualified employment-based retirement savings or the rules governing individual retirement accounts. 22 If I am right about the public’s sense of the income tax, is the public wrong to attach greater significance to the features that do not appear in the experts’ definition of the income tax than to the experts’ defining feature? The imagined question to the public is about the essence of the income tax—what makes the tax what it is—not about the source of the name of the tax. If the tax happened to be named after its rate structure instead of its base—the “unflat tax” instead of the “income tax”—such a change would have no effect on the essence of the tax. It is not unusual for things to be named after their incidental features rather than their essential features. The fact that the office of the president of the United States is the president’s office is more important than the shape of the office, and yet it is called the Oval Office (and that office is in the White House, the most significant attribute of which is decidedly not its color). Similarly, the income base of the income tax might be no more important— to the best of my knowledge there has never been any polling concerning what features of the income tax are crucial to its identity. The absence of such polling questions is not surprising because the answers to the questions would not reveal whether the respondents supported or opposed those features. 21. On 2006 income tax returns, solidly middle income taxpayers—with adjusted gross incomes in the range of $75,000 to $100,000—reported taxable interest income aggregating only 2.4% of their aggregate salaries and wages, reported ordinary dividends aggregating only 1.8% of salaries and wages, and reported capital gains (including both capital gains distributions and net gains on sales of capital assets) aggregating only 3.0% of salaries and wages. See Justin Bryan, Individual Income Tax Returns, 2006, STAT. OF INCOME BULL., Fall 2008, at 5, 21-23 (calculations based on Table 1). 22. I.R.C. §§ 219 (individual retirement accounts), 401-20 (qualified employmentbased retirement savings).
280
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:275
might even be less important—than the other five defining features, despite being the source of the name. The survival of the core of the current federal tax called the income tax does not depend uniquely on whether there continues to be a federal tax with an income base. Some prominent scholars plausibly claim that the difference between an income base and a consumption base is of only limited significance, because (1) taxpayers can and do avoid income taxation of risky investment returns by making portfolio adjustments in response to the tax, and (2) the unavoidable income taxation of the risk-free rate of return is almost trivial, given how low the risk-free rate of return has been over most of the past century. 23 If those scholars are right, then the income tax base may be the least important of the defining features of the so-called income tax. In short, it would be perfectly reasonable for the public to believe that the taxation of income (as contrasted with the taxation of consumption or wages) is not of the essence of the current federal income tax. Different proposals for substantially modifying or replacing the current federal income tax would result in the survival of different numbers of the six features of the current tax. The table set forth below indicates which features would persist following the adoption of five leading reform proposals. For purposes of the table, the first two features of the current income tax, mass taxation and direct taxation of individuals, are combined into a single feature, mass direct taxation of individuals. This is because any plausible replacement for the income tax would have to involve mass taxation; the interesting question is whether that mass taxation would be direct (as with the current income tax) or indirect (as with a retail sales tax or valueadded tax (VAT)). The five proposals considered are (1) Michael Graetz’s proposal to introduce a federal VAT, retaining the income tax only for those taxpayers with six-figure incomes;24 (2) the “Growth and Investment Tax Plan” (GITP), featuring immediate deductions for the cost of all longlived business assets, proposed in 2005 by the President’s Advisory Panel on Federal Tax Reform; 25 (3) The “flat tax” proposed by Robert E. Hall and Alvin Rabushka, which would have two components: (a) a 23. See, e.g., David A. Weisbach, The (Non)Taxation of Risk, 58 TAX L. REV. 1 (2004). But see Lawrence Zelenak, The Sometimes-Taxation of the Returns to Risk-Bearing Under a Progressive Income Tax, 59 SMU L. REV. 879, 889-90 (2006) (suggesting that the historically low inflation-adjusted risk-free rates of return may not be a good indication of real riskfree rates of return in the future). 24. Michael J. Graetz, 100 Million Unnecessary Returns: A Fresh Start for the U.S. Tax System, 112 YALE L.J. 261, 282 (2002). 25. PRESIDENT’S ADVISORY PANEL, supra note 7, at 163-64 (describing the treatment of the cost of long-lived business assets under the GITP).
2013]
281
FEDERAL INCOME TAX
flat-rate business tax imposed on a base identical to the base of a VAT, except that a deduction for salaries and wages paid would be allowed, and (b) a tax imposed on individuals, at the same flat rate, on salaries and wages in excess of a rather high exemption level;26 (4) a federal retail sales tax (or VAT) introduced as a complete replacement for the federal income tax; 27 and (5) a cash flow consumption tax with progressive marginal tax rates, resembling the current income tax except that (a) all savings would be deductible and (b) all consumption spending would be taxable (including spending financed by savings and spending financed by borrowing). 28
Proposal
Mass Taxation of direct inflows taxation rather than of outflows? individuals?
Progressive marginal rates?
Significant use of exclusions, deductions, and credits?
Tax imposed on saved income and investment returns?
Number of retained features of current income tax
(1) VAT-pluselite income tax
no
no 29
yes 30
no 31
yes 32
2
(2) GITP
yes
yes
yes
yes
no 33
4
26. See HALL & RABUSHKA, supra note 13, at 55-64. 27. See generally NEAL BOORTZ & JOHN LINDER, THE FAIRTAX BOOK: SAYING GOODBYE TO THE INCOME TAX AND THE IRS (2005) (arguing that the federal income tax should be replaced by a federal retail sales tax). 28. See, e.g., MCCAFFERY, supra note 3. Edward McCaffery has been the leading academic advocate of such a system. Id. 29. The elite income tax would continue to tax inflows, but for most people the relevant tax would be the outflow-taxing VAT. 30. Graetz proposes a single rate for the income tax imposed on six-figure incomes. Graetz, supra note 24, at 284-86. Viewing the VAT and the elite income tax as an integrated system, however, the combined rate of the VAT and the income tax (applicable to highincome persons) would be higher than the stand-alone rate of the VAT (applicable to lowincome and moderate-income persons). 31. The “no” characterization is debatable. The elite income tax would retain deductions for home mortgage interest, charitable contributions, and medical expenses, and a replacement for the earned income tax credit (EITC) for low-income workers would be introduced into the payroll-tax system. Graetz, supra note 24, at 295-96 (income tax deductions), 290-93 (EITC replacement). However, for the majority of the population neither eligible for the EITC replacement nor subject to the income tax, the “no” characterization would clearly be correct. 32. The “yes” characterization is debatable, because tax would not be imposed on the saved income and investment returns of the majority of the population not subject to the elite income tax. On the other hand, the bulk of saved income and investment returns would belong to the minority of taxpayers subject to the income tax, so the “yes” characterization seems appropriate. 33. Actually, the GITP would retain a sort of residual tax on investment returns—a 15% tax rate applicable to dividends, capital gains, and interest. PRESIDENT’S ADVISORY PANEL, supra note 7, at 152, 159. The panel considered this residual taxation insufficient to justify describing the GITP as an income tax, id., and that judgment seems reasonable.
282
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
Proposal
(3) The flat tax (4) Sales tax (or VAT)
Mass Taxation of direct inflows taxation of rather than individuals? outflows?
[Vol. 41:275
Progressive marginal rates?
Significant use of exclusions, deductions, and credits?
Tax imposed on saved income and investment returns?
Number of retained features of current income tax
yes
yes
no 34
no 35
no
2
no
no
no 36
no
no
0
yes
yes
yes
yes
no 37
4
(5) Progressive cash flow tax
As indicated in the right-hand column of the table, two of the proposals that would be considered non-income tax proposals under the standard usage of tax experts—the GITP and the progressive cash flow tax—retain four of the five defining features of the current income tax. A proposal that would be considered an income tax proposal under standard expert usage—the VAT-plus-elite-income-tax— retains only two of the five defining features. Of course, a glance at the numbers in the right-hand column is not sufficient to determine whether the current federal income tax would persist in essence, even if not in name, if a particular reform proposal were adopted. It would not necessarily be right to conclude that the essence of the current tax system survives when the replacement system retains at least three of the five defining features of the current system and that the essence does not survive when the replacement 34. Although the flat tax as proposed by Hall and Rabushka has only one positive tax rate, HALL & RABUSHKA, supra note 13, the exemption allowance under the wage tax portion of the flat tax functions as a zero bracket. Thus, the tax can be understood as really featuring two tax brackets—a zero-rate bracket and a positive-rate bracket. In addition, the structure of the wage-tax portion is readily adaptable to the introduction of any number of progressive marginal rates, if Congress should so desire. See David F. Bradford, What are Consumption Taxes and Who Pays Them?, 39 TAX NOTES 383, 384-86 (1988) (describing the “X tax” under which progressive marginal rates would apply to the wage-tax portion of the flat tax). 35. Although the flat tax as proposed by Hall and Rabushka does not allow any deductions (other than the personal allowances designed to shelter subsistence-level income from the wage tax), HALL & RABUSHKA, supra note 13, there would be no technical difficulty in introducing exclusions, deductions, and credits into the wage-tax portion of the flat tax. 36. The Boortz and Linder sales tax proposal features a “prebate”—a universal refund of the sales tax on subsistence consumption—which mimics the effect of a tax with a zero rate on subsistence consumption and a single positive rate on above-subsistence consumption. BOORTZ & LINDER, supra note 27, at 81-90. 37. McCaffery explains that a progressive cash flow tax will impose a burden on the returns to saving of a taxpayer who saves in a low-consumption year to finance a high level of consumption in a later year. Edward J. McCaffery, A New Understanding of Tax, 103 MICH. L. REV. 807, 814-15 (2005).
2013]
FEDERAL INCOME TAX
283
system retains two or fewer of those features. Mere counting is inadequate both because it is not clear that all features are equally significant 38 and because in many cases it is debatable whether a replacement should or should not be characterized as retaining a particular feature (a problem suggested by the footnotes to nine of the twentyfive yes-or-no answers in the table). The question of whether the income tax should be considered to have survived the enactment of these various proposals finds an analogue in Derek Parfit’s analysis of the survival (or not) of personal identity over time. 39 For Parfit, continued personal identity is a matter of two things.40 The first is direct psychological connectedness of memory and of other psychological features, such as intention, belief, and desire. 41 There is a direct memory connection (for example) between Z today and X of twenty years ago if Z can remember having had some of X’s experiences. Parfit emphasizes that “[c]onnectedness can hold to any degree.”42 The second element of continued personal identity is psychological continuity—“the holding of overlapping chains of strong connectedness.” 43 Even if Z remembered none of X’s experiences (so that there was no memory connectedness between Z and X), there would be memory continuity if Y of ten years ago remembered many of X’s experiences, and Z today remembers many of Y’s experiences. Because direct connectedness diminishes over time,44 personal identity also weakens over time. Parfit argues that in some cases of significant reduction in direct connectedness identity is not determinate. In such a case, “it would be an empty question whether the resulting person would be me.” 45 Similarly, although we can confidently conclude that the income tax survives when Congress tinkers 38. As shown in the table, the flat tax has only two of five income-tax-like features. Although the presence of only two features suggests the flat tax is not an income tax, that conclusion is not inevitable if one puts considerable weight on those features, or on some feature not included in the table. Former Ways and Means Committee Chairman Bill Archer wanted to replace the income tax with a federal retail sales tax or VAT. Clay Chandler, Archer Calls for End to Income-Based Tax; Lawmaker Wants Levy Tied to Consumption, WASH. POST, June 6, 1995, at D1. Archer’s opposition to income taxation extended to the Hall-Rabushka flat tax because he viewed it as a type of income tax: “In my common sense, if your wages are going to be taxed before you get them, that’s an income tax.” Jacqueline Rieschick, March Madness Spurs Trash Talk on Tax Reform, 78 TAX NOTES 1209, 1210 (1998) (quoting Rep. Bill Archer). Archer’s remark suggests that, for him, withholding at the source was the essence of income taxation. 39. DEREK PARFIT, REASONS AND PERSONS 199-347 (1984). For a more detailed summary of Parfit’s analysis (on which this paragraph is based), see Lawrence Zelenak, Tax Policy and Personal Identity Over Time, 62 TAX L. REV. 333, 338-43 (2009). 40. PARFIT, supra note 39, at 205-07, 262. 41. Id. 42. Id. at 206. 43. Id. 44. See id. at 276-77, 306. 45. Id. at 239.
284
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:275
with the tax rate schedules, and that it would not survive if replaced by a retail sales tax, there may be no real answer to the question of whether it would survive in some of the intermediate cases. Subject to all of these qualifications and caveats, however, it would be at least plausible to conclude both (1) that the essence of the current federal income tax would survive the adoption of either the GITP or a progressive cash flow tax (despite the loss of the experts’ income tax label in both cases), and (2) that the essence of the current federal income tax would not survive the adoption of the VAT-plus-elite income tax (despite the survival of a tax with an income base). If one accepts the multi-feature account of the essence of the current federal income tax system (despite its undeniable lack of precision), how would one evaluate the system’s long-term prospects? Crystal ball gazing a century into the future may be a hopeless exercise. Who, in 1913, could have predicted the events—from the Great Depression, to World War II and the Cold War, to the Reagan Revolution—that shaped the development of the income tax in its first century? And who has any idea today what the United States will be like in 2113? (How much of it, for example, will be under water?) Less ambitiously, however, it may be possible to make meaningful prognostications over the next decade or two. The survival of the income tax over that shorter time frame is likely under the multi-feature approach to defining survival. By contrast, the survival of the income tax would be very doubtful under an approach focused exclusively on the propriety (according to the usual terminology of experts) of the continued use of the income tax label. Income as a tax base may be in serious trouble over the next few decades. The George W. Bush Administration repeatedly proposed “Retirement Savings Accounts” (RSAs) and “Lifetime Savings Accounts” (LSAs) that would have greatly expanded the availability of wage tax treatment for savings. 46 The long-term strategy seemed to be a sort of slouching away from an income tax base, culminating in a tax system with too little remaining taxation of investment income to be fairly described as an income tax. Although the Bush Administration did not achieve this goal, and the Obama Administration has shown no interest in pursuing it, it is easy to imagine future administrations 46. See, e.g., Patti Mohr, White House Begins Selling Its Tax Cut to Congress, 98 TAX NOTES 631, 633-34 (2003); U.S. DEP’T OF THE TREASURY, GENERAL EXPLANATIONS OF THE ADMINISTRATION’S FISCAL YEAR 2007 REVENUE PROPOSALS 5-10 (2006), available at http://www.treasury.gov/resource-center/tax-policy/Documents/General-ExplanationsFY2007.pdf. Contributions to RSAs and LSAs would not have been deductible, but the investment returns would have been permanently tax-exempt. The Bush Administration’s RSA and LSA proposals were the inspiration for the “Save for Retirement” and “Save for Family” account proposals of the President’s Tax Reform Panel. PRESIDENT’S ADVISORY PANEL, supra note 7, at 119-21, 159.
2013]
FEDERAL INCOME TAX
285
and Congresses—particularly Republican ones—reviving RSA and LSA proposals and perhaps prevailing. A tax reward for thrifty savers has obvious political appeal, and the incrementalism of the approach is more likely to succeed than any attempt to eliminate all vestiges of an income tax base in one fell swoop. And although there may be only an attenuated connection in the tax arena between intellectual movements and political outcomes, it is also noteworthy (as mentioned earlier) that income as a tax base has lost much of its support among tax policy experts in the past few decades. 47 All things considered, then, the long-term survival chances for income as the tax base are not particularly good. By contrast, the long-term survival chances for the other defining features of the current income tax—mass direct taxation of individuals; taxation of inflows rather than outflows; significant use of exclusions, deductions, and credits; and a modestly progressive marginal tax rate structure—seem quite good. As Michael Graetz has wryly observed, in recent years Congress ha[s] used the income tax the way [his] mother employed chicken soup: as a magic elixir to solve all the nation’s economic and social difficulties. If the nation has a problem in access to education, child care affordability, health insurance coverage, or the financing of long-term care, an income tax deduction or credit is the answer. 48
As Graetz explains, the attraction is bipartisan; Republicans like almost any tax cut, and Democrats realize their favorite spending programs are more politically viable as tax expenditures than as direct expenditures.49 Moreover, members of the House Ways and Means and Senate Finance Committees can increase their campaign contributions by sending the message that they are always open to the enactment of new tax subsidies. 50 And the administrative costs of delivering subsidies through the income tax are generally much lower than the administrative costs of delivering nontax subsidies. 51 In short, Congress seems hopelessly addicted to the extensive use of exclusions, deductions, and credits in lieu of direct spending pro47. See supra note 3 and accompanying text. 48. Graetz, supra note 24, at 274. 49. Id. at 275. 50. Milton Friedman, Remarks at the Sixth Meeting of the President’s Advisory Panel on Federal Tax Reform 117-18 (Mar. 31, 2005); Richard L. Doernberg & Fred S. McChesney, On the Accelerating Rate and Decreasing Durability of Tax Reform, 71 MINN. L. REV. 913, 914 (1987). 51. See, e.g., Janet Holtzblatt, Choosing Between Refundable Tax Credits and Spending Programs, 93 PROC. ANN. CONF. ON TAX’N 116, 122 (2001) (comparing the substantial direct administrative costs of the food stamp program with the minimal direct administrative costs of the earned income tax credit).
286
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:275
grams—and thus also addicted to the existence of mass direct taxation of individuals’ inflows as the vehicle for the delivery of subsidies. By now, the addiction seems so strong that even if (in some alternate universe) there were no need for a revenue-producing direct mass tax, Congress might opt for a zero-revenue direct mass “tax” solely for its usefulness as a vehicle for delivering subsidies. There might never have been a direct mass tax, 52 but once such a tax was enacted and Congress discovered the joys of tax expenditures, the elimination of direct mass taxation became very unlikely. The survival of progressive marginal rates does not seem quite as assured as the survival of tax expenditures and the direct mass taxation of inflows. The intellectual foundation of progressive marginal tax rates has been undermined by optimal-tax analysis. The objective of optimal-tax analysis 53 is to determine what marginal tax rate structure, in combination with a system of universal cash transfers, will maximize a chosen social welfare function (SWF) 54 under various assumed conditions (relating to the distribution of wage-earning abilities in society, the elasticity of the labor supply, and the rate at which the marginal utility of money declines). Different optimal-tax simulations, based on different factual assumptions and using different SWFs, can produce very different levels of transfer payments and very different levels of taxation. However, as a leading optimal-tax scholar has explained, “One of the main conclusions to be drawn from the Mirrleesian optimal non-linear income tax model is that it is difficult (if at all possible) to find a convincing argument for a progressive marginal tax rate structure throughout” the societal wage distribution. 55 As in the case of the shift in expert opinion concerning the 52. See Lawrence A. Zelenak, The Federal Retail Sales Tax that Wasn’t: An Actual History and an Alternate History, 73 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 149 (2010) (describing how during World War II Congress might have chosen a federal retail sales tax—rather than an expansion of the income tax—as the tool of mass taxation, but for the Roosevelt Administration’s unwavering opposition to a sales tax). 53. See, e.g., MATTI TUOMALA, OPTIMAL INCOME TAX AND REDISTRIBUTION (1990) (a comprehensive monograph on optimal income taxation); J.A. Mirrlees, An Exploration in the Theory of Optimum Income Taxation, 38 REV. ECON. STUD. 175 (1971) (the seminal work in the field); Lawrence Zelenak & Kemper Moreland, Can the Graduated Income Tax Survive Optimal Tax Analysis?, 53 TAX L. REV. 51 (1999) (including a nontechnical introduction to optimal income tax analysis). 54. An SWF specifies how the well-being of individuals contributes to the overall wellbeing of society. A simple utilitarian SWF, for example, values equally the well-being of each member of society. At the other extreme, a maximin social welfare function (commonly associated with the political philosophy of John Rawls) is concerned solely with the wellbeing of the least well-off members of society. JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 75-83, 152-56 (1971). 55. TUOMALA, supra note 53, at 14. For a wide range of factual assumptions and SWFs, optimal tax rate structures feature rising marginal rates through the bottom decile of the wage distribution and falling marginal tax rates through the remaining nine deciles. Id. at 95-99. But see Zelenak & Moreland, supra note 53, at 62-71 (demonstrating that optimal tax analysis does support progressive marginal tax rates in the absence of univer-
2013]
FEDERAL INCOME TAX
287
relative merits of income taxation and consumption taxation, it is difficult to predict how much, if at all, a change in academic views will influence political outcomes. Public attitudes toward progressive marginal rates are probably more important politically than the views of academics. In this regard it is noteworthy that Robert E. Hall and Alvin Rabushka, the developers of the particular consumption-tax proposal known as the flat tax, were sufficiently persuaded of the political attractiveness of a single (“flat”) rate that they named their tax after its rate structure, rather than following the nearly universal approach of naming taxes after their bases. 56 On the other hand, opinion polling indicates considerable public support for progressive tax rates, 57 and in the almost three decades since the flat tax was originally proposed 58 neither the Hall-Rabushka tax nor any other single-rate tax has even come close to enactment as a replacement for the current federal income tax. The George W. Bush Administration, for example, demonstrated no interest in eliminating progressive marginal tax rates, in marked contrast with its strong interest in moving toward a consumptiontax base.59 Moreover, it is debatable whether the Hall-Rabushka proposal and other proposals for taxes with a single positive rate are accurately described as flat-rate tax proposals. In fact, the wage-tax portion of the Hall-Rabushka proposal (like most other so-called single-rate proposals) actually features two tax rates: a zero rate on subsistencelevel wages produced by “a generous personal allowance” in the wage tax, and one positive rate imposed on above-subsistence wages. 60 Hall and Rabushka do not think this prevents their tax from being flat. In this respect they are intellectual heirs of Walter Blum and Harry Kalven, who argued that a tax applying a single positive rate above an exemption level was different in kind, rather than merely in degree, from a tax with multiple positive rates—so much so that they sal cash transfers and arguing that universal cash transfers are politically unrealistic in the United States). 56. See HALL & RABUSHKA, supra note 13. 57. See KARLYN BOWMAN & ANDREW RUGG, AM. ENTER. INST., PUBLIC OPINION ON TAXES: 1937 TO TODAY 34 (2012) (reporting results of a 1981 Harris poll in which a majority of respondents found it was “fair” that “higher-income people not only have to pay more in taxes but must pay a greater percentage of their income in taxes,” and of a 2005 AP/Ipsos poll in which a majority of respondents thought that those “who earn more money should pay a higher tax rate on their incomes than people who earn less”). 58. HALL & RABUSHKA, supra note 13 (first edition published in 1985). 59. The Executive Order creating the President’s Advisory Panel on Federal Tax Reform instructed the Panel that its proposals should be “appropriately progressive.” Exec. Order No. 13,369, 70 Fed. Reg. 2323 (Jan. 7, 2005). By contrast, the order indicated the Panel could offer one or more non-income tax proposals, as long as it offered “[a]t least one option . . . us[ing] the Federal income tax as the base for its recommended reforms.” Id. 60. HALL & RABUSHKA, supra note 13, at 53-54.
288
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:275
gave the single-positive-rate tax its own adjective, “degressive.” 61 Despite the protestations of Hall, Rabushka, Blum, and Kalven, a tax featuring a single positive rate above an exemption level has both of the features essential to a progressive marginal tax rate structure: the existence of more than one tax rate, and the application of the higher rate(s) to higher levels of income. A forecast limited to the next few decades might predict that (1) the survival of progressive marginal tax rates in the narrower sense of the term—requiring the existence of at least two positive rates of tax—is probable, and (2) the survival of progressive marginal tax rates in the broader sense of the term—as including the “degressive” rate structures of Blum and Kalven—is nearly certain. IV. CONCLUSION Summing up the life expectancies of the major features of the existing income tax: Although the income tax base is in considerable peril, three of the other features—mass direct taxation of individuals, taxation of inflows rather than outflows, and the continued availability of an array of exclusions, directions, and credits—are almost certain to survive for decades, and the final feature—progressive marginal rates—is more likely than not to survive. If the income tax base disappears, but three or four of the remaining features persist, would the resulting tax still be the income tax? Reasonable minds can differ on the answer to that question. There is much to be said, however, in favor of a “yes” answer. The survival of an income base, as contrasted with a consumption base or a wage base, may not be necessary to the survival of the core of the current federal income tax. There is no objective way of determining something as amorphous as the essence of a tax system, so there is no reason to expect a consensus as to whether the essence of the income tax would have survived in various possible futures. The argument offered here is negative at its core—not in favor of any particular view of the essence of the current federal income tax, but against the assumption that the “income tax” label captures the essence of the tax. My focus is on the survival of essential features, not of labels; but it would not be surprising if the income tax label, as well as the income tax essence, survived the decline and fall of the income tax base. Suppose that over the next few decades Congress gradually slouched away from an income tax base, eventually arriving at a point at which the tax base could no longer be fairly described as income (at least according to standard expert usage), but without disturbing the other key features of the current system. It would be rea61. Walter J. Blum & Harry Kalven, Jr., The Uneasy Case for Progressive Taxation, 19 U. CHI. L. REV. 417, 506-16 (1952).
2013]
FEDERAL INCOME TAX
289
sonable to conclude that the core of the current tax system had survived, even if tax experts would say the tax was no longer an income tax. It also seems likely that the income tax label would survive the gradual dismantling of the income tax base. A cynic might attribute the survival of the income tax label to the boiling frog effect—just as urban legend claims that a frog will allow itself to be boiled to death as long as the water temperature is raised gradually, 62 perhaps the income tax label can endure as long as the income tax base is gradually eroded. But the label might also survive for a better reason. The income tax label may come to be understood nonliterally as a shorthand reference to the several key features of the current tax system, rather than as a literal description of the base of the tax. There are instances of things being named after nonessential features, losing those nonessential features, and retaining their names—think of the nongreen greenrooms of television fame 63 or (for tax aficionados) the nonblue bluebooks produced by the Staff of the Joint Committee on Taxation.64 Perhaps the income tax is destined to become another example of that phenomenon.
62. See, e.g., Paul Krugman, Boiling the Frog, N.Y. TIMES, July 13, 2009, at A19 (“Real frogs will, in fact, jump out of the pot—but never mind. The hypothetical boiled frog is a useful metaphor . . . .”). 63. See William Safire, The Greenroom Effect, N.Y. TIMES, Apr. 23, 1989, at SM16 (explaining that the use of the term in the theater predates the advent of television by several centuries, that the term may or may not have been based on the wall color of early greenrooms (the origins of the term are lost in the mists of time), and that the term is routinely used today even when nothing in a particular greenroom is actually green). 64. Bluebooks are prepared by the Staff of the Joint Committee on Taxation to describe recently enacted tax legislation. See, e.g., STAFF OF JOINT COMM. ON TAXATION, 111TH CONG., GENERAL EXPLANATION OF TAX LEGISLATION ENACTED IN THE 110TH CONGRESS (Comm. Print 2009). Their covers are frequently gray, but that does not affect their status as bluebooks.
290
FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 41:275
View more...
Comments